Skip to main content
Log in

Criteria for indefeasible knowledge: John Mcdowell and ‘epistemological disjunctivism’

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Duncan Pritchard has recently defended a view he calls ‘epistemological disjunctivism’, largely inspired by John McDowell. I argue that Pritchard is right to associate the view with McDowell, and that McDowell’s ‘inference-blocking’ argument against the sceptic succeeds only if epistemological disjunctivism is accepted. However, Pritchard also recognises that epistemological disjunctivism appears to conflict with our belief that genuine and illusory experiences are indistinguishable (the ‘distinguishability problem’). Since the indistinguishability of experiences is the antecedent in the inference McDowell intends to block, I suggest that his argument rests on an inconsistent set of premises. In support of this, I show that Pritchard’s response to the distinguishability problem is incompatible with the conclusion of the ‘inference-blocking’ argument, and that the response available in McDowell’s work relies on a mistaken conception of fallibility. Either McDowell must deny the sceptic’s premise that perceptual experiences are indistinguishable, or he must give up his conclusion that perceptual warrant can be indefeasible.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, Greco (2004).

  2. For the difference between these two statements of McDowell’s view, see (2009).

  3. For an earlier version of this claim, see (1982).

  4. Williamson (2000, p. 266) has shown that indefeasibility does not logically entail factiveness. However, since his counterexamples are situations where a false belief can never be discovered, one could hardly exploit them to thwart the sceptic’s conclusion. To all intents and purposes, McDowell’s indefeasibility claim requires that perceptual warrant is factive.

  5. For an intriguing challenge to this last claim, see Noe (2006) and Phillips (2011).

  6. For the transition from legal to philosophical usage, see Macagno and Walton (2014, p. 82).

  7. This example is drawn directly from Williamson (2000, p. 265).

  8. See Donnellan (1966).

  9. This adaptation of the example is based on Pritchard (2012, p. 98).

  10. As Wittgenstein asks in On Certainty: ‘Doesn’t one need grounds for doubt? (1969, §122).

  11. For an example, see Descartes (1637/1985, p. 127).

  12. See also (2011, p. 34).

  13. Oxford English Dictionary Online, accessed 4 March 2014. The Dictionary also contains an archaic sense: ‘liable to mislead’. More on this below.

  14. By contrast, the following reply would be ungrammatical: ‘I don’t mean there’s something he’s fallible about; he’s just fallible.’

  15. See McDowell (2011, pp. 41–42).

  16. Oxford English Dictionary Online, accessed 4 March 2014.

  17. Oxford English Dictionary Online, accessed 4 March 2014. (My emphasis.)

References

  • Burge, T. (2005). Disjunctivism and perceptual psychology. Philosophical Topics, 33(1), 1–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2011). Disjunctivism again. Philosophical Explorations: An International Journal for the Philosophy of Mind and Action, 14(1), 43–80.

  • Dancy, J. (1995). Arguments from illusion. The Philosophical Quarterly, 45(181), 421–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1637). Discourse on the method, (J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff & D. Murdoch, Trans. 1985). The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (Vol. 1). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Donnellan, K. (1966). Reference and definite descriptions. The Philosophical Review, 75(3), 281–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2004). Externalism and skepticism. In R. Schantz (Ed.), The externalist challenge (pp. 53–64). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macagno, F., & Walton, D. (2014). Emotive language in argumentation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1982). Criteria, defeasibility, and knowledge. In Proceedings of the British Academy 68 (pp. 455–479). (Reprinted from Meaning, knowledge, and reality, by J. McDowell, Ed., Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).

  • McDowell, J. (1986). Singular thought and the extent of inner space. In P. Pettit & J. McDowell (Eds.), Subject, thought, and context, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Reprinted from Meaning, knowledge, and reality, by J. McDowell, Ed., Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • McDowell, J. (1995). Knowledge and the internal. In Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55/4 (pp. 877–893). (Reprinted from Meaning, knowledge, and reality, by J. McDowell, Ed., 1998, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2008). The disjunctive conception of experience as material for a transcendental argument. In A. Haddock & F. Macpherson (Eds.), Perception, action, knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2009). Avoiding the myth of the given. In J. Lindgaard, John McDowell (Ed.), Experience, norm, and nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Reprinted from Having the world in view, by J. McDowell, Ed., 2009, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • McDowell, J. (2010). Tyler Burge on disjunctivism. Philosophical Explorations: An International Journal for the Philosophy of Mind and Action, 13(3), 243–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2011). Perception as a capacity for knowledge. Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neta, R., & Pritchard, D. (2007). McDowell and the new evil genius. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74(2), 381–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noe, A. (2006). Experience of the world in time. Analysis, 66(1), 26–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, I. (2011). Perception and iconic memory: What Sperling doesn’t show. Mind & Language, 29(4), 381–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2007). How to be a neo-Moorean. In S. Goldberg (Ed.), Internalism and Externalism in Semantics and Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2008). McDowellian neo-Mooreanism. In A. Haddock & F. Macpherson (Eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, action, knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2009). Wright contra McDowell on perceptual knowledge and scepticism. Synthese, 171(3), 467–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2011). Epistemological disjunctivism and the basis problem. Philosophical Issues, 21(1), 434–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2012). Epistemological disjunctivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rödl, S. (2007). Self-consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On certainty. In G. E. M. Anscombe & G. H. von Wright (Eds.). Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Wright, C. (2002). (Anti-)sceptics simple and subtle: G.E. Moore and John McDowell. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65(2), 330–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (2008). Comment on John McDowell’s the disjunctive conception of experience as material for a transcendental argument. In A. Haddock & F. Macpherson (Eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, action, knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Max de Gaynesford, Andrew Khoury, and James Stazicker for comments on previous drafts, to Asya Passinsky for discussion, and to audiences at Reading University, LSE, and the Joint Session of the Aristotelian Society and the Mind Association 2013.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Dennis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dennis, P. Criteria for indefeasible knowledge: John Mcdowell and ‘epistemological disjunctivism’. Synthese 191, 4099–4113 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0516-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0516-0

Keywords

Navigation