Skip to main content
Log in

Identity and quantification

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is a philosophical commonplace that quantification involves, invokes, or presupposes, the relation of identity. There seem to be two major sources for this belief: (1) the conviction that identity is implicated in the phenomenon of bound variable recurrence within the scope of a quantifier; (2) memories of Quine’s insistence that quantification requires absolute identity for the values of variables. With respect to (1), I show that the only extant argument for a dependence of variable recurrence on identity, due to John Hawthorne, fails. I further show that the function of variable recurrence is not subsumed under that of identity, so that a dependence of the former on the latter, if any, would have to be of a rather indirect nature. With respect to (2), I argue that the relevant passage in Quine fails to establish a connection between quantification and the identity relation, and indeed wasn’t intended by Quine to do so.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This was first pointed out, I believe, by Humberstone and Townsend (1994: 255), who provide examples similar to those used below.

  2. Alexis Burgess (forthcoming) points out that it is also unclear why we should feel compelled to cash out the semantic difference between (1) and (2) in terms of their implicational relationships to (4). As Burgess notes, (1), but not (2), follows from the premises Fa and Gb. This seems a perfectly natural explanation of the semantic difference between (1) and (2), in which the identity relation, however, does not figure at all.

  3. To expand a bit: PFL has a finite lexicon and a compositional semantics, as can be gleaned from Appendix 2. There is thus no reason why PFL should not be a learnable language, and anyone brought up to learn to speak PFL would naturally formulate PFL’s metalanguage in, well, PFL.

  4. See Burgess (2005: 53–54) for a suggestion on how to pronounce PFL-predicates; in particular, note that the \(\mathsf {Ref}\) functor plays the role of the prefix self that turns a two-place predicate such as destroys into the one-place predicate self-destructs, rather than the role of an is of identity.

  5. Indeed, the collection of all finite numerical quantifiers, say of the form there are at least n objects such that, is equivalent, over first-order logic without identity, to identity. See Wehmeier (2008: 368) for a proof.

  6. I am indebted to Lloyd Humberstone (p.c.) for suggesting this line of argument.

  7. In terms of predicate functor logic, this means that PFL without the functor \(\mathsf {Ref}\) but with the identity predicate I is strictly less expressive than full PFL.

  8. It follows from results by Monk (1965) that, in first-order languages with identity, we can dispense with variable recurrence within atomic formulas, that is, the fragment of such a language in which primitive predicates must be followed by strings of mutually distinct variables is equi-expressive with the full language. By way of example, consider the formula \(\exists x\, Rxx\), which is logically equivalent to \(\exists x\,\exists y (Rxy \wedge x=y)\). Of course this paraphrase depends heavily on variable recurrence across atomic formulas. Thanks to Lloyd Humberstone for bringing this result of Monk’s to my attention.

References

  • Burgess, A. (forthcoming ). The things we do with identity. Mind.

  • Burgess, J. (2005). Being explained away. Harvard Review of Philosophy, 13(2), 41–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. T. (1962). Reference and generality. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2003). Identity. In M. J. Loux & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 99–130). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone, L., & Townsend, A. (1994). Co-instantiation and identity. Philosophical Studies, 74(2), 243–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (2000). Logical properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Monk, D. (1965). Substitutionless predicate logic with identity. Archiv für mathematische Logik und Grundlagenforschung, 7(3–4), 102–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noonan, H., & Curtis, B. (2014). Identity. In Edward N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/identity/.

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Variables explained away. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 104(3), 343–347.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1961). Reply to Professor Marcus. Synthese, 13(4), 323–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1964). Review of P.T. Geach, Reference and generality. Philosophical Review, 73(1), 100–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wehmeier, K. F. (2008). Wittgensteinian Tableaux, identity, and co-denotation. Erkenntnis, 69, 363–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wehmeier, K. F. (2012). How to live without identity—and why. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(4), 761–777.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Many thanks to Alexis Burgess, Lloyd Humberstone, and Richard Pettigrew for extended discussions on the content of this paper. This material has been presented at the workshop The Logic, Metaphysics, and Semantics of Identity at UC Irvine in October 2014, in André Fuhrmann’s Philosophical Colloquium at Goethe University Frankfurt, Germany, in November 2014, and in the Logic Seminar of UC Irvine’s Center for the Advancement of Logic, its Philosophy, History, and Applications (C-ALPHA) in March 2016. Thanks to all the participants at these occasions, particularly Alexis Burgess, André Fuhrmann, and Rob Trueman. I am grateful, too, to an anonymous referee for this journal who provided valuable advice. Finally I would like to thank Ulrich Pardey for many illuminating conversations about identity over the years.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kai F. Wehmeier.

Appendices

Appendix 1

Here we establish the result that first-order logic with identity but without variable recurrence within the scope of a quantifier is strictly less expressive than full first-order logic with identity.

To see this, consider a first-order language \(\mathcal {L}\) with identity whose signature is given by two unary predicate symbols F and G. The recurrence-free \(\mathcal {L}\)-formulas can be defined as follows: Whenever x and y are distinct variables, Fx, Gx, and \(x=y\) are recurrence-free \(\mathcal {L}\)-formulas; whenever \(\phi \) is a recurrence-free \(\mathcal {L}\)-formula, so is \(\lnot \phi \); whenever \(\phi \) and \(\psi \) are recurrence-free \(\mathcal {L}\)-formulas such that no variable occurs free in both \(\phi \) and \(\psi \), \((\phi \wedge \psi )\) is a recurrence-free \(\mathcal {L}\)-formula; and whenever x is any variable and \(\phi \) a recurrence-free \(\mathcal {L}\)-formula, \(\exists x\phi \) is a recurrence-free \(\mathcal {L}\)-formula.

Now let \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\) be the model for \(\mathcal {L}\) whose domain is given by the set \(M = \{ 0,1\}\) and that interprets both F and G as the singleton set \(\{ 0\}\). Let \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\) be the model for \(\mathcal {L}\) whose domain is also the set M and that interprets F as \(\{ 0\}\) (just like \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\)), but interprets G as \(\{ 1\}\). Clearly \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\) and \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\) can be distinguished by means of the non-recurrence-free \(\mathcal {L}\)-sentence \(\exists x\, (Fx \wedge Gx)\), i.e. (2) in the main text, which is true in \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\) but false in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\). However, as we will now prove, \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\) and \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\) make exactly the same recurrence-free \(\mathcal {L}\)-sentences true. It follows that the expressive power of first-order logic with identity is indeed diminished by disallowing variable recurrence. Hence the identity relation cannot subsume the semantic function of variable recurrence.

To obtain the desired result, we must prove a slightly more general fact:

Lemma

For every recurrence-free \(\mathcal {L}\)-formula \(\phi \) there is a set \(A_\phi \) included in the set \(\mathsf {FV}(\phi )\) of variables occurring free in \(\phi \) such that, for all variable assignments \(\sigma \) in the set M, \(\sigma \) satisfies \(\phi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\) if and only if \(\delta ^\phi _\sigma \) satisfies \(\phi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\), where \(\delta ^\phi _\sigma \) is the variable assignment that maps a variable x to \(\sigma (x)\) if \(x\not \in A_\phi \), but to \(1-\sigma (x)\) if \(x\in A_\phi \).

The lemma can be proved by induction on the recurrence-free formula \(\phi \). If \(\phi \) is atomic, it is of one of the forms Fx, Gx, and \(x=y\). We let \(A_{Fx}\) and \(A_{x=y}\) be the empty set, so that \(\delta ^{Fx}_\sigma = \delta ^{x=y}_\sigma = \sigma \) for every assignment \(\sigma \). This has the desired result, since the interpretation of F is the same in \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\) and \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\), and likewise for \(=\). For the remaining atomic case, we let \(A_{Gx}\) be \(\{ x\}\), so that \(\delta ^{Gx}_\sigma (x) = 1-\sigma (x)\) for every assignment \(\sigma \). Since i is in the interpretation of G in \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\) if and only if \(1-i\) is in the interpretation of G in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\), this too has the desired result.

If \(\phi \) is compound, it is of one of the forms \(\lnot \psi \), \(\exists x\psi \), and \((\psi \wedge \theta )\). We let \(A_{\lnot \psi }\) be \(A_\psi \), so that \(\delta ^{\lnot \psi }_\sigma \) is \(\delta ^\psi _\sigma \). The induction hypothesis then immediately gives the desired result.

Let \(A_{\exists x\psi }\) be \(A_\psi {\setminus } \{ x\}\), so that, for \(y\in \mathsf {FV}(\exists x\psi )\), \(\delta ^{\exists x\psi }_\sigma (y)\) is \(\delta ^{\psi }_\sigma (y)\). For assignments \(\tau \) and elements \(i\in M\), let us write \(\tau \{ x:= i\}\) for the x-variant of \(\tau \) that maps x to i. We note that the existence of an \(i\in M\) such that \(\delta ^\psi _{\sigma \{ x:= i\}}\) satisfies \(\psi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\) is equivalent to the existence of a \(j\in M\) such that \(\delta ^\psi _\sigma \{ x:= j\}\) satisfies \(\psi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\). This is because, if \(x\not \in A_\psi \), \(\delta ^\psi _{\sigma \{ x:= i\}}\) is \(\delta ^\psi _\sigma \{ x:= i\}\) for each \(i\in M\), while if \(x\in A_\psi \), \(\delta ^\psi _{\sigma \{ x:= i\}}\) is \(\delta ^\psi _\sigma \{ x:= 1-i\}\). Further, for any \(j\in M\), \(\delta ^\psi _\sigma \{ x:= j\}\) is the same function as \(\delta ^{\exists x\psi }_\sigma \{ x:= j\}\), since \(\delta ^\psi _\sigma \) and \(\delta ^{\exists x\psi }_\sigma \) differ at most in what they assign to x. With these observations in place, we see that \(\sigma \) satisfies \(\exists x\,\psi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\) if and only if for some \(i\in M\), \(\sigma \{ x:= i\}\) satisfies \(\psi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\), if and only if (by induction hypothesis) for some \(i\in M\), \(\delta ^\psi _{\sigma \{ x:= i\}}\) satisfies \(\psi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\), if and only if for some \(j\in M\), \(\delta ^\psi _\sigma \{ x:= j\}\) satisfies \(\psi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\), if and only if for some \(j\in M\), \(\delta ^{\exists x\psi }_\sigma \{ x:= j\}\) satisfies \(\psi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\), if and only if \(\delta ^{\exists x\psi }_\sigma \) satisfies \(\exists x\, \psi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\), as desired.

Finally, let \(A_{(\psi \wedge \theta )}\) be \(A_\psi \cup A_\theta \). We note that \(\delta ^\psi _\sigma \) and \(\delta ^{(\psi \wedge \theta )}_\sigma \) agree on \(\mathsf {FV}(\psi )\), and \(\delta ^\theta _\sigma \) and \(\delta ^{(\psi \wedge \theta )}_\sigma \) agree on \(\mathsf {FV}(\theta )\). To see the former, observe that for every \(x\in \mathsf {FV}(\psi )\), \(x\in A_\psi \cup A_\theta \) if and only if \(x\in A_\psi \), since \((\psi \wedge \theta )\) is recurrence-free, so that \(\psi \) and \(\theta \) do not share any free variables, and x cannot be in \(A_\theta \subseteq \mathsf {FV}(\theta )\). The corresponding claim for \(\theta \) follows analogously. We then have that \(\sigma \) satisfies \((\psi \wedge \theta )\) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\) if and only if \(\sigma \) satisfies both \(\psi \) and \(\theta \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\), if and only if (by induction hypothesis) \(\delta ^\psi _\sigma \) satisfies \(\psi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\) and \(\delta ^\theta _\sigma \) satisfies \(\theta \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\). By the fact just observed, and since satisfaction depends only upon what is assigned to the variables actually occurring free in a formula, this is the case if and only if \(\delta ^{(\psi \wedge \theta )}_\sigma \) satisfies \(\psi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\) and \(\delta ^{(\psi \wedge \theta )}_\sigma \) satisfies \(\theta \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\), i.e. if and only if \(\delta ^{(\psi \wedge \theta )}_\sigma \) satisfies \((\psi \wedge \theta )\) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\), as desired. This completes the proof of our lemma.

The result concerning recurrence-free sentences now follows from the lemma by observing that a sentence (closed formula) is true in a model if and only if it is satisfied by at least one assignment. Thus a recurrence-free sentence \(\phi \) is true in \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\) if and only if there is an assignment \(\sigma \) that satisfies \(\phi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_0\); by the lemma, this is the case if and only if there is an assignment (to wit, \(\delta ^\phi _\sigma \), which in the case of sentences just is \(\sigma \)) that satisfies \(\phi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\), if and only if \(\phi \) is true in \({\mathfrak {M}}_1\).Footnote 8

In an analogous fashion, one can prove the corresponding result about first-order languages in predicate functor notation: PFL-languages with an identity predicate but without the functor \(\mathsf {Ref}\) are, in general, strictly less expressive than the same languages with \(\mathsf {Ref}\).

Appendix 2

Here we recall the syntax and semantics of predicate functor logic.

A language \(\mathcal {L}\) of predicate functor logic with identity is characterized by its set of non-logical primitive predicates, each of which has an arity \(n\ge 0\). The primitive symbols of such a language \(\mathcal {L}\) are, in addition to its non-logical primitive predicates, the functors \(\mathsf {Der}\), \(\mathsf {Ref}\), \(\mathsf {Inv}\), \(\mathsf {inv}\), and \(\mathsf {Neg}\), all of arity 1, the functor \(\times \) of arity 2, and the identity predicate I of arity 2 (as well as left and right parentheses for grouping).

The predicates of \(\mathcal {L}\) and their arities are defined inductively as follows. Every n-ary non-logical primitive predicate P of \(\mathcal {L}\) is an \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicate of arity n. The identity predicate I is an \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicate of arity 2. If \(\phi \) is an n-ary \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicate, \(\mathsf {Der}\phi \) is an \((n-1)\)-ary \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicate (except when \(n=0\), in which case \(\mathsf {Der}\phi \) is also 0-ary), \(\mathsf {Ref}\phi \) is an \((n-1)\)-ary \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicate (except when \(n=0\), in which case \(\mathsf {Ref}\phi \) is also 0-ary), and \(\mathsf {Inv}\phi \), \(\mathsf {inv}\phi \), as well as \(\mathsf {Neg}\phi \), are n-ary \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicates. If \(\phi \) is an n-ary, and \(\psi \) an m-ary, \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicate, \((\phi \times \psi )\) is an \((n+m)\)-ary \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicate. The 0-ary \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicates are also called \(\mathcal {L}\)-sentences.

A model \({\mathfrak {M}}\) for \(\mathcal {L}\) is a pair \((M, \mathcal {I})\), where M, the domain of \({\mathfrak {M}}\), is a non-empty set and \(\mathcal {I}\) is a function assigning to each n-ary primitive predicate P of \(\mathcal {L}\) an n-ary function \(P^{\mathfrak {M}}\) from \(M^n\) to the set \(\{ 0,1\}\) of truth values. \(M^0\) is the singleton set containing the empty tuple \(\langle \rangle \) as a member, so a function f from \(M^0\) to \(\{0,1\}\) maps \(\langle \rangle \) to \(f(\langle \rangle )\in \{ 0,1\}\), and we will simply identify such f with \(f(\langle \rangle )\).

For each n-ary \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicate \(\phi \), we define the interpretation \(\phi ^{\mathfrak {M}}: M^n \rightarrow \{0,1\}\) of \(\phi \) in \({\mathfrak {M}}\) recursively as follows: Where P is an n-ary primitive non-logical predicate of \(\mathcal {L}\), \(P^{\mathfrak {M}}\) is already given by \({\mathfrak {M}}\). The interpretation \(I^{\mathfrak {M}}\) of the identity predicate I in \({\mathfrak {M}}\) is true identity, i.e. the binary function on M that maps each pair (aa) to 1 and every other pair to 0. Where \(\phi \) is an \((n+1)\)-ary \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicate, \((\mathsf {Der}\phi )^{\mathfrak {M}}\) is the function that maps any n-tuple \((a_1,\ldots ,a_n)\) to \(\max \{ \phi ^{\mathfrak {M}}(a_1,\ldots ,a_n,a)\, |\, a\in M \}\); if \(\phi \) is 0-ary, \((\mathsf {Der}\phi )^{\mathfrak {M}}\) is just \(\phi ^{\mathfrak {M}}\). Where \(\phi \) is an \((n+1)\)-ary \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicate, \((\mathsf {Ref}\phi )^{\mathfrak {M}}\) is the function that maps any n-tuple \((a_1,\ldots ,a_n)\) to \(\phi ^{\mathfrak {M}}(a_1,\ldots ,a_n,a_n)\); if \(\phi \) is 0-ary, \((\mathsf {Ref}\phi )^{\mathfrak {M}}\) is just \(\phi ^{\mathfrak {M}}\). If \(\phi \) is an n-ary \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicate, \((\mathsf {Inv}\phi )^{\mathfrak {M}}\) is the function that maps any n-tuple \((a_1,\ldots ,a_n)\) to \(\phi ^{\mathfrak {M}}(a_n,a_1,\ldots ,a_{n-1})\), \((\mathsf {inv}\phi )^{\mathfrak {M}}\) maps \((a_1,\ldots ,a_n)\) to \(\phi ^{\mathfrak {M}}(a_1,\ldots ,a_{n-2},a_n,a_{n-1})\), and \((\mathsf {Neg}\phi )^{\mathfrak {M}}\) maps any n-tuple \((a_1,\ldots ,a_n)\) to \(1 - \phi ^{\mathfrak {M}}(a_1,\ldots ,a_n)\). Finally, if \(\phi \) is an n-ary and \(\psi \) an m-ary \(\mathcal {L}\)-predicate, \((\phi \times \psi )^{\mathfrak {M}}\) maps any \((n+m)\)-tuple \((a_1,\ldots ,a_n,b_1,\ldots ,b_m)\) to \(\min \{ \phi ^{\mathfrak {M}}(a_1,\ldots ,a_n), \psi ^{\mathfrak {M}}(b_1,\ldots ,b_m)\}\).

If \(\phi \) is a sentence of \(\mathcal {L}\), we say that \(\phi \) is true in \({\mathfrak {M}}\) just in case \(\phi ^{\mathfrak {M}}= 1\); otherwise the sentence \(\phi \) is false in \({\mathfrak {M}}\).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wehmeier, K.F. Identity and quantification. Philos Stud 174, 759–770 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0706-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0706-3

Keywords

Navigation