Skip to main content
Log in

Wallace’s and Darwin’s natural selection theories

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This work takes a stand on whether Wallace should be regarded as co-author of the theory of natural selection alongside Darwin as he is usually considered on behalf of his alleged essential contribution to the conception of the theory. It does so from a perspective unexplored thus far: we will argue for Darwin’s priority based on a rational reconstruction of the theory of natural selection (following a hierarchical perspective for scientific theories, we present its conceptual framework together with its fundamental and special laws) as it appears in the writings of both authors. We show that the theory does not appear in exactly the same manner in the writings of each of its alleged co-discoverers: tough we find the same fundamental elements in both works, even in Darwin’s early texts, we discern a more complex unifying and ramified structure than the one we find in Wallace’s Ternate manuscript. Even when we think the badge of the “Darwin–Wallace” theory is well deserved, the unifying force of Darwin’s version has proved to be one of the keys for the ulterior success of the so-called Darwinian revolution in Biology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Adapted from (Ginnobili 2010, 2016)

Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Remarkably, Wallace did not use the expression “natural selection”. See note 14 on his opinion regarding the use of this nomenclature.

  2. In Wallace’s own words (Wallace 1908, pp. 5–7):

    Since the death of Darwin in 1882, I have found myself in the somewhat unusual position of receiving credit and praise from popular writers under a complete misapprehension of what my share in Darwin’s work really amounted to. It has been stated (not unfrequently) in the daily and weekly press, that Darwin and myself discovered “natural selection” simultaneously, while a more daring few have declared that I was the first to discover it, and that I gave way to Darwin! [...] He [Darwin] would have been at once recognised, and should be ever recognised, as the sole and undisputed discoverer and patient investigator of the great law of “Natural Selection” in all its far-reaching consequences.

  3. Despite subsequent debates [see the well documented work of Malcolm Kottler on this (Kottler 1985)], both Darwin and Wallace stressed the similarities when discussing originality. In 1858, and after receiving Wallace’s Ternate paper, Darwin wrote two famous letters to his close friend Charles Lyell, expressing desperate worries regarding priority. In the first one (dated June \(18{\mathrm{th}}\)) he wrote: “I never saw a more striking coincidence [between his ideas and Wallace’s]. If Wallace had my M.S. sketch written out in 1842 he could not have made a better short abstract! Even his terms now stand as Heads of my Chapters.” (Burkhardt and Smith 1992, p. 107) In the second letter (dated June \(25{\mathrm{th}}\)) he wrote that “there is nothing in Wallace’s sketch which is not written out much fuller in my sketch copied in 1844” (Burkhardt and Smith 1992, p. 117). Several years later, on May \(14{\mathrm{th}}\), 1864, Hooker called Darwin’s attention to a recent writing of Wallace’s (Wallace 1864) in which the latter did not claim any authorship whatsoever in the theory –he uses there expressions such as “Mr. Darwin’s celebrated theory of natural selection”, and “the theory promulgated by Mr. Darwin”. This perplexed Hooker who said “I am struck [...] with his negation of all credit or share in the Natural Selection theory” (Hooker 1864). Darwin’s reaction was to write to Wallace and admonish him thus: “You ought not [...] speak of the theory as mine; it is just as much yours as mine.” (Burkhardt 2001, p. 216)

  4. Endler is not alone in this. Many other authors claim that fitness can be determined independently of survival (Ginnobili 2010, 2016; Gould 1976; Kutschera 2003, p. 354; Lerner 1959; Naylor and Handford 1985; Wassermann 1978). On the other hand, Lennox and Wilson think that, for Darwin, the struggle for existence is necessary for natural selection to occur (Lennox and Wilson 1994).

  5. The same idea can be found in other authors. For example, Castrodeza (1988, pp. 182–183), Bateman (1948), Mayr (1972), Ghiselin (1969, p. 242), Gruber (1974, pp. 87–88), Thornhill and Alcock (1983), Spencer and Masters (1992), Dobzhansky et al. (1977, p. 118), Ayala (1995, pp. 80–82) and especially Ghiselin (1997), p. 226.

  6. Darwin himself told Lyell (in his letter of June \(18{\mathrm{th}}\), 1858) that “all the labour” in his Book “consists in the application of the theory” (Burkhardt and Smith 1992, p. 107). As a matter of fact, one of us performed just this task by going through every kind of practical application of the theory that we can find in OS, identifying both what they all share and their differences (Ginnobili 2010, 2012, 2016).

  7. To conceiving sexual selection as a form of natural selection may be considered controversial. If natural selection is confined to what relates to survival, it is clear that sexual selection then constitutes a different construct. In fact, it could be argued that sometimes Darwin himself seemed to regard them as different for that very reason. See, for instance, this statement from the 1842 text:

    Besides selection by death, in bisexual animals \(\langle \hbox {illegible}\rangle \) the selection in time of fullest vigour, namely struggle of males; even in animals which pair there seems a surplus \(\langle ? \rangle \) and a battle, possibly as in man more males produced than females, struggle of war or charms. Hence that male which at that time is in fullest vigour, or best armed with arms or ornaments of its species, will gain in hundreds of generations some small advantage and transmit such characters to its offspring. (Darwin 1909a, p. 10)

    In OS this opposition is still more explicit:

    [Sexual Selection] depends, not on a struggle for existence, but on a struggle between the males for possession of the females; the result is not death to the unsuccessful competitor, but few or no offspring. Sexual selection is, therefore, less rigorous than natural selection. (Darwin 1859, p. 88, our emphasis)

    In these terms, sexual selection will have applications that exclude those of natural selection. On the other hand, and this is crucial, putting these discussions aside, it is enough for our purposes that the use of the same concepts be recognized in all the proposals we review here. This clue will enable us to see unity in the diversity of theories, as Endler and Tuomi did. Our treatment will be justified, we hope, later on in this section.

  8. We insist: the connection between the trait that is adequate for the environment and success in differential reproduction may be due to different reasons: either an improvement in survival, or an improvement in mating, or an improvement in the ability to attract pollinators, etc., all of which may, in turn, be due to different causes.

  9. This terminological choice may be strange for the reader. It is a predicament hard to overcome. We either choose terms are not typically used to talk about natural selection, which makes the text harder to read; or, rather, we opt for terms that are more familiar and run the risk of being misinterpreted or of upsetting those who use these terms in a different way. This is a consequence of the fact that in this discussion the number of concepts involved outruns the number of terms to express them.

  10. Note that the theory of artificial selection can also be thought of as different from that of natural selection restricted to survival. This is hinted at in several passages from Darwin himself in later editions of OS (Darwin 1872, pp. 39, 80–81, 137–138), and from many commentators that follow him on this when they present these theories as being in competition (Beer 2001, p. 166; Karlin and Carmelli 1975; Minvielle 1981; Nicholas and Robertson 1980; Secord 1981) and deserving separate treatment. Even though the relationship between artificial selection and natural selection is undoubtedly debatable, here we assume the position that artificial selection can be judged as a case of natural selection (Álvarez 2010; Brandon 1978, 1990, p. 13, Gayon 1998, pp. 54–59; Campbell 1984, pp. 149–152; Richards 2014; Wilner 2006; Ginnobili 2011; among others). For our purposes, it is sufficient to know that that relationship has been discussed in Darwin’s version of the theory, and that it is absent in Wallace’s version because he explicitly denied that possibility (at least in the treated works).

  11. We thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out to us.

  12. Gray is one the few people we are aware of that had come to know Darwin’s transmutationist ideas before 1858 directly from Darwin’s own mouth or pen. Others were, chronologically, Joseph Hooker; Leonard Jenyns; Charles Lyell; William Fox; George Thwaites; Samuel Woodward; and James Dana (see Costa 2013, p. 229; Kottler 1985; Porter 1993). On the other hand, Darwin personally explained in detail the theory of natural selection to Lyell, Hooker and Thomas Huxley.

  13. In a letter to Lyell, Darwin himself wrote that Wallace and him “differ only that I [Darwin] was led to my views from what artificial selection has done for domestic animals” (Burkhardt and Smith 1992, p. 117).

  14. Let us remember that for this reason Wallace urges Darwin to substitute the expression “natural selection” for “survival of the fittest”. Darwin ended up following his colleague’s advice. In the fifth edition of OS he wrote:

    I have called this principle, by which each slight variation, if useful, is preserved, by the term Natural Selection, in order to mark its relation to man’s power of selection. But the expression often used by Mr. Herbert Spencer of the Survival of the Fittest is more accurate, and is sometimes equally convenient. (Darwin 1869, p. 72)

    Wallace’s proposal was delivered (once again) by correspondence, in a letter dated July \(2{\mathrm{nd}}\) 1866. As Darwin admits, Herbert Spencer (1820–1903) coined the expression, more specifically, in his The Principles of Biology of 1864 (Spencer 1864). Darwin adopted the Spencerian language in this fifth edition of OS and in the sixth one. However, he never dropped “natural selection” altogether, but preserved it, using both expressions interchangeably up to the end (Darwin 1872, pp. 80, 102, 134–135, 180, 471) (Adopting this terminology is inadequate for multiple reasons. To mention an oft-quoted one, it was precisely this formulation that drove many authors to (wrongly) declare the theory to be unfalsifiable on account of circularity.)

  15. It is well known that in later writings Wallace advocated for teleological versions of evolution, specifically for the appearance of humans (Carmo and Martins 2006; Fichman 2001; Levit and Polatayko 2013; Wallace 1869a, 1903, 1910, 1913), a topic that exceeds our present purposes.

  16. Cf. (Kutschera 2003), where we can find this and other interesting differences between Darwin’s and Wallace’s theoretical proposals. On account of our approach, we only pick up two: the difference in how they treat natural selection and Wallace’s omission of sexual selection, about which we will speak later in this section.

  17. Note what Darwin claims at the beginning of his longer work The Variation of Animals and Plants under Domestication:

    No doubt man selects varying individuals, sows their seeds, and again selects their varying offspring. [...] Man, therefore, may be said to have been trying an experiment on a gigantic scale; and it is an experiment which nature during the long lapse of time has incessantly tried. Hence, it follows that the principles of domestication are important for us. (Darwin 1868, vol. 1, p. 3; cf. Wilner 2006)

    Just as breeders intervene positively selecting those traits which will be useful for their ends and they are interested in preserving, thereby creating in relatively few generations products that satisfy their practical or aesthetic agenda, in an analogous manner nature “chooses”, unintentionally but not randomly, “creating” and preserving new varieties for different reasons (Darwin 1859, Chapters 1–2). Again, Darwin attributes a greater creative power to the selective force of nature than he does to artificial selection.

  18. Note that camouflage can be useful to survival both for escaping predators—what Wallace wrote about—and food supply—what Wallace omitted—(cf. Díez and Lorenzano 2013, 2015).

  19. So extraordinary that it can hardly be attributed to chance. Perhaps a historiographical analysis of their interaction before 1858 could shed light to an explanation (see Kottler 1985). Notwithstanding this, we should remember that these coincidences surprised Darwin himself (cf. note 3).

References

  • Álvarez, J. R. (2010). La selección natural: lenguaje, método y filosofía. Endoxa, 24, 91–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayala, F. J. (1995). Origen y Evolución del Hombre. Madrid: Alianza Editorial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balzer, W., Moulines, C. U., & Sneed, J. D. (1987). An architectonic for science: The structuralist program. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbadilla, A. (1990). La estructura de la teoría de la selección natural. In A. Ruiz & M. Santos (Eds.), Temas Actuales de Biología Evolutiva. Barcelona: UAB.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, P. H., Gautrey, P. J., Herbert, S., Kohn, D., & Smith, S. (Eds.). (1987). Charles Darwin’s notebooks. New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateman, A. J. (1948). Intra-sexual selection in Drosophila. Heredity, 2(3), 349–368.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beddall, B. G. (1968). Wallace, Darwin, and the theory of natural selection: A study in the development of ideas and attitudes. Journal of the History of Biology, 1(2), 261–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beddall, B. G. (1972). Wallace, Darwin, and Edward Blyth: Further notes on the development of evolution theory. Journal of the History of Biology, 5(1), 153–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beddall, B. G. (1973). Notes for Mr. Darwin: Letters to Charles Darwin from Edward Blyth at Calcutta: A study in the process of discovery. Journal of the History of Biology, 6(1), 69–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beddall, B. G. (1988). Darwin and Divergence: The Wallace connection. Journal of the History of Biology, 21(1), 1–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer, G. (2001). La evolución de la novela. In A. Fabián (Ed.), Evolución. Sociedad, ciencia y universo (pp. 157–182). Barcelona: Tusquets Editores.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanco, D. (2011). Las teorías científicas nacen como respuesta a problemas de la experiencia. Una objeción a Paul Thompson. Ludus Vitalis, 19(35), 113–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanco, D. (2012). Primera aproximación estructuralista a la Teoría del Origen en Común. Ágora, 31(2), 171–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blyth, E. (1835). An attempt to classify the varieties of animals, with observations on the marked seasonal and other changes which naturally take place in various british species, and which do not constitute varieties. Magazine of Natural History, 8, 40–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bock, W. (2009). The Darwin-Wallace Myth of 1858. Proceedings of the Zoological Society, 62(1), 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brackman, A. C. (1980). A delicate arrangement: The strange case of Charles Darwin and Alfred Russel Wallace. New York: Times Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. (1978). Adaptation and evolutionary theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 9, 181–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. (1990). Adaptation and environment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooke, J. (1984). Just before the origin: Alfred Russel Wallace’s theory of evolution. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, J. (1969). Re-assessment of A. R. Wallace’s contribution to the theory of organic evolution. Year Book 1968, Am. Phil. Sci (pp. 539–535).

  • Brooks, J. (1972). Extinction and the origin of organic diversity. Transactions of the Connecticut Academy of Arts and Sciences, 44, 19–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno Hernández, A., & Llorente Bousquets, J. (2003). El pensamiento biogeográfico de Alfred Russel Wallace. México DF: UNAM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burkhardt, F., Porter, D. M., Dean, S. A., White, P. S., & Wilmot, S. (Eds.). (2001). The correspondence of Charles Darwin, v. 12: 1864. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Burkhardt, F., & Smith, S. (Eds.). (1992). The correspondence of Charles Darwin, v. 7: 1858–1859. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Burkhardt, F., & Sydney, S. (Eds.). (1990). The correspondence of Charles Darwin, v. 6: 1856–1857. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Burstyn, H. L. (1975). If Darwin wasn’t the Beagle’s naturalist, Why was he on board? The British Journal for the History of Science, 8(1), 62–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cadevall i Soler, M. (1988). La estructura de la teoría de la evolución. Barcelona: Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerini, J. R. (1993). Evolution, biogeography, and maps: An early history of Wallace’s line. Isis, 84(4), 700–727.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. H. (1984). An organizational interpretation of evolution. In D. J. Depew & B. H. Weber (Eds.), Evolution at a crossroads: The new biology and the new philosophy of science (pp. 133–167). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caponi, G. (2009). Definitivamente no estaba ahí. Scientiae Studia, 17(32), 55–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castrodeza, C. (1988). Ortodoxia darwiniana y progreso biológico. Madrid: Alianza Editorial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costa, J. T. (2013). Engaging with Lyell: Alfred Russel Wallace’s Sarawak law and ternate papers as reactions to Charles Lyell’s principles of geology. Theory in Biosciences, 132(4), 225–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costa, J. T. (2014). Wallace, Darwin, and the origin of species. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L., & Cain, J. (1989). Selection type theories. Philosophy of Science, 56, 106–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. R. (1839). Journal of researches into the geology and natural history of the various countries visited by H.M.S. Beagle. London: Colburn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. R. (1859). On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. R. (1860). On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life (2nd ed.). London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. R. (1861). On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life (3rd ed.). London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. R. (1868). The variation of animals and plants under domestication. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. R. (1869). On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life (5th ed.). London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. R. (1872). The origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life (6th ed.). London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. R. (1883). The variation of animals and plants under domestication. New York: D. Apleton and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. R. (1909a). Essay of 1842. In F. Darwin (Ed.), The foundations of the origin of species. Two essays written in 1842 and 1844 (pp. 1–53). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. R. (1909b). Essay of 1844. In F. Darwin (Ed.), The foundations of the origin of species. Two essays written in 1842 and 1844 (pp. 57–255). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. R. (1958). The autobiography of Charles Darwin 1809–1882. With the original omissions restored. Edited and with appendix and notes by his grand-daughter Nora Barlow. London: Collins.

  • Díez, J. A., & Lorenzano, P. (2013). Who got what wrong? Fodor and Piattelli on Darwin: Guiding principles and explanatory models in natural selection. Erkenntnis, 78(5), 1143–1175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Díez, J. A., & Lorenzano, P. (2015). Are natural selection explanatory models a priori? Biology and Philosophy, 30(6), 887–889.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky, T., Ayala, F. J., Stebbins, G. L., & Valentine, J. W. (1977). Evolution. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • do Carmo, V. A., & Martins, L. A.-C. P. (2006). Charles Darwin, Alfred Russel Wallace e a seleção natural: um estudo comparativo. Filosofia E História Da Biologia, 1(1), 335–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eiseley, L. (1958). Darwin’s century: Evolution and the men who discovered it. New York: Barnes & Nobles.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eiseley, L. (1979). Darwin and the mysterious Mr. X. New York: Harvest Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Endler, J. A. (1986). Natural selection in the wild. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Endler, J. A. (1992). Natural selection: Current usages. In E. FoxKeller & E. A. Lloyd (Eds.), Keywords in evolutionary biology (pp. 220–224). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, L. T. (1984). Darwin’s use of the analogy between artificial and natural selection. Journal of the History of Biology, 17(1), 113–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fichman, M. (2001). Science in theistic contexts: A case study of Alfred Russel Wallace on human evolution. Osiris, 16, 227–250.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fichman, M. (2004). An elusive victorian: The evolution of Alfred Russel Wallace. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flew, A. G. N. (1959). The structure of Darwinism. New Biology, 28, 25–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. (1998). Darwinism’s struggle for survival: Heredity and the hypothesis of natural selection. Cambridge studies in philosophy and biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. T. (1969). The triumph of the Darwinian method. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. T. (1997). Metaphysics and the origin of species. SUNY series in philosophy and biology. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginnobili, S. (2010). La teoría de la selección natural darwiniana. Theoria, 25(1), 37–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginnobili, S. (2011). Selección artificial, selección sexual, selección natural. Metatheoria, 2(1), 61–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginnobili, S. (2012). Reconstrucción estructuralista de la teoría de la selección natural. Ágora Papeles de Filosofía, 31(2), 143–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginnobili, S. (2016). Missing concepts in natural selection theory reconstructions. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 38(3), 8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1976). Darwin’s untimely burial. Natural History, 85, 24–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1987). An urchin in the storm. New York: Norton & Company Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruber, H. E. (1974). Darwin on man: A psychological study of scientific creativity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, M. J. (1977). The structure and strategy of Darwin’s ‘long argument’. British Journal for the History of Science, 10(3), 237–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, M. J. (1983a). Darwin and the laws of the animate part of the terrestrial system (1835–1837). Studies in History of Biology, 6, 1–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, M. J. (1983b). The development of Darwin’s general biological theorizing. In D. S. Bendall (Ed.), Evolution: From molecules to men (pp. 43–62). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, M. J. (1985). Darwin as a lifelong generation theorist. In D. Kohn (Ed.), The Darwinian heritage: A centennial retrospect (pp. 207–243). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, M. J. (2010). Darwin, the Galapagos and his changing thoughts about species origins: 1835–1837. In Proceedings of the California Academy of Sciences, Series 4, vol. 61, Supplement II, No. 7, pp. 89–106.

  • Hodge, M. J., & Kohn, D. (1985). The immediate origins of natural selection. In D. Kohn (Ed.), The Darwinian heritage: A centennial retrospect (pp. 185–206). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Hooker, J. D. (1864). Hooker to Darwin, 14 May 1864. https://www.darwinproject.ac.uk/entry-4494. Retrieved 15 Oct 2015.

  • Hossfeld, U., & Olsson, L. (2013). The prominent absence of Alfred Russel Wallace at the Darwin anniversaries in Germany in 1909, 1959 and 2009. Theory in Biosciences, 132(4), 251–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, J., & de Asúa, F. (1942). Evolution: The modern synthesis. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karlin, S., & Carmelli, D. (1975). Some population genetics models combining artificial and natural selection pressures. Theoretical Population Biology, 7, 94–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science: Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klimovsky, G. (1994). Las desventuras del conocimiento científico. Buenos Aires: A-Z Editora.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kottler, M. (1985). Charles Darwin and Alfred Russell Wallace: Two decades of debate over natural selection. In D. Kohn (Ed.), The Darwinian heritage (pp. 367–431). Princeton: Princeton University Pess.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krimbas, C. B., & Krimbas, C. B. (2004). On fitness. Biology and Philosophy, 19, 185–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kutschera, U. (2003). A comparative analysis of the Darwin–Wallace papers and the development of the concept of natural selection. Theory in Biosciences, 122(4), 343–359.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kutschera, U. (2008). Darwin–Wallace principle of natural selection. Nature, 453(7191), 27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kutschera, U., & Hossfeld, U. (2013). Alfred Russel Wallace (1823–1913): The forgotten co-founder of the Neo-Darwinian theory of biological evolution. Theory in Biosciences, 132(4), 207–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kutschera, U., & Niklas, K. (2004). The modern theory of biological evolution: An expanded synthesis. Naturwissenschaften, 91, 255–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1978). The methodology of scientific research programmes: Philosophical papers (Vol. 1). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, J., & Wilson, B. (1994). Natural selection and the struggle for existence. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 25(1), 65–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lerner, I. M. (1959). The concept of natural selection: A centennial view. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 103(2), 173–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levit, G., & Hossfeld, U. (2011). Darwin without borders? Looking at generalised Darwinism through the prism of the hourglass model. Theory in Biosciences, 130(4), 299–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levit, G., & Polatayko, S. (2013). At home among strangers: Alfred Russel Wallace in Russia. Theory in Biosciences, 132(289–297), 292–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, D., Wimpenny, J., & Venables, A. (2010). Alfred Russel Wallace deserves better. Journal of Biosciences, 35(3), 339–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyell, C. (1830). Principles of geology. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malthus, T. R. (1798). An essay on the principle of population. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1972). Sexual selection and natural selection. In B. C. Campbell (Ed.), Sexual selection and the descent of man (pp. 1871–1971). Chicago: Aldine Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1982). The growth of biological thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1991). One long argument. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (2001). What evolution is. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKinney, H. L. (1966). Alfred Russel Wallace and the discovery of natural selection. Journal of the History of Medicine and Allied Sciences, XX, I(4), 333–357.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKinney, H. L. (1969). Wallace’s earliest observations on evolution: 28 December 1845. Isis, 60(3), 370–373.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKinney, H. L. (1972). Wallace and natural selection. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaux, B. (1966). Alfred Russel Wallace, biogeographer. In C. H. Smith & G. Beccaloni (Eds.), Natural selection and beyond: The intellectual legacy of Alfred Russel Wallace. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minvielle, F. (1981). Natural selection opposing artificial selection: A two-locus deterministic simulation. Genetics, 98, 231238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. (1997). Wallace’s Malthusian moment: The common context revisited. In B. Lightman (Ed.), Victorian science in context (pp. 290–311). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moulines, C. U. (1982). Exploraciones metacientíficas. Estructura, desarrollo y contenido de la ciencia. Madrid: Alianza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naylor, B. G., & Handford, P. (1985). In defense of Darwin’s theory. BioScience, 35(8), 478–484.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicholas, F. W., & Robertson, A. (1980). The conflict between natural and artificial selection in finite populations. Theoretical and Applied Genetics, 56(1–2), 57–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, D. (1993). On the road to the origin with Darwin, Hooker, and Gray. Journal of the History of Biology, 26(1), 1–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recker, D. (1990). There’s more than one way to recognize a Darwinian: Lyell’s Darwinism. Philosophy of Science, 57(3), 459–478.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reif, W., Junker, T., & Hossfeld, U. (2000). The synthetic theory of evolution: General problems and the German contribution to the synthesis. Theory in Biosciences, 119(1), 41–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. A. (2014). Darwin’s experimentalism. Endeavour, 38(3–4), 235–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1975). Charles Darwin and artificial selection. Journal of the History of Ideas, 36(2), 339–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1998). Taking Darwin seriously: A naturalistic approach to philosophy. New York: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (2013). Charles Robert Darwin and Alfred Russel Wallace: Their dispute over the units of selection. Theory in Biosciences, 132(4), 215–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, J. (1974). Charles Darwin’s debt to Malthus and Edward Blyth. Journal of the History of Biology, 7(2), 301–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Secord, J. A. (1981). Nature’s fancy: Charles Darwin and the breeding of pigeons. Isis, 72(2), 163–186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Secord, J. A. (2000). Victorian sensation. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slotten, R. A. (2004). The heretic in Darwin’s court: The life of Alfred Russel Wallace. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, C. (2015). Alfred Russel Wallace and the road to natural selection, 1844–1858. Journal of the History of Biology, 48(2), 279–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sneed, J. D. (1971). The logical structure of mathematical physics. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, H. (1864). The principles of biology (Vol. 1). London: William and Norgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, H. G., & Masters, J. C. (1992). Sexual selection: Contemporary debates. In E. F. Keller & E. A. Lloyd (Eds.), Keywords in evolutionary biology (pp. 294–301). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stauffer, R. C. (Ed.). (1975). Charles Darwin’s natural selection; being the second part of his big species book written from 1856 to 1858. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterrett, S. G. (2002). Darwin’s analogy between artificial and natural selection: How does it go? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 33(1), 151–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sulloway, F. (1982). Darwin’s conversion: The Beagle voyage and its aftermath. Journal of the History of Biology, 15, 325–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sulloway, F. (2009). Tantalizing tortoises and te Darwin-Galápagos legend. Journal of the History of Biology, 42, 3–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornhill, R., & Alcock, J. (1983). The evolution of insect mating systems. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomi, J. (1981). Structure and dynamics of Darwinian evolutionary theory. Systematic Zoology, 30(1), 22–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomi, J., & Haukioja, E. (1979a). An analysis of natural selection in models of life-history theory. Savonia, 3, 9–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomi, J., & Haukioja, E. (1979b). Predictability of the theory of natural selection: An analysis of the structure of the Darwinian theory. Savonia, 3, 1–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Wyhe, J. (2016). The impact of A. R. Wallace’s Sarawak law paper reassessed. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 60, 56–66.

  • Wallace, A. R. (1853). Narrative of travels on the Amazon and Rio Negro, with an account of the native tribes, and observations on the climate, geology, and natural history of the Amazon Valley. London: Reeve & CO.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1855). On the law which has regulated the introduction of new species. Annals and Magazine of Natural History, 16, 184–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1858). On the tendency of varieties to depart indefinitely from the original type. Journal of the Proceedings of the Linnean Society of London, 3, 53–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1864). The origin of human races and the antiquity of man deduced from the theory of natural selection. Anthropological Society of London, 2, 158–186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1869a). Review of principles of geology and elements of geology, by Charles Lyell. Quarterly Review, 126, 359–394.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1869). The Malay Archipelago: The land of the Orang-Utan and the bird of paradise. A narrative of travel, with studies of man and nature. London: Macmillan & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1870). Contributions to the theory of natural selection. A series of essays. London: Macmillan & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1880). Island life: Or, the phenomena and causes of Insular Faunas and Floras, including a revision and attempted solution of the problem of geological climates. London: Macmillan & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1889). Darwinism: An exposition of the theory of the theory of natural selection with some of its applications. London: Macmillan & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1891). Natural selection and tropical nature: Essays on descriptive and theoretical biology. London: Macmillan & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1898). The wonderful century; its successes and its failures. London: Swan Sonnenschein & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1903). Man’s place in the Universe: A study of the results of scientific research in relation to the unity or plurality of worlds. London: Chapman & Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1905). My life: A record of events and opinions. London: Chapman & Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1908). Wallace acceptance speech on receiving the Darwin-Wallace medal. In Linnean Society of London (Ed.), The Darwin-Wallace Celebration held on thursday, 1st July, 1908, by the Linnean Society of London. London: Burlington House.

  • Wallace, A. R. (1909). Note on the passages of Malthus’s “principle of population” which suggested the idea of natural selection to Darwin and myself. The Darwin–Wallace celebration held on Thursday. 1st July 1908, by the Linnean Society of London. London: Longmans Green & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1910). The world of life: A manifestation of creative power, directive mind and utimate purpose. London: Chapman & Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. R. (1913). Social environment and moral progress. London: Cassell & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wassermann, G. D. (1978). Testability of the role of natural selection within theories of population genetics and evolution. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 29(3), 223–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilner, E. (2006). Darwin’s artificial selection as an experiment. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C, 37(1), 26–40.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We want to thank Roberto Biaggi, Damien Rochford and two anonymous referees for their helpful comments on previous versions of this paper. This research was supported by the research Projects PICT-2014-1741 (ANPCyT, Argentina), Research Program “Philosophy and History of Science” PUNQ, 1719/11 (UNQ, Argentina), and 32/15 255 (UNTREF, Argentina).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Santiago Ginnobili.

Additional information

Equal time was dedicated to the production of this article. Order of authorship was decided by chance.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ginnobili, S., Blanco, D. Wallace’s and Darwin’s natural selection theories. Synthese 196, 991–1017 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1491-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1491-z

Keywords

Navigation