Skip to main content
Log in

Anticausatives in Sinhala: involitivity and causer suppression

  • Published:
Natural Language & Linguistic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many recent theories of causative/inchoative alternations adopt an anticausativization analysis, wherein the inchoative is derived from the causative via some operation that eliminates the causer argument from a verb’s argument structure, provided the causer is semantically unspecified for agentivity (Levin and Rappaport Hovav 1995; Chierchia 2004; Koontz-Garboden 2009). We explore the properties of such an analysis for causative/inchoative alternations in Colloquial Sinhala, which are overtly indicated via a volitive/involitive stem contrast on the verb. We argue that the alternation arises from a causer suppression operation that deletes the causer syntactically but preserves it semantically, albeit formally marking it as unresolvable for agentivity. This prevents the verb from occurring in certain contexts requiring agentivity of a syntactically active argument, including the volitive stem, although such a reading may be derived pragmatically. The patient in turn shows a case alternation that we argue reflects two ways the suppressed causer can be interpreted—via reflexivization or existential binding. These data, we argue, support an anticausative analysis as elimination of causers unspecified for agentivity. They also expand the typology of ways agentivity is encoded and left unspecified, how causer elimination can occur, and what types of overt morphology can indicate the alternation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The following abbreviations are used: acc = accusative, caus = cause, dat = dative, def = definite, emph = emphatic, gen = genitive, inf = infinitive, inst = instrumental, inv = involitive, loc = locative, neg = negation, pl = plural, prs = present, prt = participle, post = postposition, pst = past, ques = question, refl = reflexive, sg = singular, vol = volitive.

  2. Sinhala also has compound verbs, including those formed from nominal, adjectival, or verbal roots suffixed with -we- ‘do/become’ or -kərə- ‘do’, which themselves may surface as volitive or involitive (as discussed by Henadeerage 2002:55). Furthermore, volitive -kərə- vs. involitive -we- forms often mark causative/inchoative pairs. We do not distinguish these from non-compound pairs, since as far as we know this distinction is irrelevant to any claims we make regarding the relation of involitivity to anticausatives.

  3. Differential object marking patterns vary across speakers. The pattern outlined here is that noted by Gair (1970:61–62), though our speakers tend to use accusative more or less obligatorily with animates and optionally with some inanimates. Kahr (1989:113–124) provides some additional discussion of which DPs may be considered animate (though our speakers find some of her data formal). The details of the pattern will not matter, as we are ultimately interested in what accusative case means when it does arise.

  4. We use the ECOS/ICOS labels here as gross descriptive terms, though they were intended by Levin and Rappaport Hovav (1995) to distinguish verbs that describe change-of-state events that require a causer vs. those that do not. (See Alexiadou et al. 2006 and Alexiadou 2010 for a more nuanced classification of verb types building on this.) We later outline a notion of internal vs. external causation for ECOS verbs that distinguishes (self) causation by the patient vs. causation by some entity other than the patient respectively.

  5. In some dialects transitive involitives also allow instrumental subjects:

    (i):
    figure i

    However, our informants did not find these acceptable (likewise for Jany 2005); we set them aside for now.

  6. Literature on mirativity (DeLancey 1997, 2001; Dickinson 2000), the grammatical encoding of incongruency between an event and a speaker’s expectation of that event, suggests a similar overlap of volition and speaker expectation. A comparison of volitives and miratives, however, would take us too far afield.

  7. We take the volitive to be the causative form, though most, but not all, volitive causatives also have involitive causative counterparts. Thus the causative may properly speaking be thought of as a root that may occur in at least the volitive and possibly the involitive. Conversely, inchoatives are always involitive. Sinhala also has a productive morphological causative -(w)ə- that can apply to any verb; we set this aside.

  8. The data in (15), as well as those in (14b), do have acceptable but irrelevant pro-drop readings, where there is a separate null causer and the verbs are technically transitive; see below.

  9. Arguing for a subject grammatical function in Sinhala is problematic. Henadeerage (2002:Chap. 3) (see also Gair 1976, 1990; Kahr 1989:36) makes a detailed argument that many otherwise cross-linguistically viable subjecthood diagnostics are inapplicable to Sinhala, because they either do not exist, are restricted to some property other than grammatical function, or pick out multiple DPs in a clause, not isolating one single class of DPs one could call “subjects”. Nonetheless, the diagnostics we discuss do seem to converge on one class of DPs, nominative A and S arguments of volitive clauses, that could be argued to be subjects.

  10. Gair and Karunatillake (1998:130) suggest that for some speakers taman may not be subject-oriented, though it appears to be for our informants and Inman’s.

  11. In the case of minimarannə ‘murder’ the fact that it has no detransitive counterpart is also independently predicated by the fact that it allows no involitive at all, due to its inherently volitional nature.

  12. Although we use “agent” as a convenient cover term for these two notions, DeLancey (1985) in fact reifies a prototype notion of agentivity involving at least these two categories (see also Cruse 1973; Lakoff 1977; DeLancey 1984; Dowty 1991; Van Valin and Wilkins 1996; Kittilä 2005; inter alia).

  13. Languages do vary in which ECOS verbs alternate in causative/inchoative alternations, and some non-ECOS verbs show similar alternations in some languages (see e.g., Reinhart 2000 on ICOS verbs in Hebrew and McKoon and Macfarland 2000 on ICOS verbs in English, which do not alternate in Sinhala). However, Levin and Rappaport Hovav (1995:Chap. 3) argue extensively that such so-called “causative pairs” with non-ECOS verbs do not represent the same causative/inchoative relationship found with ECOS verbs. Nonetheless, that Sinhala detransitives are lexically restricted argues against a general passive analysis.

  14. This is different from the ECOS label adopted above to indicate verbs that describe changes-of-state that by default require a causer. The notion of “external” causation defined here is a subset of this where the causer is explicitly entailed to be a participant distinct from those expressed overtly in the clause. From here on out we use “external” causation in this sense, and ECOS as a descriptive label for a class of verbs.

  15. We use the volitive transitive in (29b) for comparison, since the involitive is ruled out with purposives on its canonical non-volitional reading, for obvious reasons. We return to the issue in Sect. 5.1.

  16. Non-expression of arguments follows from his Minimal Argument Constraint (p. 153), though Inman leaves open what non-expression means syntactically or semantically. He also assumes that this principle operates solely within the domain of involitives, so that detransitives are derived from transitive involitives. This fails to predict that some detransitives will not have involitive transitive counterparts as in (17).

  17. A fourth argument given by Alexiadou et al. is that inchoatives show evidence of having causal semantics, in terms of taking PPs that express causers. However, this is not an argument against anticausativization, just an argument against analyses of inchoatives that do not suppose that they are underlyingly causative. The anticausative analysis we adopt (following Levin and Rappaport Hovav 1995; Chierchia 2004; Koontz-Garboden 2009) assumes they are causative, so this argument does not apply.

  18. Doron (2003:11–14) argues against an anticausative analysis for ECOS verbs only as an operation on verbs per se, suggesting instead that markedness asymmetries arise because roots that are realized as unmarked causative verbs are those that typically require instigators à la Croft (1990) or Haspelmath (1993). We concur, but do not see that this observation argues against treating the marked form as derived from the unmarked form (verbs or roots) when such an asymmetry exists.

  19. Another argument Koontz-Garboden (2009:124) makes against causer deletion is that it would violate the Monotonicity Hypothesis of Kiparsky (1982), Rappaport Hovav and Levin (1998), and Koontz-Garboden (2007), by which lexical semantic operations may only add and never subtract meaning.

  20. One interesting difference between Sinhala and Spanish is that ICOS verbs in Spanish (according to Koontz-Garboden 2009:108) are generally unacceptable with por sí solo, suggesting that they lack causal semantics, while in Sinhala ibeemə is acceptable with these verbs, suggesting that they have causal semantics (see also Alexiadou et al. 2006). Since we are only concerned with derived inchoatives we ignore this issue, and leave an analysis of lexical inchoatives for future work.

  21. An alternative anticausativization analysis to both deletion and reflexivization is an analysis where causation is preserved but the causer is existentially bound, a variant of the analysis of Levin and Rappaport Hovav (1995). We in fact assume this is possible in Sinhala as well, and discuss it in Sect. 7.1.

  22. Koontz-Garboden does not discuss exactly how his λ-terms relate to syntactic argument structure, e.g., how the arguments of dyadic and monadic predicates are realized. The details are not necessarily important here, save that we assume that by virtue of taking two individual arguments the verbs in (36) are transitive, while those with one individual argument as in (38) are intransitive, regardless of whether that single argument is the subject or an object that raises to subject position. For present purposes there is no need to appeal to a level of syntactic argument structure above and beyond the argument structure of the typed λ-theoretic denotations we give, and thus we set that aside here, though we do assume it exists.

  23. See Beavers and Koontz-Garboden (2012) for some discussion of negligence readings, building on Talmy (2000), Wolff (2003, 2007), Wolff and Song (2003), and Wolff et al. (2010).

  24. That a certain verb form might have such a requirement is not unheard of; Doron (2003:18–19) notes that for certain verb roots in Hebrew the intensive transitive template can have a similar effect in requiring an action reading. An alternative to the disjunctive requirement we have posited for the Sinhala volitive could be that what the volitive requires of its subject is simply action, but deliberate non-action constitutes a type of action in some possible world but not the real world, i.e., an action embedded under a sublexical modality in the sense of Koenig and Davis (2001) (cf. also Dowty 1979:176 on agentive states as in John deliberately stood still). Either analysis would work just as well here.

  25. These conclusions are also supported by the verbs Henadeerage (2002:137) non-exhaustively lists as having volitive stems, which includes many externally caused-change-of-state verbs that alternate with inchoatives. Our speakers have informally felt that such verbs require agentivity; non-deliberate neglect, if possible at all, requires involitive variants. However, we have found three exceptions, namely the word for ‘know’ in (35), the word for ‘like’ in (42), and the word for ‘exist’ used to indicate possession as in (i), which (a) take quirky dative subjects (also rare for a volitive verb) and (b) have non-actor readings.

    (i):
    figure az

    For the moment, we simply treat these as lexical exceptions.

  26. Koontz-Garboden argues that the supposed implicational relationship in (51) is not an entailment as commonly assumed, but might be some weaker sort of inference. For us this is beside the point. All that matters is that the inchoative is judged as true at the same time as an agentive causative.

  27. Recall that accusative only occurs on animates, and usually only optionally. Thus all of our patient arguments here are human, and the relevant class of verbs are those that take human patient arguments. Note that this pattern in general is less acceptable to some of our speakers, especially younger speakers, and may represent an older pattern that is dying out in the language.

  28. At least one unergative is also acceptable to at least some of our informants with an accusative subject, namely the verb for ‘dance’, on the reading that the subject was compelled to dance by an outside source:

    (i):
    figure bg

    We suggest that this may be a lexicalized exception, following a process of implicit causativization cross-linguistically attested for motion verbs (Levin and Rappaport Hovav 1995; Folli and Harley 2006).

  29. An interesting ramification of this possibility is that technically the inchoative form for *The promise/contract broke is grammatical in Sinhala, but crucially only on a passive-type reading:

    (i):
    figure bj

    Although the patient here is overtly nominative, as noted in Sect. 2 Sinhala shows differential object marking, so that inanimates rarely show overt accusative. Thus the object in (i) may be underlyingly accusative, and (i) is an accusative-subject inchoative, consistent with its interpretation. That only a passive-type reading is possible is in line with the cross-linguistically attested fact that not every causative use of ‘break’ verbs has a true inchoative reading, suggesting the causative form is unmarked as in Sect. 4.1.

  30. A reviewer asks if accusative-subject inchoatives might be underlyingly transitive, as per the analysis of accusative subject inchoatives in various Germanic languages proposed by Schäfer (2008:291–302), who posits a null, semi-expletive external agent DP (see also Haider 2001 and Sigurðsson 2005). However, there is no evidence for a null argument in accusative-subject anticausatives in Sinhala, and the impossibility of purposives argues against positing an agent DP (and in Sinhala the accusative argument is clearly a subject, unlike in German, the only Germanic language where an expletive is overtly attested). Furthermore, the Sinhala constructions differ from the Germanic ones in being restricted to the same class of verbs that show regular anticausatives, i.e., those with effector-subject transitive variants. In Germanic the relevant verbs have agent-subject transitive counterparts (Sigurðsson 2005), suggesting that the two constructions are not identical. However, they do share in common entailing external causation, and below we present a truth-conditional analysis of this that does not rely on positing a null argument.

  31. Reinhart (2000, 2002) likewise proposes a type of elimination specifically restricted to causers (arguments bearing the [+c] feature in her Theta System). This is also reminiscent of the analysis of Alexiadou and Anagnostopoulou (2004) of non-active voice morphology in Greek (building on Embick 1998, 2004) as the Spell-Out of a Voice/v head in a configuration without an external argument, with different instantiations (e.g., inchoative, reflexive, and passive) due to different syntactic and thematic features (see also Alexiadou et al. 2006; Alexiadou 2010). We return to this syncretism from a semantic perspective below.

  32. Kaufmann (2007) proposes an analysis of middles (in the sense of Kemmer 1993, 1994) in Fula that also assumes unbound variables in need of binding, which may again be reflexive or existential (among other options). She extends this to anticausatives, but suggests that in this case the effector is disposed of by existentially binding off the entire causing event, although she does not say what the ultimate interpretation of the effector is. For the reasons discussed above, the analysis we have proposed, whereby the effector is reflexivized or existentially-bound, seems more appropriate for Sinhala anticausatives.

  33. Whether a property or disposition causal reading is possible may depend on the choice of subject. As Beth Levin (p.c.) points out, The lightning destroyed the car lacks this reading, though as noted in Sect. 5.2 at least some natural forces may be defined only in terms of their actions (e.g., lightning is by definition electricity in motion), which may preclude or disprefer non-action readings.

  34. This is also essentially Levin and Rappaport Hovav’s (1995:91) definition of internal causation. However, consistent with their later discussion (p. 92), this interpretation arises with ECOS verbs by coidentifying the external causer with the patient. See also Prior et al. (1982) on the causal basis of dispositions.

  35. DeLancey (1984) also identifies a category of “inactive direct causation”, citing in particular diseases and states like hunger (e.g., Hunger killed him; p. 204; ex. (67)), that serve as invisible, but less prototypical causers due to a lack of volition. He partly motivates this category on the basis of special types of marked morphosyntactic encoding it receives in Hare and Newari, suggesting its grammatical relevance.

  36. Van Valin and Wilkins (1996:301) (following Talmy 1996), similarly assume subjects may stand in for causal events by a process of ‘metonymic clipping’ (see also Levin and Rappaport Hovav 1995:84).

  37. Such data preclude the analysis of the stem alternation of Henadeerage (2002). Henadeerage argues that the involitive stem found in inchoatives is a special use of the involitive that does not indicate any non-volitional semantics or anything else otherwise associated with involitives. However, (79) shows this is not the case. Furthermore, this association of the inchoative with the involitive stem is a stipulation on his analysis; on our analysis it follows directly from the meaning of an inchoative and the two stem forms.

  38. Lexical ICOS inchoatives, which have no causative uses in Sinhala, are also all involitive. This follows if we assume they lexically have denotations that do not admit event subjects; see fn. 40.

  39. Lavine (2010) discusses a similar sort of construction in Russian and Ukrainian, the so-called “transitive impersonal”, where an accusative subject can occur with an inchoative or passive only on a reading where there was external causation (we thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out to us):

    (i):
    figure cf

    Lavine analyzes this by positing a v head that encodes external causation and assigns accusative to the object, but does not itself license an external argument (following Pylkkänen 2008). This analysis has the same semantic intuition as ours, though we remain agnostic as to whether the denotations we give in turn determine different syntactic functional heads, for which we see no particular evidence in Sinhala.

  40. We have not discussed verbs lexically selecting a stative causer. We leave this for future investigation, though bloom-type ICOS verbs may be such a case (cf. Levin and Rappaport Hovav 1995:97).

References

  • Alexiadou, Artemis. 2010. On the morpho-syntax of (anti-)causative verbs. In Syntax, lexical semantics and event structure, eds. Malka Rappaport Hovav, Edit Doron, and Ivy Sichel, 177–203. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Alexiadou, Artemis, and Elena Anagnostopoulou. 2004. Voice morphology in the causative-inchoative alternation: Evidence for a non-unified structural analysis of unaccusatives. In The unaccusativity puzzle, eds. Artemis Alexiadou, Elena Anagnostopoulou, and Martin Everaert, 114–136. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Alexiadou, Artemis, Elena Anagnostopoulou, and Florian Schäfer. 2006. The properties of anti-causatives crosslinguistically. In Phases of interpretation, ed. Mara Frascarelli, 187–211. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, Jon, and Robin Cooper. 1981. Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy 18: 153–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beavers, John, and Andrew Koontz-Garboden. 2012. Manner and result in the roots of verbal meaning. Linguistic Inquiry 43: 331–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beavers, John, and Cala Zubair. 2010. The interaction of transitivity features in the Sinhala involitive. In Transitivity: Form, meaning, acquisition, and processing, eds. Patrick Brandt and Marco Garcia, 69–92. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohnemeyer, Jürgen. 2007. Morpholexical transparency and the argument structure of verbs of cutting and breaking. Cognitive Linguistics 18: 153–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, Gennaro. 2004. A semantics for unaccusatives and its syntactic consequences. In The unaccusativity puzzle, eds. Artemis Alexiadou, Elena Anagnostopoulou, and Martin Everaert, 22–59. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The minimalist program. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coates, William A. 1972. Review of Gair (1970). Language 48: 463–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Croft, William. 1990. Possible verbs and the structure of meaning. In Meanings and prototypes, ed. S. L. Tsohatzidis, 48–73. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cruse, D. A. 1973. Some thoughts on agentivity. Journal of Linguistics 9: 11–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeLancey, Scott. 1984. Notes on agentivity and causation. Studies in Linguistics 8: 181–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeLancey, Scott. 1985. Agentivity and syntax. In CLS 21, part 2: Papers from the parasession on causatives and agentivity, eds. William H. Eilfort, Paul D. Kroeber, and Karen L. Peterson, 1–12. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeLancey, Scott. 1997. Mirativity: The grammatical marking of unexpected information. Linguistic Typology 1: 33–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeLancey, Scott. 2001. The mirative and evidentiality. Journal of Pragmatics 33: 369–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeSilva, M. W. S. 1960. Verbal categories in Colloquial Sinhalese. University of Ceylon Review 18: 96–112. January–April.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeSilva, M. W. S. 1974. Convergence in diglossia: The Sinhalese situation. International Journal of Dravidian Linguistics 3: 60–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickinson, Connie. 2000. Mirativity in Tsafiki. Studies in Language 24: 379–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doron, Edit. 2003. Agency and voice: The semantics of the Semitic templates. Natural Language Semantics 11: 1–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, David. 1979. Word meaning and Montague Grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, David. 1991. Thematic proto-roles and argument selection. Language 67: 547–619.

    Google Scholar 

  • Embick, David. 1998. Voice systems and the syntax-morphology interface. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 32: 41–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Embick, David. 2004. Unaccusative syntax and verbal alternations. In The unaccusativity puzzle, eds. Artemis Alexiadou, Elena Anagnostopoulou, and Martin Everaert, 137–158. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fagan, Sarah M. B. 1992. The syntax and semantics of middle constructions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fairbanks, G. H., James W. Gair, and M. W. S. DeSilva. 1986. Sinhala diglossia revisited, or diglossia dies hard. In South Asian languages: Structure, convergence & diglossia, ed. Bhadriraju Krishnamurti, 233–236. New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fillmore, Charles J. 1968. The case for case. In Universals in linguistic theory, eds. Emmon Bach and Robert T. Harms, 1–90. New York: Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fillmore, Charles J. 1970. The grammar of hitting and breaking. In Readings in English transformational grammar, eds. Roderick Jacobs and Peter S. Rosenbaum, 120–133. Waltham: Ginn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Folli, Raffaella, and Heidi Harley. 2006. On the licensing of causatives of directed motion: Waltzing Matilda all over. Studia Linguistica 60: 121–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gair, James W. 1970. Colloquial Sinhalese clause structures. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gair, James W. 1976. Is Sinhala a subject language? In The notion of subject in South Asian languages, ed. M. K. Varma. Madison: University of Wisconsin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gair, James W. 1990. Subjects, case, and INFL in Sinhala. In Experiencer subjects in South Asian languages, eds. Manindra K. Verma and K. P. Mohanan, 13–42. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gair, James W., and W. S. Karunatillake. 1998. Pronouns, reflexives, and antianaphora in Sinhala. In Studies in South Asian linguistics: Sinhala and other South Asian languages, ed. Barbara C. Lust, 126–139. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gair, James W., and John C. Paolillo. 1997. Sinhala. München: Lincom Europa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimshaw, Jane. 1982. On the lexical representation of Romance reflexive clitics. In The mental representation of grammatical relations, ed. Joan Bresnan, 87–148. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimshaw, Jane. 1990. Argument structure. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guerssel, Mohamed, Kenneth Hale, Mary Laughren, Beth Levin, and Josie White Eagle. 1985. A cross-linguistic study of transitivity alternations. In CLS 21, part 2: Papers from the parasession on causatives and agentivity, eds. William H. Eilfort, Paul D. Kroeber, and Karen L. Peterson, 48–63. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunasinghe, Khema Hemamala Himaransi. 1985. Passive voice: A new perspective, some evidence for a re-analysis from Sinhala. PhD diss., University of Victoria, Victoria.

  • Gunasinghe, Khema Hemamala Himaransi, and Joseph F. Kess. 1989. Volition, agency and the Sinhala passive. Indian Linguistics 50: 47–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haider, Hubert. 2001. How to stay accusative in insular German. Working Papers in Scandinavian Syntax 68: 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, Kenneth L., and Samuel Jay Keyser. 2002. Prolegomenon to a theory of argument structure. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall (Partee), Barbara. 1965. Subject and object in modern English. PhD diss., MIT, Cambridge, MA.

  • Härtl, Holden. 2003. Conceptual and grammatical characteristics of argument alternations: The case of decausative verbs. Linguistics 41: 883–916.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haspelmath, Martin. 1987. Transitivity alternations of the anticausative type (Arbeitspapiere, N.F., Nr. 4). Cologne: Institut für Sprachwissenschaft der Universität zu Köln.

  • Haspelmath, Martin. 1990. The grammaticization of passive morphology. Studies in Language 14: 25–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haspelmath, Martin. 1993. More on the typology of inchoative/causative verb alternations. In Causation and transitivity, eds. Bernard Comrie and Maria Polinsky. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henadeerage, Deepthi Kumara. 2002. Topics in Sinhala syntax. PhD diss., The Australian National University, Canberra.

  • Holisky, Dee Ann. 1987. The case of the intransitive subject in Tsova-Tush (Batsbi). Lingua 71: 103–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Inman, Michael Vincent. 1993. Semantics and pragmatics of Colloquial Sinhala involitive verbs. PhD diss., Stanford University, Stanford.

  • Jackendoff, Ray. 1990. Semantic structures. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaeggli, Osvaldo A. 1986. Passive. Linguistic Inquiry 17: 587–622.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jany, Carmen. 2005. The relationship between case marking and S, A, and O in spoken Sinhala. In Proceedings from the workshop on Sinhala linguistics. University of California, Santa Barbara.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahr, Joan Caspar. 1989. Discourse functions of the Sinhala passive. PhD diss., Harvard University, Cambridge, MA.

  • Kaufmann, Ingrid. 2007. Middle voice. Lingua 117: 1677–1714.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kemmer, Suzanne. 1993. The middle voice. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kemmer, Suzanne. 1994. Middle voice, transitivity, and the elaboration of events. In Voice: Form and function, eds. Barbara Fox and Paul J. Hopper, 179–230. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiparsky, Paul. 1982. Word-formation and the lexicon. In Proceedings of the 1982 mid-America linguistics conference, ed. F. Ingemann. Lawrence, Kansas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiparsky, Paul. 1992. Structural case. Unpublished Ms., Institute for Advanced Study, Berlin.

  • Kittilä, Seppo. 2005. Remarks on involuntary agent constructions. Word 56: 381–419.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koenig, Jean-Pierre, and Anthony R. Davis. 2001. Sublexical modality and the structure of lexical semantic representations. Linguistics and Philosophy 24: 71–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koontz-Garboden, Andrew. 2007. States, changes of state, and the monotonicity hypothesis. PhD diss., Stanford University, Stanford.

  • Koontz-Garboden, Andrew. 2009. Anticausativization. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 27: 77–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, George. 1965. On the nature of syntactic irregularity. PhD diss., Indiana University, Bloomington.

  • Lakoff, George. 1977. Linguistic gestalts. In Proceedings of CLS 13, 236–287.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lavine, James E. 2010. Case and events in transitive impersonals. Journal of Slavic Linguistics 18: 101–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levin, Beth, and Malka Rappaport Hovav. 1995. Unaccusativity: At the syntax-lexical semantics interface. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKoon, Gail, and Talke Macfarland. 2000. Externally and internally caused change of state verbs. Language 76: 833–858.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mendikoetxea, Amaya. 1999a. Construcciones con se: Medias, pasivas e impersonales. In Gramática descriptiva de la lengua Española, eds. Ignacio Bosque and Violeta Demonte, 1631–1722. Madrid: Editorial Espasa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendikoetxea, Amaya. 1999b. Construcciones inacusatives y pasivas. In Gramática descriptiva de la lengua Española, eds. Ignacio Bosque and Violeta Demonte, 1575–1629. Madrid: Editorial Espasa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nedyalkov, Vladimir P., and G. G. Silnitsky. 1973. The typology of morphological and lexical causatives. In Trends in Soviet theoretical linguistics, ed. Ferenc Kiefer, 1–32. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Paolillo, John C. 1992. Functional articulation in diglossia: A case study of grammatical and social correspondences in Sinhala. PhD diss., Stanford University, Stanford.

  • Paolillo, John C. 1997. Sinhala diglossic variation: Continuous or discrete? Language in Society 26: 269–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, Terence. 1990. Events in the semantics of English: A study in subatomic semantics. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perlmutter, David. 1978. Impersonal passives and the unaccusative hypothesis. In BLS 4, 157–189. Berkeley: UC Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piñón, Christopher. 2001a. A finer look at the causative-inchoative alternation. In SALT XI. Ithaca: Cornell Linguistics Circle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piñón, Christopher. 2001b. Modelling the causative-inchoative alternation. Linguistische Arbeitsberichte 76: 273–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, Elizabeth W., Robert Pargetter, and Frank Jackson. 1982. Three theses about dispositions. American Philosophical Quarterly 19: 251–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylkkänen, Liina. 2008. Introducing arguments. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rappaport Hovav, Malka, and Beth Levin. 1998. Building verb meanings. In The projection of arguments: Lexical and compositional factors, eds. Miriam Butt and Wilhelm Geuder, 97–133. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinhart, Tanya. 2000. The theta system: Syntactic realization of verbal concepts. In OTS working papers in linguistics, 267–310. Utrecht Institute of Linguistics, University of Utrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinhart, Tanya. 2002. The theta system—an overview. Theoretical Linguistics 28: 229–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roeper, Thomas. 1987. Implicit arguments and the head-complement relation. Linguistic Inquiry.

  • Schäfer, Florian. 2008. The syntax of (anti-)causatives: External arguments in change-of-state contexts. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schäfer, Florian. 2009. The causative alternation. Language and Linguistics Compass 3: 641–681.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siewierska, Anna. 1984. The passive: A comparative linguistic analysis. London: Croom Helm.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sigurðsson, Halldór Ármann. 2005. Accusative and the nom/acc alternation in Germanic. Working Papers in Scandinavian Syntax 76: 93–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Carlota. 1970. Jespersen’s ‘move and change’ class and causative verbs in English. In Linguistics and literary studies in honor of Archibald A. Hill, eds. Mohammad A. Jazayery, Edger C. Polomé, and Werner Winter, 101–109. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talmy, Leonard. 1996. The windowing of attention in language. In Grammatical constructions: Their form and meaning, eds. Masayoshi Shibatani and Sandra A. Thompson, 235–288. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talmy, Leonard. 2000. Toward a cognitive semantics: Typology and process in concept structuring. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Oosten, Jeanne. 1977. Subjects and agenthood in English. In CLS 13, eds. Woodford A. Beach, Samuel E. Fox, and Shulamith Philosoph, 451–471.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Valin, Robert D., and David P. Wilkins. 1996. The case for ‘effector’: Case roles, agents, and agency revisited. In Grammatical constructions: Their form and meaning, eds. Masayoshi Shibatani and Sandra A. Thompson, 289–322. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wijayawardhana, G. D., Daya Wickramasinghe, and Theodora Bynon. 1991. Passive-related constructions in Colloquial Sinhala. In Subject, voice and ergativity, eds. David C. Bennet, Theodora Bynon, and B. George Hewitt, 105–141. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, Philip. 2007. Representing causation. Journal of Experimental Psychology 136: 82–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, Philip, Aron K. Barbey, and Matthew Hausknecht. 2010. For want of a nail: How absences cause events. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 139: 191–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, Phillip. 2003. Direct causation in the linguistic encoding and individuation of causal events. Cognition 88: 1–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, Phillip, and Grace Song. 2003. Models of causation and the semantics of causal verbs. Cognitive Psychology 27: 276–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zubair, Cala. 2008. Doxastic modality as a means of stance taking in Colloquial Sinhala. In Proceedings of SALSA 16, eds. Amy Brown and Josh Iorio, 174–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zubair, Cala. 2011. Ethnolinguistic nationalism among Sri Lankan university youth. PhD diss., Georgetown University, Washington, DC.

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to especially thank our informants, who spent many hours graciously discussing Sinhala verbs: Harendra Alwis, Dhanusha Amarasinghe, Kenneth DeAbrew, Manjula Dissanayake, Sahan Dissanayake, Shazard Izzadeen, Aruni Liyanage, and Khalid Zubair. We would also like to offer a special thanks to Beth Levin, Farzan Zaheed, and three anonymous NLLT reviewers for their extensive comments on an earlier draft, and Andrew Koontz-Garboden in particular for detailed comments on an earlier draft and extensive discussion that helped refine the ideas here. In addition, we thank Patrick Brandt, Alexis Dimitriadis, Donna Gerdts, Paul Kroeger, Jean-Pierre Koenig, John Peterson, Chris Piñón, György Rákosi, Bettina Zeisler, and audiences at the 2008 LSA Annual Meeting, the 2008 Cologne Workshop on Transitivity, the 2010 Paris Conference on Events and Subevents, and the 2012 Debrecen Workshop on Argument Structure for feedback on earlier versions of this work, though not all of their comments could be incorporated. Any errors or omissions are of course our own responsibility.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Beavers.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Beavers, J., Zubair, C. Anticausatives in Sinhala: involitivity and causer suppression. Nat Lang Linguist Theory 31, 1–46 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-012-9182-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-012-9182-4

Keywords

Navigation