Skip to main content
Log in

Cognitive penetration and the cognition–perception interface

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

A Correction to this article was published on 04 October 2018

This article has been updated

Abstract

I argue that discussions of cognitive penetration have been insufficiently clear about (i) what distinguishes perception and cognition, and (ii) what kind of relationship between the two is supposed to be at stake in the debate. A strong reading, which is compatible with many characterizations of penetration, posits a highly specific and directed influence on perception. According to this view, which I call the “internal effect view” (IEV) a cognitive state penetrates a perceptual process if the presence of the cognitive state causes a change to the computation performed by the process, with the result being a distinct output. I produce a novel argument that this strong reading is false. On one well-motivated way of drawing the distinction between perceptual states and cognitive states, cognitive representations cannot play the computational role posited for them by IEV, vis-à-vis perception. This does not mean, however, that there are not important causal relationships between cognitive and perceptual states. I introduce an alternative view of these relationships, the “external effect view” (EEV). EEV posits that each cognitive state is associated with a broad range of possible perceptual outcomes, and biases perception towards any of those perceptual outcomes without determining specific perceptual contents. I argue that EEV captures the kinds of cases philosophers have thought to be evidence for IEV, and a wide range of other cases as well.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

  • 04 October 2018

    On page 3653, there is a mistake in the explanation of the Cornsweet illusion. In fact, the explanation is that the panel perceived as darker is facing towards the light source?in the case of this figure the light is coming from the right.

  • 04 October 2018

    On page 3653, there is a mistake in the explanation of the Cornsweet illusion. In fact, the explanation is that the panel perceived as darker is facing towards the light source���in the case of this figure the light is coming from the right.

Notes

  1. Even though philosophers generally claim to be interested in the relationship between cognition and perceptual experiences, all arguments surrounding cognitive penetration involve characterizing and attempting to establish (or deny) particular causal relationships between the two. As such, a typology of possible causal relationships is highly pertinent.

  2. This is a slight oversimplification, since Dretske argues that, even in a digital representation, information can be logically nested—for instance, the information that s is a square nests the information that it is a rectangle. I will ignore this complication here.

  3. See (Burnston and Cohen 2013, 2015) for a view of perceptual architecture that explicitly builds in these features.

  4. I will often discuss lexical concepts hereafter, but it should be noted that I don’t take these as predominant over or exclusive of atomic representations.

  5. For a full discussion of these topics; see (Burnston, in submission).

  6. Stokes (2012) definition of cognitive penetration does not explicitly include either the semantic or computation conditions, but he has a weaker view than many in this respect. Wu (2013), in some places the most explicit proponent of the computation condition, also occasionally describes cognitive influence on perception in terms of “structuring causes,” which could potentially be interpretable as a weaker relationship. I offer such a weaker characterization in the next section.

  7. Thanks to Matt Fulkerson for encouraging me to stress extractability here.

  8. Why not suggest that a single cognitive concept can convey multiple distinct commands to distinct perceptual processes? All that this would require would be that the cognitive content was interpreted differently by distinct perceptual processes to which it was connected (e.g., perceptual processes in distinct modalities would interpret the same signal as a command to modify their mappings of arguments in their distinct domains), and this would support distinct internal effects coming from the same process. While this argument, appropriately supplemented, might show how distinct processes could be modified, it doesn’t account for evidence-sensitivity or graded effects. So long as the appropriate amount of modification depends on the evidence for the category, simply conveying a different command to each perceptual process won’t solve the problem. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this objection.

  9. Similarly, it won’t work to propose that the translation mechanism doesn’t represent anything at all, but is a pure format converter, similar to a digital-to-analog converter. Without going too far into it, digital-to-analog converters work by mapping each digital signal, via a filtering or interpolation function, to one specific analog waveform or value. So, positing a format converter is simply a sophisticated version of the command objection.

  10. To acknowledge some debts: EEV is inspired partially by Barsalou et al. ’s (2008) theory of language-perception interaction, which treats linguistic representations as a kind of indexing system for perceptual representations, and by Millikan ’s (2000) underappreciated theory of atomic “substance” concepts. However, EEV neither shares all of the assumptions, nor recapitulates all of the claims of these views, and supplies a more detailed view of the interface than either. Like these other views, EEV presupposes some learning theory that explains how particular lexical or atomic concepts get hooked up to particular processes. I won’t speculate as to that here; see Millikan (2000) for one proposal.

  11. There are a number of remaining questions about this kind of view, for instance how viewpoint-dependent these representations are, whether categories consist in abstract prototypes or a range of exemplars, etc. I won’t go into these here (but see the end of Sect. 6). Also, I should note some different potential readings of these claims—Goldstone and Hendrickson (2010) suggest that these categories reflect “permeability” between cognition and perception, since they take the reading that categorical effects must be cognitive. I think this is a mistake, for the reasons given in Sect. 2 (cf. Burnston, in submission). Raftopoulos (2009, p. 70) takes the fact that categorical representations like these are representations in memory, and must be matched to incoming stimuli, to show that they are cognitive. Others have focused on the fact that they are learned to make a similar point (Stokes 2014). But given that it is possible to store representations with perceptual form in long term memory (Barsalou 1999), these inferences don’t follow. I can’t argue for this convincingly here; I say much more on these topics in (Burnston, in submission).

  12. For simplicity’s I will talk about a uniform biasing of any process associated with the concept, but EEV is not in principle committed to this. Some processes, in virtue of being more typical of the category, could be more heavily biased than others.

  13. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging me to get clearer about the role that the visual world studies are playing in the argument here.

References

  • Altmann, G., & Mirković, J. (2009). Incrementality and prediction in human sentence processing. Cognitive Science, 33(4), 583–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(4), 577–609.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L. W., Santos, A., Simmons, W. K., & Wilson, C. D. (2008). Language and simulation in conceptual processing. In M. De Vega, A. M. Glenberg, & A. C. Graesser (Eds.), Symbols, embodiment, and meaning (pp. 245–283). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brunel, L., Goldstone, R. L., Vallet, G., Riou, B., & Versace, R. (2013). When seeing a dog activates the bark: Multisensory generalization and distinctiveness effects. Experimental Psychology, 60(2), 100–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burnston (in submission). Is aesthetic experience evidence for cognitive penetration?

  • Burnston, D., & Cohen, J. (2013). Perception of features and perception of objects. Croatian Journal of Philosophy, 12(3), 283–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnston, D. C., & Cohen, J. (2015). Perceptual integration, modularity, and cognitive penetration. In J. Zeimbekis & A. Raftopoulos (Eds.), Cognitive influences on perception: Implications for philosophy of mind, epistemology, and philosophy of action (pp. 123–143). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Delk, J. L., & Fillenbaum, S. (1965). Difference in perceived colour as a function of characteristic colour. The American Journal of Psychology, 52(2), 255–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deroy, O. (2013). Object-sensitivity versus cognitive penetrability of perception. Philosophical Studies, 162(1), 87–107.

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Firestone, C., & Scholl, B. J. (2015). Cognition does not affect perception: Evaluating the evidence for “top-down” effects. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. doi:10.1017/S0140525X15000965.

  • Fodor, J. A. (1998). Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (2001). The mind doesn’t work that way: The scope and limits of computational psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (2007). The revenge of the given. In B. P. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind (pp. 105–116). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2015). Minds without meanings: An essay on the content of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glenberg, A. M., & Kaschak, M. P. (2002). Grounding language in action. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 9(3), 558–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstone, R. L., & Hendrickson, A. T. (2010). Categorical perception. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 1(1), 69–78. doi:10.1002/wcs.26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heck, R. (2007). Are there different kinds of content? In J. Cohen & B. P. McLaughlin (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind (pp. 117–138). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herz, R. S., & von Clef, J. (2001). The influence of verbal labeling on the perception of odors: Evidence for olfactory illusions? Perception, 30(3), 381–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heurley, L. P., Milhau, A., Chesnoy-Servanin, G., Ferrier, L. P., Brouillet, T., & Brouillet, D. (2012). Influence of language on colour perception: A simulationist explanation. Biolinguistics, 6(3–4), 354–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huettig, F., & Altmann, G. T. (2007). Visual-shape competition during language-mediated attention is based on lexical input and not modulated by contextual appropriateness. Visual Cognition, 15(8), 985–1018.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huettig, F., & Altmann, G. T. (2011). Looking at anything that is green when hearing “frog”: How object surface colour and stored object colour knowledge influence language-mediated overt attention. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 64(1), 122–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Julesz, B. (1981). Textons, the elements of texture perception, and their interactions. Nature, 290(12), 91–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S. M. (2005). Mental images and the brain. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 22(3), 333–347. doi:10.1080/02643290442000130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kulvicki, J. (2005). Perceptual content, information, and the primary/secondary quality distinction. Philosophical Studies, 122(2), 103–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levin, D. T., & Banaji, M. R. (2006). Distortions in the perceived lightness of faces: The role of race categories. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 135(4), 501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, F. (2012). Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(1), 24–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (2000). On clear and confused ideas: An essay about substance concepts. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mishra, R. K., & Marmolejo-Ramos, F. (2010). On the mental representations originating during the interaction between language and vision. Cognitive Processing, 11(4), 295–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mole, C. (2015). Attention and cognitive penetration. In J. Zeimbekis & A. Raftopoulos (Eds.), The cognitive penetrability of perception: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 218–238). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2014). Cognitive penetration and the gallery of indiscernibles. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1527.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olkkonen, M., Hansen, T., & Gegenfurtner, K. R. (2008). Color appearance of familiar objects: Effects of object shape, texture, and illumination changes. Journal of Vision, 8(5), 11–16. doi:10.1167/8.5.13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palmeri, T. J., & Gauthier, I. (2004). Visual object understanding. Nature reviews. Neuroscience, 5(4), 291–303. doi:10.1038/nrn1364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pulvermüller, F., Hauk, O., Nikulin, V. V., & Ilmoniemi, R. J. (2005). Functional links between motor and language systems. European Journal of Neuroscience, 21(3), 793–797.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Purves, D., Shimpi, A., & Lotto, R. B. (1999). An empirical explanation of the Cornsweet effect. The Journal of Neuroscience, 19(19), 8542–8551.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1999). Is vision continuous with cognition? The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(3), 341–365; discussion 366–423.

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2007). Things and places: How the mind connects with the world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2009). Cognition and perception: How do psychology and neural science inform philosophy?. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rock, I. (1983). The logic of perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (2005). Consciousness and mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2012). Cognitive penetrability and perceptual justification. Noûs, 46(2), 201–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanfield, R. A., & Zwaan, R. A. (2001). The effect of implied orientation derived from verbal context on picture recognition. Psychological Science, 12(2), 153–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, D. (2012). Perceiving and desiring: A new look at the cognitive penetrability of experience. Philosophical Studies, 158(3), 477–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, D. (2014). Cognitive penetration and the perception of art. Dialectica, 68(1), 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toribio, J. (2015). Visual experience: Rich but impenetrable. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0889-8.

  • Wu, W. (2013). Visual spatial constancy and modularity: Does intention penetrate vision? Philosophical Studies, 165(2), 647–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zwaan, R. A., & Madden, C. J. (2005). Embodied sentence comprehension. In D. Pecher & R. A. Zwaan (Eds.), Grounding cognition: The role of perception and action in memory, language, and thinking (pp. 224–245). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zwaan, R. A., Madden, C. J., Yaxley, R. H., & Aveyard, M. E. (2004). Moving words: Dynamic representations in language comprehension. Cognitive Science, 28(4), 611–619.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwaan, R. A., Stanfield, R. A., & Yaxley, R. H. (2002). Language comprehenders mentally represent the shapes of objects. Psychological Science, 13(2), 168–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank William Bechtel, Jonathan Cohen, Matthew Fulkerson, Shannon Spaulding, Sarah Robins, and Wayne Wu for exceedingly helpful comments on earlier drafts. An early version of this paper was presented at the 2014 Central APA Meeting in Chicago; thank you to the audience for a very helpful discussion, and to Wayne Wu for thoughtful commentary.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel C. Burnston.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Burnston, D.C. Cognitive penetration and the cognition–perception interface. Synthese 194, 3645–3668 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1116-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1116-y

Keywords

Navigation