Skip to main content
Log in

Interpretations without justification: a general argument against Morgan’s Canon

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I critically discuss and, in the end, reject Morgan’s Canon, a popular principle in comparative psychology. According to this principle we should always prefer explanations of animal behavior in terms of lower psychological processes over explanations in terms of higher psychological processes, when alternative explanations are possible. The validity of the principle depends on two things, a clear understanding of what it means for psychological processes to be higher or lower relative to each other (1) and a justification of a general preference for explanations that refer to lower psychological abilities (2). However, I argue that we cannot spell out the idea of a psychological scale in a way that claim (2) is satisfied. I start with the discussion of different interpretations of the notion of a psychological scale (Sect. 2). In Sect. 3, I discuss different possible strategies to justify any of those interpretations and argue that all of them fail. Finally, in Sect. 4, I generalize the argument for all possible interpretations of Morgan’s Canon and propose an alternative strategy: We should base our interpretations of animal behavior on more general principles such as evidential support and explanatory power, as followed in other scientific domains.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is also what Morgan had in mind as becomes clear in the following passage: ,,[T]o assume [...] complexity of mental nature on grounds other than those of sound induction, is to depart from the methods of scientific procedure“ (Morgan 1894, p. 54, my italics).

  2. Interestingly, Morgan himself was one of he first to describe the Baldwin effect (Morgan 1896).

  3. In this paper I am interested in the question whether the principle Morgan’s Canon can be justified under any interpretation (including views Morgan did not consider). To answer this, the question which interpretation is historically most accurate is of minor importance. For a good discussion of Morgan’s view of the different methods see Sober (1998). A very good discussion of Morgan’s Canon from a historical point of view can be found in Thomas (2001).

  4. It should be mentioned that the conceptions discussed in the following sections do not constitute an exhaustive list of all suggestions for how one can understand the notion of a psychological scale.

  5. Note that although according to Karin-D’Arcy higher (derived) psychological processes are additional processes, the notion of causal priority is also consistent with lower (ancestral) processes evolving into higher ones. In this case the higher process would substitute the lower one, a possibility that will play a role for the question of justification.

  6. Thanks to Hans-Johann Glock for pointing this possibility out to me. For his own view see Glock, Animal Minds—Conceptual Problems (2016).

  7. In fact this is close to Morgan’s original idea that the method we use in animal psychology is based on double induction. See also Sect. 3.3.1.

  8. This is not a purely theoretical objection. The nature of concepts, beliefs, theory of mind, causal understanding etc. is subject of ongoing debates in philosophy.

  9. Obviously there is also the possibility that the behavioral output of a psychological process doesn’t even overlap with the output of another. But in this case, the two processes can’t be rival explanation for one and the same behavior and thus this case is irrelevant for the present discussion.

  10. For instance it has been argued that false explanations don’t really explain anything.

  11. I can’t defend this claim in this paper. But it can be read as a concession to Morgan’s Canon because it opens the possibility that Morgan’s Canon picks out better explanations even if it turns out that these explanations are not more likely to be true than alternatives.

  12. It should be noted, however, that both Morgan, and Povinelli and Vonk (2006) don’t interpret that as speaking in favor of higher-level explanations, but rather for discarding this kind of simplicity (cognitive salience) as relevant, since it ,,is no necessary criterion for it’s truth“ (Morgan 1894, p. 54). This supports the claim that it’s in terms of truth, not explanatory power that Morgan’s Canon should be justified, as I argue below.

  13. The term likeliness is used in its ordinary usage in the English language as a synonym for probability. It refers to the probability of an explanatory hypothesis in the light of the evidence (Pr(H|E)). This is not to be confused with the technical term likelihood which refers to “the probability that the [hypothesis] confers to [the evidence]” (Sober 2009, p. 120). In other words, the likelihood of an explanatory hypothesis H on evidence E expresses “the degree to which the hypothesis predicts the data given the background information” (Joyce 2008) and it is represented by “Pr(E|H)”.

  14. Here I am following Fitzpatrick (2008) with his assumption that parsimony is a special kind of simplicity.

  15. Strictly speaking, this is only true if the probability of both conjuncts is \(>\)0 (if it wasn’t, they couldn’t be alternative explanations that call for Morgan’s Canon) and the probability of the conjunction is \(<\)1.

  16. This example fits both the scale of causal priority and the scale of conceptual entailment.

  17. This is just to say that ontologically more parsimonious explanations are not more likely to be true in virtue of being ontologically more parsimonious. In the next section I’ll discuss whether these probabilities change if we assess them on the basis of our empirical knowledge.

  18. In fact this seems to be true for every conception of a psychological scale, since what is being ranked are types of processes rather than tokens.

  19. There is a debate whether this is true for the question of ToM in animals. Some argue that mind-readers exploit the same behavioral cues as behavior readers and thus the learning history must be the same and cannot be used to determine which ability underlies an animal’s behavior (Penn and Povinelli 2007; Penn et al. 2008). This view has been challenged by others who argue that the benefit of mind-reading is precisely that it allows a subject to interpret behavioral cues on the basis of inference rather than merely from previous experience with the same cue (Buckner 2014; Sober 2015). In this case, mind-readers would have to learn different things than behavior-readers to produce similar behavior and this difference in learning trajectories could be exploited to determine which abilities underlie a behavior in question. I am sympathetic to the second view.

  20. Although it’s true that lower psychological processes are more likely to be found in animals than higher processes according to the scales based on causal priority and (because of its implicit evolutionary claim) conceptual entailment, as I argued in Sect. 3.3.2 these are the wrong probabilities to compare.

  21. This probably also corresponds to the view of Shettleworth (2013).

  22. Alternatively, it might be argued that all species are relevant, but to different degrees. In this case, our knowledge concerning closely related or behaviorally similar species would carry more weight than that of others. The conclusion, however, would still be the same.

  23. Cladistic parsimony can even be assessed without looking at behavior: all we have to look for is whether the most closely related species have a certain property/ability or not.

  24. Note that this is not only a problem for my position, but for every position including Morgan’s Canon. Showing that it picks out better explanations presupposes being able to identify better explanations.

  25. Inconclusive evidence just means that the available evidence doesn’t make one explanation more likely than an alternative. Thus, cases where we lack any evidence also count as cases where the evidence is inconclusive.

  26. Not only do we not have to believe in the hypothesis we are testing to continue scientific investigation, the hypothesis we should choose will often be the higher-level explanation. A good example from comparative psychology can be found in Fitzpatrick (2008, p. 236). There he argues that von Frisch ’s (1967) working under the hypothesis that honeybees communicate with each other made him investigate the topic and discover the communicative function of the bee-dance. More generally, if we adopt Sober’s conception of higher and lower psychological abilities, what we should do in cases where we can explain a certain behavior with two different psychological processes is to check whether we also find behavior that is not in the overlap of the two processes (Sober 1998, p. 238). If there is a behavioral inclusion relation, this will always be the higher process.

References

  • Allen, C. (2006). Transitive inference in animals: Reasoning or conditioned associations. In M. Nudds & S. Hurley (Eds.), Rational animals? (pp. 175–186). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, C., & Bekoff, M. (2007). Animal minds, cognitive ethology, and ethics. Journal of Ethics, 11, 299–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2013). Morgan’s Canon, meet Hume’s Dictum: avoiding anthropofabulation in cross-species comparisons. Biology Philosophy, 28, 853–871.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2014). The semantic problem(s) with research on animal mind-reading. Mind & Language, 29(5), 566–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burghardt, G. (1985). Animal awareness-current perceptions and historical perspective. American Psychologist, 40, 905–919.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1982). Rational animals. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Subjective, intersubjective, objective (pp. 95–105). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1983). Intentional systems in cognitive ethology: the ‘Panglossian paradigm’ defended. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 6, 343–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (2013). Intuition pumps and other tools for thinking. New York: Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewsbury, D. A. (1984). Comparative psychology in the twentieth century. Stroudsburg, PA: Hutchinson Ross.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dewsbury, D. A. (1973). Introduction. In D. A. Dewsbury & D. A. Rethlingshafer (Eds.), Comparative psychology: A modern survey. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Waal, F. B. M. (1991). Complementary methods and convergent evidence in the study of primate social cognition. Behaviour, 118, 297–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, S. (2008). Doing away with Morgan’s Canon. Mind and Language, 23(2), 224–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galef, B. (1996). Historical origins: The making of a science. In L. Houck & L. Drickamer (Eds.), Foundations of animal behavior: Classic papers with commentaries. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H.-J. (2016). Animal minds—conceptual problems (forthcoming).

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2014). Philosophy of biology. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, W. (1856). Discussions on philosophy and literature, education and university reform. New York: Harper & Brothers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heider, F., & Simmel, M. (1944). An experimental study of apparent behavior. The American Journal of Psychology, 57, 243–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. (2008). Bayes’ theorem. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2008 edition). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/bayes-theorem/.

  • Kaplan, D. M., & Craver, C. F. (2011). The explanatory force of dynamical and mathematical models in neuroscience: A mechanistic perspective. Philosophy of Science, 78(4), 601–627. doi:10.1086/661755.

  • Karin-D’Arcy, M. R. (2005). The modern role of Morgan’s Canon in comparative psychology. International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 18, 179–201.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamarck, J.-B. (2011). Zoological philosophy: An exposition with regard to the natural history of animals (H. S. R. Elliott, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McClelland, J. L., Botvinick, M. M., Noelle, D. C., Plaut, D. C., Rogers, T. T., Seidenberg, M. S., et al. (2010). Letting structure emerge: Connectionist and dynamical systems approaches to cognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14(8), 348–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meketa, I. (2014). A critique of the principle of cognitive simplicity in comparative cognition. Biology Philosophy. doi:10.1007/s10539-014-9429-z.

  • Morgan, C. L. (1890). Animal life and intelligence. London: Edward Arnold.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, C. L. (1894). Introduction to comparative psychology. London: Walter Scott.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, C. L. (1896). Habitat and instinct. London: Edward Arnold.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, C. L. (1903). Introduction to comparative psychology. London: Walter Scott.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penn, D., & Povinelli, D. (2007). On the lack of evidence that non-human animals possess anything remotely resembling a ‘theory of mind’. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B-Biological Sciences, 362(1480), 731–744.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penn, D., Holyoak, K., & Povinelli, D. (2008). Darwin’s mistake: Explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 31, 109–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli, D. J., & Vonk, J. (2006). We don‘t need a microscope to explore the chimpanzees mind. In M. Nudds & S. Hurley (Eds.), Rational animals? (pp. 385–412). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Roeckelein, J. E. (Ed.). (2006). Elsevier’s dictionary of psychological theories. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shettleworth, S. J. (2013). Fundamentals of comparative cognition. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1998). Morgan’s Cannon. In D. Cummins & C. Allen (Eds.), The Evolution of Mind (pp. 224–242). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2009). Parsimony arguments in science and philosophy: A test case for naturalism P. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 83(2), 117–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2012). Anthropomorphism, parsimony, and common ancestry. Mind and Language, 27(3), 229–238.

  • Sober, E. (2015). Parsimony and chimpanzee mind-reading. In Keynote Talk held at the Conference, The nature and origins of human cognition. Berlin, June 18th 2015.

  • Sterelny, K. (2012). The evolved apprentice. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1979). Do animals have beliefs? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 57, 15–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, R. K. (2001). Lloyd Morgan’s Canon: A history of misrepresentation. Retrieved from https://faculty.franklin.uga.edu/rkthomas/sites/faculty.franklin.uga.edu.rkthomas/files/MCPrintOptimal.pdf.

  • Tomasello, M., & Call, J. (2006). Do chimpanzees know what others see—or only what they are looking at? In M. Nudds & S. Hurley (Eds.), Rational animals? (pp. 371–384). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • von Frisch, K. (1967). The dance language and the orientation of bees. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, B. H., & Depew, D. J. (2003). Evolution and learning: The Baldwin effect reconsidered. In Bradford books—life and mind: Philosophical issues in biology and psychology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Ylikoski, P., & Kuorikoski, J. (2010). Dissecting explanatory power. Philosophical Studies, 148(2), 201–219.

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work has been generously supported by the Fritz Thyssen Stiftung für Wissenschaftsförderung. I’d also like to thank Albert Newen, Hanjo Glock, Cameron Buckner, Peter Brössel and Markus Werning for discussion, as well as two anonymous reviewers for their constructive criticism and their extremely helpful comments on the manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tobias Starzak.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Starzak, T. Interpretations without justification: a general argument against Morgan’s Canon. Synthese 194, 1681–1701 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1013-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1013-4

Keywords

Navigation