Skip to main content
Log in

In support of anti-intellectualism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Intellectualist theories attempt to assimilate know how to propositional knowledge and, in so doing, fail to properly explain the close relation know how bears to action. I develop here an anti-intellectualist theory that is warranted, I argue, because it best accounts for the difference between know how and mere “armchair knowledge.” Know how is a mental state characterized by a certain world-to-mind direction of fit (though it is non-motivational) and attendant functional role. It is essential of know how, but not propositional knowledge, that it makes possible performance errors and has the functional role of guiding action. The theory is attractive, in part, because it allows for propositional, non-propositional and perhaps even non-representational varieties of know how.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See especially Stanley and Williamson (2001). References to other recent work are provided below.

  2. Harry, by the way, represents an analogue to Mary in Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument (Jackson 1987). Mary knows everything there is to know in the science of color vision but doesn’t have knowledge by acquaintance of the color red. Harry knows everything there is to know about how hockey is played but doesn’t know how to play the game.

  3. Michael Polanyi’s work on “tacit knowledge” has also been influential in certain quarters (Polanyi 1962).

  4. See also Pollock’s (1987) anti-intellectualist view. My own view has, perhaps, more in common with Pollock’s view than with Ryle’s and Hawley’s views.

  5. Other intellectualist treatments of know how can be found in Katzoff (1984), Carr (1979, 1981), Hintikka (1975) and Brown (1970).

  6. Stanley and Williamson are careful not to commit themselves to a Russellian account of propositions rather than, say, a Fregean account. Following them, I ignore alternative accounts of propositions in order to make their view more perspicuous.

  7. The terms I use to denote the two directions of fit, ‘descriptive’ and ‘directive,’ are taken from Millikan (1996).

  8. Whether this is possible in any given case may turn on the specific content of the representations and/or whether the descriptive representation and directive representation have exactly the same content. I do not have the space to go into this in detail.

  9. Even those who do not identify intentions with belief-desire complexes do appear to think intentions have both directions of fit, e.g., Davidson (1978), Harman (1986, p. 79).

  10. I examine anti-representationalist accounts of know how of the sort that deny this claim in Sect. 6, below.

  11. Perhaps, as an anonymous reviewer suggests, one should say that the subject must have an overriding desire to act as she knows how to act. I doubt that this is necessary. In most actions this more specific desire is not present. One should at least say that the subject must not have an overriding desire to act other than in the way she knows how to act. In what follows, I assume that this condition holds in the relevant cases.

  12. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for directing me to these accounts of belief.

  13. One reason to take issue with the assertion account of belief is that it denies belief to non-linguistic animals and perhaps even human beings incapable of physically expressing the content of their mental states. The link between belief and utterance seems contingent rather than constitutive.

  14. See Stich (1978) for articulation of these constraints on belief.

  15. I owe this point to Shaun Nichols. Cf. Fodor (1968).

  16. The intellectualism/anti-intellectualism debate may appear to find purchase outside of epistemology too, in linguistics and cognitive science. Chomsky’s account of linguistic competence is described as intellectualist (see, e.g., Chomsky 1980, p. 91). It would be rash, however, to assume that the debates are strictly analogous. All linguistic competence can’t be a matter of having a propositionally encoded belief, on pain of regress. Some basic linguistic competence must be non-propositional. Fodor (1968) claims to be an intellectualist but I suspect that his view is not relevantly similar to the intellectualists discussed here.

  17. All “mental state theories” of know how—and not just intellectualism—must face Ryle’s regress argument. Suppose that in deploying one’s know how, one must activate a mental state. If activation of this mental state is an exercise of know how, then one must activate another mental state in order to exercise one’s know how. And so on, ad infinitum. Stanley and Williamson argue, I believe correctly, that the way out of this regress is to deny that all exercises of know how are intelligent activities of the sort that we must know how to perform.

  18. See also Noe (2005, pp. 282–283). Thanks to Ephraim Glick for helping me to see this point.

  19. This is not to say that know how isn’t embodied. I discuss the putative embodiment of know how in Sect. 6.

  20. Bengson and Moffett do not actually offer this argument as I have presented it. Their main concern lies elsewhere. I do think, however, the argument presents an interesting way of extending their view in order to account for the phenomena.

  21. See also Varela (1999), who offers an extended discussion of embodied ethical know how.

  22. See Clark (2000) for criticism. Clark argues that the public symbols of natural language provide important “cognitive scaffolding” for the development of moral know how.

  23. I don’t suppose we have any intuitive purchase on whether or not prototypes qua prototypes entail the possibility of performance errors.

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J., & Moffett, M. (2007). Know how and concept-possession. Philosophical Studies, 136(1), 31–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J., Moffett, M., & Wright, J. (2009). The folk on knowing how. Philosophical Studies, 142(3), 387–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, D. G. (1970). Knowing how and knowing that, what. In O. P. Wood & G. Pitcher (Eds.), Ryle: A collection of critical essays. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4, 73–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, R. (2007). What is moral judgment. Journal of Philosophy, 104(7), 321–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (1979). The logic of knowing how and ability. Mind, 88, 394–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (1981). Knowledge in practice. American Philosophical Quarterly, 18, 53–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1980). Rules and representations. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. (1989). A neurocomputational perspective. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. (1995). The engine of reason, the seat of the soul: A philosophical journey into the brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. (1998). Toward a cognitive neurobiology of the virtues. Topoi, 17, 83–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain body and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2000). Word and action: Reconciling rules and know-how in moral cognition. In R. Campbell & B. Hunter (Eds.), Moral epistemology naturalized (pp. 267–290). Alberta: University of Calgary Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1978). Intending. In Y. Yovel (Ed.), Philosophy of history and action. Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1968). The appeal to tacit knowledge in psychological explanations. Journal of Philosophy, 65(20), 627–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1986). Change in view. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2003). Success and knowledge-how. American Philosophical Quarterly, 40(1), 19–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1975). Different constructions in terms of the basic epistemological verbs. In J. Hintikka (Ed.), The intentions of intentionality and other new models for modalities (pp. 1–25). Boston: Reidel Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1987). Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32, 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, M. (1996). Decision theory as philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katzoff, C. (1984). Knowing how. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 22, 61–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maher, P. (1993). Betting on theories. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1996). Pushmi-pullyu representations. In L. May, M. Friedman, & A. Clark (Eds.), Minds and morals (pp. 145–161). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noe, A. (2005). Against intellectualism. Analysis, 65(4), 278–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noe, A. (2006). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1962). Personal knowledge. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. (1987). Epistemic norms. Synthese, 55, 61–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of “meaning”. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Mind, language and reality: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1946). Knowing how and knowing that. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 46, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1979). A taxonomy of illocutionary acts in expression and meaning. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon, P. (2004). Knowing how and knowing that: A distinction reconsidered. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 104, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (forthcoming). Knowing (how). Nous.

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. The Journal of Philosophy, 98, 411–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1978). Beliefs and subdoxastic states. Philosophy of Science, 45(4), 499–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1999). Ethical know-how: Action wisdom and cognition. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Richmond Campbell, Terry Horgan, Bruce Hunter, Heather Logue, Duncan MacIntosh, Chris Maloney, Farid Masrour, Adam Morton, Jennifer Nagel, Shaun Nichols, Brendan Ritchie, Mark Timmons, Robert Wilson, Jennifer Woodrow and an anonymous referee at Philosophical Studies for very useful feedback. Earlier versions of the essay were presented to audiences at Dalhousie University, MIT, Arizona State University and The University of Arizona. All of these audiences were generous with helpful questions, comments and criticisms. Work on the essay was supported by a fellowship from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Victor Kumar.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kumar, V. In support of anti-intellectualism. Philos Stud 152, 135–154 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9459-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9459-6

Keywords

Navigation