Skip to main content
Log in

Mixed equilibriums in a three-candidate spatial model with candidate valence

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We study a spatial model of electoral competition among three office-motivated candidates of unequal valence (one advantaged and two equally disadvantaged candidates) under majority rule assuming that candidates are uncertain about the voters’ policy preferences and that the policy space consists of three alternatives (one at each extreme of the linear policy spectrum and one in the center) and we characterize mixed strategy Nash equilibriums of the game. Counterintuitively, we show that (a) when uncertainty about voters’ preferences is high, the advantaged candidate might choose in equilibrium a more extremist strategy than the disadvantaged candidates and that (b) when uncertainty about voters’ preferences is low, there exist equilibriums in which one of the disadvantaged candidates has a larger probability of election than the disadvantaged candidate of the equivalent two-candidate (one advantaged and one disadvantaged candidate) case.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Valence politics has received a lot of attention in recent economics and political science literatures. Theoretical results, mainly about the two-candidate case, are offered by Stokes (1963), Groseclose (2001), Adams (1999), Ansolabehere and Snyder (2000), Erikson and Palfrey (2000), Dix and Santore (2002), Aragonès and Palfrey (2002), Herrera et al. (2008), Schofield (2007), Carillo and Castanheira (2008), Zakharov (2009), Ashworth and Bueno de Mesquita (2009), Serra (2010), Hummel (2010), Aragonès and Xefteris (2012) and Xefteris (2012). Empirical results can be found in Erikson and Palfrey (2000), Clarke et al. (2005), Schofield (2007) and Schofield and Zackharov (2010).

  2. The reason why we make assumptions only about the median voter’s ideal policy is the following. In settings where (i) candidates have unequal valence, (ii) the policy space is unidimensional, (iii) voter’s preferences on the policy dimension are single-peaked (for continuous policy spaces the extra assumption of concavity of voters’ utility functions is required) and (iv) majority rule is applied to determine the winner we know from Groseclose (2007) that a Condorcet winning candidate exists and she/he is the candidate that the median voter ranks first. Potthoff and Munger (2005) provide, essentially, the same formal result in a different context (they show that when three candidates try to maximize vote share under plurality rule and voter uncertainty about candidates platforms is present, Condorcet-cycles are ruled out).

  3. Notice that for our model the notion of “minimal advantage” implies that the degree of concavity of the utility functions should not affect the results. The reason is that a non-policy advantage is minimal if and only if it affects a voter’s choice when this voter is indifferent between the policy proposal of the advantaged candidate and the policy proposal of a disadvantaged candidate. This can only happen (i) when the advantaged candidate offers the same policy as a disadvantage candidate independently of the location of the voter or (ii) when the voter is in the central location and the advantaged candidate is at one extreme and the disadvantaged candidate(s) is (are) at the other extreme. If we assumed more general concave functions, we would only increase the disutility of a voter who is at one extreme from a policy outcome at the other extreme from 1 to β>1. This would, obviously, not affect the payoff matrix of the game and, thereafter, the equilibrium behavior of all players in any way.

  4. Notice that the uniqueness of a type-symmetric equilibrium is not obvious in three-person games with two identical players. Consider a voting game with three players {1,2,3} and two alternatives {A,B} under majority rule and compulsory voting, such that the first player strictly prefers A to B and the other two players strictly prefer B to A. In that case we have a continuum of type-symmetric equilibria \(\hat{\sigma}^{1}=(q,1-q)\), \(\hat{\sigma}^{2}=(0,1)\) and \(\hat{\sigma}^{3}=(0,1)\) such that q∈[0,1].

  5. Valence in this model is considered to be a candidate’s characteristic equally valued by all voters (as in Groseclose 2001; Aragonès and Palfrey 2002 and others). An alternative specification would be that valence is voter-specific in the sense that each candidate is considered to be the best by different fractions of the society. In our three-candidate and three-policy setup we could rename our candidates to L, C, and R and assume that L is the best candidate for the leftist voters, C is the best candidate for the centrist voters and R is the best candidate for the rightist voters. If, for example, L and C choose the leftist policy, then all leftist voters prefer L to C, all centrist voters prefer C to L and all rightist voters are indifferent between them (or prefer C to L). In this case we always have a pure strategy equilibrium such that L offers the leftist platform, C offers the centrist platform and R offers the rightist platform provided that valence is still minimal.

  6. Proofs of Propositions 2, 3, 4, 5 can be found in the Appendix.

  7. In national elections the communist party received 10.9 %, the socialist party 48.1 % and the right-wing party 35.9 % while in the European parliamentary elections the communist party received 12.8 %, the socialist party 40.1 % and the right-wing party 31.3 %.

References

  • Adams, J. (1999). Policy divergence in multicandidate probabilistic spatial voting. Public Choice, 100, 103–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ansolabehere, S., & Snyder, J. M. Jr. (2000). Valence politics and equilibrium in spatial election models. Public Choice, 103, 327–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aragonès, E., & Palfrey, T. (2002). Mixed strategy equilibrium in a Downsian model with a favored candidate. Journal of Economic Theory, 103, 131–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aragonès, E., & Palfrey, T. R. (2004). The effect of candidate quality on electoral equilibrium: an experimental study. American Political Science Review, 98, 77–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aragonès, E., & Xefteris, D. (2012). Candidate quality in a Downsian model with a continuous policy space. Games and Economic Behavior, 75(2), 464–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashworth, S., & Bueno de Mesquita, E. (2009). Elections with platform and valence competition. Games and Economic Behavior, 67, 191–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carillo, J. D., & Castanheria, M. (2008). Information and strategic political polarisation. Economic Journal, 118, 845–874.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, H., Sanders, D., Stewart, M., & Whiteley, P. (2005). Political choice in Britain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dix, M., & Santore, R. (2002). Candidate ability and platform choice. Economics Letters, 76, 189–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erikson, R. S., & Palfrey, T. R. (2000). Equilibria in campaign spending games: theory and data. American Political Science Review, 94, 595–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evrenk, H. (2009). Three-candidate competition when candidates have valence: the base case. Social Choice and Welfare, 32, 157–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evrenk, H., & Kha, D. (2010). Three-candidate spatial competition when candidates have valence: stochastic voting. Public Choice, 147, 421–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Featherstone, K. (1990). The ‘party-state’ in Greece and the fall of Papandreou. West European Politics, 13(1), 101–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • GAMBIT software, http://www.gambit-project.org, 2011.

  • Groseclose, T. (2001). A model of candidate location when one candidate has a valence advantage. American Journal of Political Science, 45(October), 862–886.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groseclose, T. (2007). One and a half dimensional preferences and majority rule. Social Choice and Welfare, 28, 321–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herrera, H., Levine, D., & Martinelli, C. (2008). Policy platforms, campaign spending and voter participation. Journal of Public Economics, 92, 501–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hummel, P. (2010). On the nature of equilibriums in a Downsian model with candidate valence. Games and Economic Behavior, 70(2), 425–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey, R. D., & Ordeshook, P. C. (1976). Symmetric spatial games without majority rule equilibriums. American Political Science Review, 70, 1172–1184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, M. J., & Pitchik, C. (1986). The nature of equilibrium in a location model. International Economic Review, 27, 223–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potthoff, R., & Munger, M. (2005). Voter uncertainty can produce preferences with more than one peak, but not preference cycles. The Journal of Politics, 67, 429–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Serra, G. (2010). Polarization of what? A model of elections with endogenous valence. Journal of Politics, 722, 426–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, D. E. (1963). Spatial models of party competition. American Political Science Review, 57, 368–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, N. J. (2003). Valence competition in the spatial stochastic model. The Journal of Theoretical Politics, 154, 371–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, N. J. (2007). The mean voter theorem: necessary and sufficient conditions for convergent equilibrium. The Review of Economic Studies, 74, 965–980.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, N. J., & Zakharov, A. V. (2010). A stochastic model of 2007 Russian Duma election. Public Choice, 142(1–2), 177–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Synaspismos. 1989. Programme. Party document.

  • Tullock, G. (1967). Towards a mathematics of politics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verney, S. (2011). An exceptional case? Party and popular Euroskepticism in Greece, 1959–2009. South European Society and Politics, 16(01), 51–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Xefteris, D. (2012). Mixed strategy equilibrium in a Downsian model with a favored candidate: a comment. Journal of Economic Theory, 147(1), 393–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zakharov, A. V. (2009). A model of candidate location with endogenous valence. Public Choice, 138, 347–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Georg Vanberg and two anonymous referees for excellent suggestions and comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dimitrios Xefteris.

Appendix: Proofs

Appendix: Proofs

Proof (Proposition 2)

We will prove the proposition by contradiction. Assume that \(\hat{\sigma} _{1}^{D_{1}}=\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{2}}>\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{1}}=\hat{\sigma} _{3}^{D_{2}}\). Then, \(\varPi_{A}(x_{3},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma} ^{D_{2}})=r+(1-2r)(1-\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{1}}-\hat{\sigma} _{3}^{D_{1}})^{2}+r(\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{1}})^{2}\) and \(\varPi_{A}(x_{1},\hat{ \sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=r+(1-2r)(1-\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{1}}- \hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{1}})^{2}+r(\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{1}})^{2}\). It is obvious that \(\varPi_{A}(x_{3},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})<\varPi_{A}(x_{1},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\) and therefore that \(\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{A}\) must be equal to zero. Notice that \(\hat{\sigma} _{1}^{A}\) must be positive, because from the arguments in support of Proposition 1 it is made clear that no equilibrium exists in which A uses a pure strategy. Then we have that \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{1},\hat{ \sigma}^{D_{2}})=r(1-\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{A})(1-\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{2}}+\frac{ \hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{2}}}{2})=r(1-\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{A})(1-\frac{\hat{\sigma} _{1}^{D_{2}}}{2})\) and \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{3},\hat{\sigma} ^{D_{2}})=r(1-\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{2}}+\frac{\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{2}}}{2} )=r(1-\frac{\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{2}}}{2})\), which implies that \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{1},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})<\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{3},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\); a disadvantaged player cannot place a positive probability on x 1. The equivalent occurs if we assume that \(\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{1}}=\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{2}}<\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{1}}=\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{2}}\). Therefore, in a type-symmetric equilibrium the disadvantaged candidates must mix symmetrically about the center of the policy space. To conclude the proof we must investigate the case in which the advantaged player mixes asymmetrically about the center of the policy space (\(\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{A}\neq \hat{\sigma}_{3}^{A}\)). Since we have proved that in a type-symmetric equilibrium we must have \(\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{1}}=\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{2}}=\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{1}}=\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{2}}\), then it follows that if \(\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{A}>\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{A}\) (the equivalent occurs if we assume \(\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{A}<\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{A}\)) we have \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{1},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=r(1-\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{A})(1-\frac{\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{2}}}{2})<\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{3},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=r(1-\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{A})(1-\frac{\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{2}}}{2})\) and, therefore, a disadvantaged player cannot place positive probability on x 1. This contradicts the fact that in a type-symmetric equilibrium we must have \(\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{1}}=\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{2}}=\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{1}}=\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{2}}\) and therefore it should also be the case that in a type-symmetric equilibrium \(\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{A}\) must be equal to \(\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{A}\). □

Proof (Proposition 3)

By Proposition 2 we have that \(\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{A}=\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{A}\) and \(\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{1}}=\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{2}}=\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{1}}=\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{2}}\) in every type-symmetric equilibrium. Therefore, since we are looking for an equilibrium in which candidates mix symmetrically about the center of the policy space we can impose: \(\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{1}}=\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{1}}=\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{D_{2}}=\hat{\sigma}_{3}^{D_{2}}=\hat{s}\). We need to check for the values of \(\hat{\sigma }_{1}^{A}\) and \(\hat{s}\) at which we get \(\varPi_{A}(x_{1},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=\varPi_{A}(x_{2},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\) and \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{1},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{2},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\) (due to the symmetry of the problem if these equalities hold then \(\varPi_{A}(x_{3},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=\varPi_{A}(x_{2},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\), \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{3},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})= \varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{2},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\), \(\varPi_{D_{2}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},x_{1})= \varPi_{D_{2}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},x_{2})\) and \(\varPi_{D_{2}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},x_{3})=\varPi_{D_{2}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},x_{2})\) should hold as well). We know that \(\varPi_{A}(x_{1},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=r+(1-2r)(4\hat{s}^{2})+r\hat{s}^{2}\) and that \(\varPi_{A}(x_{2},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=(1-2r)+2r(1-\hat{s})^{2}\) and therefore \(\varPi_{A}(x_{1},\hat{\sigma }^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=\varPi_{A}(x_{2},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\) holds if and only if

Equivalently, \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{1},\hat{\sigma} ^{D_{2}})=r((1-\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{A})(1-\hat{s}+\frac{\hat{s}}{2}))\) and \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{1},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=(1-2r)(2\hat{\sigma} _{1}^{A}(2\hat{s}+\frac{1-2\hat{s}}{2}))+2r(\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{A}(\hat{s}+ \frac{1-2\hat{s}}{2}))\), and therefore \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{1}, \hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{2}, \hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\) holds if and only if

$$\hat{\sigma}_{1}^{A}= \frac{r\hat{s}-2r}{9r\hat{s}-4\hat{s}-2}=\frac{rf(r)-2r}{9rf(r)-4f(r)-2}. $$

Therefore, the presented equilibrium is the unique type-symmetric equilibrium of our game. □

Proof (Proposition 4)

We will provide a proof for (i). It is effortless to see that the proofs for (ii), (iii) and (iv) are equivalent. We have to demonstrate that (a) \(\varPi_{A}(x_{1},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\leq \varPi_{A}(x_{2}, \hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=\varPi_{A}(x_{3},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\), that (b) \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{1},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\leq \varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{2},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{3},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\), that (c) \(\varPi_{D_{2}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},x_{1})\geq \max \{\varPi_{D_{2}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},x_{2}), \varPi_{D_{2}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},x_{3})\}\) and that (d) (a), (b) and (c) all hold simultaneously only if \(r\in (0,\frac{1}{3}]\). Starting with (a) we compute \(\varPi_{A}(x_{1},\hat{ \sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=r+(1-2r)\frac{1-2r}{1-r}\), \(\varPi_{A}(x_{2},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=(1-2r)+r\frac{r}{1-r}\) and \(\varPi_{A}(x_{3},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=r+(1-2r)\frac{1-2r}{1-r}\) and we observe that \(\varPi_{A}(x_{1},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=\varPi_{A}(x_{2},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=\varPi_{A}(x_{3},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\) holds for any r. That is, \(\hat{\sigma}^{A}\) is a best response to \(\{\hat{\sigma }^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}}\}\). We proceed to point (b). We compute \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{1},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=\frac{r}{2}\), \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{2},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}}) =(1-2r)\frac{r}{1-r}\) and \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{3},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=r\frac{1-2r}{1-r}\) and we observe that \(\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{1},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\leq \varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{2},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})=\varPi_{D_{1}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},x_{3},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\) holds for any \(r\in (0,\frac{1}{3}]\); that is, \(\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}}\) is a best response to \(\{\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}}\}\) for any \(r\in (0,\frac{1}{3}]\) (this proves point (d)). Finally we go to point (c) and we compute \(\varPi_{D_{2}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},x_{1})=r\), \(\varPi_{D_{2}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},x_{2})=\frac{r}{1-r}(1-r)(\frac{1-2r}{1-r}+\frac{1}{2}\frac{r}{1-r})\) and \(\varPi_{D_{2}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},x_{3})=\frac{1-2r}{1-r}r(\frac{r}{1-r}+\frac{1}{2}\frac{1-2r}{1-r})\) and we observe that \(\varPi_{D_{2}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},x_{1})\geq \max \{\varPi_{D_{2}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},x_{2}), \varPi_{D_{2}}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},x_{3})\}\) holds for any r; that is, \(\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}}\) is a best response to \(\{\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}}\}\) for any r. □

Proof (Proposition 5)

We first prove part (a) of this proposition. Consider a type-symmetric equilibrium \(\{\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}}\}\) (that is, \(\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}}=\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}}=\hat{\sigma}\)). Now let us create a parallel game in which instead of A we have a player B (we also rank her/him in first place) who is identical to the other two disadvantaged candidates. If all players had the same valence and they were using the same mixed strategy \(\hat{\sigma}\) then they would obviously enjoy the same election probability (\(\frac{1}{3}\)). Observe that \(\varPi_{A}(\hat{\sigma},\hat{\sigma},\hat{\sigma})>\varPi_{B}(\hat{\sigma},\hat{\sigma}, \hat{\sigma})=\frac{1}{3}\), as for any possible platform realization in our game, we have that A should receive a payoff at least as large as B in the parallel game, and for some platform realizations (for the case in which all candidates end up offering the same policy to the voters, for example) A should receive a payoff strictly larger than the payoff of B in the parallel game. That is, \(\varPi_{A}(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\geq \varPi_{A}(\hat{\sigma},\hat{\sigma},\hat{\sigma})>\frac{1}{3}\).

As far as part (b) is concerned notice that for \([\frac{1}{3}+\frac{1}{n-1}, \frac{2}{3}-\frac{1}{n-1}]\) to be well defined and non-degenerate we must have \(\frac{1}{3}+\frac{1}{n-1}<\frac{2}{3}-\frac{1}{n-1}\Longrightarrow n>7\). Assume that for some equilibrium we have \([\frac{1}{3}+\frac{1}{n-1}, \frac{2}{3}-\frac{1}{n-1}]\varsubsetneq S(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\). Since both sets are convex, this implies that either \(\frac{1}{3}+\frac{1}{n-1}<z\) for any \(z\in S(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\) or \(\frac{2}{3}-\frac{1}{n-1}>z\) for any \(z\in S(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\), or both. Without loss of generality assume that \(\frac{1}{3}+\frac{1}{n-1}<z\) for any \(z\in S(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\) holds. This implies that the policy x k such that \(x_{k}\notin S(\hat{ \sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\) and \(x_{k+1}\in S( \hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\) satisfies \(x_{k}>\frac{1}{3}\). In any equilibrium there exists at least one candidate who receives a payoff that does not exceed \(\frac{1}{3}\). If this candidate deviates to x k and since the probability that some other candidate announces a policy identical or to the left of x k is zero then she/he will receive a payoff larger than \(\frac{1}{3}\). Therefore, in any equilibrium of the game \([\frac{1}{3}+\frac{1}{n-1},\frac{2}{3}-\frac{1}{n-1}] \subseteq S(\hat{\sigma}^{A},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{1}},\hat{\sigma}^{D_{2}})\). □

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Xefteris, D. Mixed equilibriums in a three-candidate spatial model with candidate valence. Public Choice 158, 101–120 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-012-9948-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-012-9948-6

Keywords

Navigation