Skip to main content
Log in

Free will eliminativism: reference, error, and phenomenology

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Shaun Nichols has recently argued that while the folk notion of free will is associated with error, a question still remains whether the concept of free will should be eliminated or preserved. He maintains that like other eliminativist arguments in philosophy, arguments that free will is an illusion seem to depend on substantive assumptions about reference. According to free will eliminativists, people have deeply mistaken beliefs about free will and this entails that free will does not exist. However, an alternative reaction is that free will does exist, we just have some deeply mistaken beliefs about it. According to Nichols, all such debates boil down to whether or not the erroneous folk term in question successfully refers or not. Since Nichols adopts the view that reference is systematically ambiguous, he maintains that in some contexts it’s appropriate to take a restrictivist view about whether a term embedded in a false theory refers, while in other contexts it’s appropriate to take a liberal view about whether a token of the very same term refers. This, according to Nichols, affords the possibility of saying that the sentence “free will exists” is false in some contexts and true in others. In this paper I argue that even if we grant Nichols his pluralistic approach to reference, there is still good reason to prefer eliminativism to preservationism with regard to free will. My argument focuses on one important difference between the concept of “free will” and other theoretical terms embedded in false theories—i.e., the role that the phenomenology of free agency plays in reference fixing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, Nichols and Knobe (2007), Sarkissian et al. (2010), Roskies and Nichols (2008).

  2. As Nichols notes, his main argument can also be made if we assume instead that (1) in addition to the presupposition of indeterminism, people also have a presupposition that choice isn’t random and that (2) all events are either determined or random (cf. Russell 1995, 14; Kane 1996, 11) (Nichols 2013, fn.1).

  3. For an alternative account of our folk-psychological intuitions about free will, see (Nahmias et al. 2005, 2006), Nahmias and Murray (2010).

  4. Nichols, however, notes that a descriptivist can be more or less liberal about reference fixing, depending “on how much of the theory has to be true in order for the term to refer” (2013, fn.2).

  5. On Nichols’s taxonomy of positions, revisionism (e.g., Vargas 2005, 2007) is just one form of preservationism. Preservationism is a broader category, including other possible positions as well (see Nichols 2013).

  6. I should note that there is some precedent of natural kind terms getting their reference fixed by phenomenology by causal-historical theorists Kripke (1980), for example, famously does this for the concept of pain.

  7. Consider the practice of collective punishment—“retaliation against people who play no part in committing the offence that is to be avenged” (2012, 48). “The anthropologist Ram Nath Sharma (1997, 377) writes that in most tribal societies, ‘the punishment given for murder is death, but this punishment may not be given to him who has murdered. In his place, some other member of his family, group, or clan may be killed since the group is collectively responsible for the criminal acts of each of its members” (Sommers 2012, 48).

  8. In honor cultures, it is very important that the victim respond personally, and not necessarily to the person that harmed them. As Sommers describes it, “Third-party punishment strips the victim of his opportunity to avenge himself. Since personal retaliation is crucial, one would expect the emergence of norms that discourage third-party punishment and attitudes that find it to be unsatisfying” (2012, 44).

  9. A preservationist could, perhaps, argue that there is an underlying common property (or set of properties) among cultures, but that moral responsibility practices evolved differently given different ways of life resulting from adaptations to local ecological conditions (Justin Caouette, in correspondence). The challenge, however, is for the preservationist to explain exactly what this common property (or set of properties) is. The proposal under consideration, remember, is to conceive of the initial baptism in terms of an external set of reference-fixing properties, such as the cultural practices associated with punishment, reward, praise, and blame. Sommers, however, maintains that there is no common property (or set of properties) that can fit this bill, hence preservationists looking to make this move need to address his challenge head on.

  10. As Sommers notes, “In many honor cultures, the condition appears to either be de-emphasized or in some cases absent; agents need not have control over an act in order to be deemed fair and morally appropriate targets of blame and retaliation” (2012, 48).

References

  • Andreasen, R. O. (2000). Race: Biological reality or social construct? Philosophy of Science, 67, S653–S666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Appiah, A. (1995). The uncompleted argument: Du Bois and the illusion of race. In Linda A. Bell & D. Blumenfeld (Eds.), Overcoming racism and sexism (pp. 59–78). Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. (1985). Errors and the phenomenology of value. In T. Honderich (Ed.), Morality and objectivity (pp. 1–22). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P. (2004). Descartes’ baby. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (2002). Scientific realism. In E.N. Zalta (Ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2002 ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2002/entries/scientific-realism/

  • Campbell, J. (1957). Of selfhood and godhood. London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caruso, G. (2008). Consciousness and free will: A critique of the argument from introspection. Southwest Philosophy Review, 24(1), 219–231.

  • Caruso, G. D. (2012). Free will and consciousness: A determinist account of the illusion of free will. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deery, O., Bedke, M., & Nichols S. (2013). Phenomenal abilities: Incompatibilism and the experience of agency. In D. Shoemaker (Ed) Oxford studies in agency and responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1962). Explanation, reduction and empiricism. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science: Scientific explanation, space, and time (Vol. 3, pp. 28–97). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (1996). The significance of free will. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kozuch, B., & Nichols, S. (2011). Awareness of unawareness. Folk psychology and introspective transparency. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18(11–12), 135–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1984). Science and values (Vol. 66). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1972). Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50(3), 249–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (1988). Judgement and justification. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J.L. (1997). Ethics: Investigating right and wrong. London: Penguin Books Ltd.

  • Mallon, R. (2006). Race: Normative, not metaphysical or semantic. Ethics, 116(3), 525–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T., & Turner, J. (2005). Surveying freedom: Folk intuitions about free will and moral responsibility. Philosophical Psychology, 18, 561–584.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T., & Turner, J. (2006). Is incompatibilism intuitive? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73, 28–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., & Murray, D. (2010). Experimental philosophy on free will: An error theory for incompatibilist intuitions. In J. Aguilar, A. Buckareff, & K. Frankish (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of action (pp. 189–215). New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (2012). The indeterminist intuition. The Monist, 95(2), 290–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (2013). Free will and error. In Gregg D. Caruso (Ed.), Exploring the illusion of free will and moral responsibility. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2007). Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions. Nous, 41, 663–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., Pinillos, A., & Mallon, R. (Forthcoming). Ambiguous reference. Mind.

  • O’Connor, T. (1995). Agent causation. In T. O’Connor (Ed.), Agents, causes and events: Essays on free will and indeterminism (pp. 173–200). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, D., & Nichols, S. (2013). The lesson of bypassing. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4, 599–619.

  • Roskies, A., & Nichols, S. (2008). Bringing moral responsibility down to Earth. Journal of Philosophy, 105(7), 371–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, P. (1995). Freedom and moral sentiment. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkissian, H., Chatterjee, A., De Brigard, F., Knobe, J., Nichols, S., & Sirker, S. (2010). Is belief in free will a cultural universal? Mind and Language, 25(3), 346–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sommers, T. (2012). Relative justice: Cultural diversity, free will, and moral responsibility. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. P. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (1986). Freedom and belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, R. (1992). Metaphysics. 4th ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall (First ed., 1963).

  • Vargas, M. (2005). The revisionist’s guide to responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 125, 399–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2007). Revisionism. In J. Fischer, et al. (Eds.), Four views on free will. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2013). Building better beings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M. (2002). The Illusion of conscious will. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books, MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, L. (1941). Determinism: Free will is an illusion. Philosophy, 16, 386–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gregg D. Caruso.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Caruso, G.D. Free will eliminativism: reference, error, and phenomenology. Philos Stud 172, 2823–2833 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0453-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0453-x

Keywords

Navigation