Skip to main content
Log in

Retractions

  • S.I. : Lang And Mind
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Intuitions about retractions have been used to motivate truth relativism about certain types of claims. Among these figure epistemic modals, knowledge attributions, or personal taste claims. On MacFarlane’s prominent relativist proposal, sentences like “the ice cream might be in the freezer” or “Pocoyo is funny” are only assigned a truth-value relative to contexts of utterance and contexts of assessment. Retractions play a crucial role in the argument for assessment-relativism. A retraction of a past assertion is supposed to be mandatory whenever the asserted sentence is not true at the context of use and the context of assessment. If retractions were not obligatory in these conditions, there would be no normative difference between assessment-relativism and contextualism. The main goal of this paper is to undermine the claim that retractions reveal this normative difference. To this effect, the paper offers a review of three important objections to the obligatoriness of retractions. Taken together, these objections make a strong case against the alleged support that retractions give to assessment-relativism. The objections are moreover supported by recent experimental results that are also discussed. This will satisfy a further goal, which is to undermine the idea that there is a constitutive retraction rule. The paper also discusses two ways to understand what such a rule would be constitutive of, and concludes with a discussion of how to describe what retractions are.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Authors that have contributed to the debate include among others DeRose (1991, 1992), Dowell (2011, 2013), Hawthorne (2004), Egan et al. (2005), Egan (2007, 2010), Glanzberg (2007), Kölbel (2002, 2004a, b), Kolodny and MacFarlane (2010), Lasersohn (2005), López de Sa (2008, 2015), MacFarlane (2005a, b), Recanati (2007), Stanley (2005), Stephenson (2007), and Stojanovic (2007).

  2. It is certain that for indexical contextualists only the truth of sentences depends on, i.e. is relative to, context. Once a sentence as used in context expresses a proposition, that proposition’s truth-value only varies with respect to possible worlds, if it is contingent. For nonindexical contextualists, the same possible world proposition may still vary in truth-value with respect to times, judges, standards of taste, etc.

  3. I will not offer in detail an exposition of MacFarlane’s semantics, nor of his distinction between semantics and postsemantics. For a detailed exposition, see for instance MacFarlane (2014), Chap. 3 and schematically, Fig. 3.2 on p. 58 and Fig. 3.3. on p. 61.

  4. MacFarlane (2014) discussion in p. 102 and ff. suggests he agrees with Pagin’s characterization of constitutive rules.

  5. MacFarlane’s comments in p. 109 suggest that he thinks that, for any kind of speech act T, there is a corresponding kind of retraction \(R_T\).

  6. This is also how Pagin (2015) interprets the Retraction Rule. MacFarlane (2014) repeats the second interpretation of the Retraction Rule as constitutive of retraction in other places, for instance p. 256. I think this is confused, for the reasons indicated earlier.

  7. I thank an anonymous referee for pointing out the need to distinguish between these two retraction challenges.

  8. MacFarlane (2005b) admits that having to retract whenever one is challenged is “too damaging to the integrity of a single person’s body of assertions...It demands too much of asserters to give every challenger the home stadium advantage” (MacFarlane 2005b, p. 320).

  9. See Saul (2012) on the wrongness of misleading and lying.

  10. I had doubts about the “appropriate to retract” question, since I think an appropriate act is not the same deontically as a required act. If something is required, then it better be appropriate. But if we agree that something is appropriate we have not, yet, established that it is required. Contrast for instance the two cases “it is appropriate for a woman to wear high heels to work” and “a woman is required to wear high heels to work”. Most people would agree with the former, but disagree with the latter. With this distinction in mind, we repeated the last experiment by Knobe and Yalcin (2014), using the same Sally and George example, the same methods with AMT, with 203 participants. The only change in our new experiment was a small change in the retraction question, which now read “Is Sally required to take back what she said?” In our new experiment, the divergence in judgments of falsity and of retraction was even more striking, confirming the prediction that “being appropriate” and “being required” elicit disparate judgments. The mean rating for agreement with the falsity of the modal was down at 3.49 on the Likert scale, and the mean rating for agreement with the requirement to retract was even lower at 3.26. The results confirm, among other things, that there is a significant deontic difference between appropriateness and obligation, and reinforce Knobe and Yalcin’s conclusion that (J) is mistaken. Full results and their analysis are presented in forthcoming work.

  11. In recent work, Kneer (2015) also tested formulations of epistemic modals which made the indexical contextualist interpretation explicit. Besides collecting data on sentences like ‘John might be in China’ (when it turns out he isn’t), he also tested the formulation ‘For all I know, John is in China’. On the results he reports, there is no significant difference between the modal formulation and the contextualist’s best shot (‘for all I know, \(\phi \)’). He concludes that this refutes assessment-relativism and also makes a strong case for indexical-contextualism.

  12. These are in contrast with Hom (2008)’s view on pejoratives, for whom assertions with pejoratives and slurs express thick prescriptive properties, and as a result apply to no one—no one should be treated in such and such contemptuous way as a virtue of possessing certain features. As a result, pejorative assertions are, he claims, false. For a different view and criticism, see Jeshion (2013).

  13. On metalinguistic negation, see for instance Horn (1989) and Carston (1998).

References

  • Carston, R. (1998). Negation, ‘presupposition’ and the semantics/ pragmatics distinction. Journal of Linguistics, 34, 309–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1991). Epistemic possibilities. Philosophical Review, 100(4), 581–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1992). Contextualism and knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52(4), 913–929.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2002). Knowledge, assertion, and context. Philosophical Review, 111, 167–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowell, J. (2011). A flexible contextualist account of epistemic modals. Philosophers’ Imprint, 11(14), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowell, J. (2013). Flexible contextualism about deontic modals: A puzzle about information-sensitivity. Inquiry, 56(2–3), 149–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. A. E. (1978). Truth and other enigmas. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edgington, D. (1995). On conditionals. Mind, 104(414), 235–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan, A. (2007). Epistemic modals, relativism and assertion. Philosophical Studies, 133(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan, A. (2010). Disputing about taste. In R. Feldman & T. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement (pp. 247–286). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Egan, A., Hawthorne, J., & Weatherson, B. (2005). Epistemic modals in context. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy: Knowledge, meaning and truth (pp. 131–170). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • García-Carpintero, M. (2008). Relativism, vagueness and what is said. In M. García-Carpintero & M. Klbel (Eds.), Relative truth (pp. 129–154). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Glanzberg, M. (2007). Context, content, and relativism. Philosophical Studies, 136(1), 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hom, C. (2008). The semantics of racial epithets. Journal of Philosophy, 105(8), 416–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hom, C. (2010). Pejoratives. Philosophy Compass, 5(2), 164–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. (1989). A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huvenes, T. T. (2012). Varieties of disagreement and predicates of taste. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(1), 167–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeshion, R. (2013). Slurs and stereotypes. Analytic Philosophy, 54(3), 314–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. K. Perry, H. Wettstein, & D. Kaplan (Eds.), Themes from kaplan. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kölbel, M. (2002). Truth without objectivity. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kölbel, M. (2004a). Faultless disagreement. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 104(1), 53–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kölbel, M. (2004b). Indexical relativism versus genuine relativism. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 12(3), 297–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kneer, M. (2015). Truth-assessment and retraction of epistemic modals: Empirical data, unpublished manuscript.

  • Knobe, J., & Yalcin, S. (2014). Epistemic modals and context: Experimental data. Semantics and Pragmatics, 7(10), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny, N., & MacFarlane, J. (2010). Ifs and oughts. Journal of Philosophy, 107(3), 115–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (1991). Modality. In A. von Stechow & D. Wunderlich (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of contemporary research (pp. 639–650). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn, P. (2005). Context dependence, disagreement, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 28(6), 643–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • López de Sa, D. (2008). Presuppositions of commonality: An indexical relativist account of disagreement. In M. García-Carpintero & M. Kölbel (Eds.), Relative truth (pp. 297–310). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • López de Sa, D. (2015). Expressing disagreement: A presuppositional indexical contextualist relativist account. Erkenntnis, 80(1), 153–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2005a). The assessment sensitivity of knowledge attributions. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 1, pp. 197–234). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2005b). Making sense of relative truth. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 105(3), 321–8211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2009). Nonindexical contextualism. Synthese, 166(2), 231–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2011). Epistemic modals are assessment-sensitive. In B. Weatherson & A. Egan (Eds.), Epistemic modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2014). Assessment sensitivity: Relative truth and its applications. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Macià, J. (2002). Presuposición y significado expresivo. Theoria, 17(3), 499–513.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marques, T. (2014). Relative correctness. Philosophical Studies, 167(2), 361–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marques, T. (2015). Disagreeing in Context. Frontiers in Psychology, 6(257). doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00257.

  • Marques, T., & García-Carpintero, M. (2014). Disagreement about taste: commonality presuppositions and coordination. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92(4), 701–723.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pagin, P. (2015). Assertion. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab—Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1993). The problem of the essential indexical: And other essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plunkett, D., & Sundell, T. (2013). Disagreement and the semantics of normative and evaluative terms. Philosophers’ Imprint, 13(23), 1–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potts, C. (2005). The logic of conventional implicatures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2007). Perspectival thought: A plea for (moderate) relativism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richard, M. (2008). When truth gives out. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, J., & Schroeder, M. (2013). Reversibility or disagreement. Mind, 122(485), 43–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, J. (2012). Just go ahead and lie. Analysis, 72(1), 3–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, P. (2007). Expressive presuppositions. Theoretical Linguistics, 33(2), 237–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stephenson, T. (2007). Judge dependence, epistemic modals, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30(4), 487–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stojanovic, I. (2007). Talking about taste: Disagreement, implicit arguments, and relative truth. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30(6), 691–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sundell, T. (2011). Disagreements about taste. Philosophical Studies, 155(2), 267–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. S. (2008). CIA leaks. Philosophical Review, 117(1), 77–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1996). Knowing and asserting. Philosophical Review, 105(4), 489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work was presented at the conference of the European Society for Philosophy and Psychology in Granada, August 2013, the 2nd PLM Conference in Budapest, September 2013, the LanCog seminar in Lisbon, November 2013, and the LOGOS seminar in Barcelona, February 2014. I am grateful to the audiences at those events for discussion of this material, and in particular to Robyn Carston, Manuel García-Carpintero, Kathrin Glüer-Pagin, Joshua Knobe, Dan López de Sa, Josep Macià, Peter Pagin, François Recanati, Sven Rosenkranz, Pedro Santos, Isidora Stojanovic, Elia Zardini and Dan Zeman, and to two anonymous reviewers for this journal. This work was supported by FP7 Marie Curie Action, Intra-European Fellowship. Grant Agreement Number: PIEF-GA-2012-622114; Grup de Recerca Consolidat en Filosofia del Dret, 2014 SGR 626, funded by AGAUR de la Generalitat de Catalunya; About Ourselves, FFI2013-47948-P; and Online Companion to Problems of Analytic Philosophy, FCT Project PTDC/FIL-FIL/121209/20.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Teresa Marques.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Marques, T. Retractions. Synthese 195, 3335–3359 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0852-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0852-8

Keywords

Navigation