Skip to main content
Log in

Defining disease in the context of overdiagnosis

  • Scientifc Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recently, concerns have been raised about the phenomenon of ‘overdiagnosis’, the diagnosis of a condition that is not causing harm, and will not come to cause harm. Along with practical, ethical, and scientific questions, overdiagnosis raises questions about our concept of disease. In this paper, we analyse overdiagnosis as an epistemic problem and show how it challenges many existing accounts of disease. In particular, it raises questions about conceptual links drawn between disease and dysfunction, harm, and risk. We argue that ‘disease’ should be considered a vague concept with a non-classical structure. On this view, overdiagnosed cases are ‘borderline’ cases of disease, falling in the zone between cases that are clearly disease, and cases that are clearly not disease. We then develop a précising definition of disease designed to provide practical help in preventing and limiting overdiagnosis. We argue that for this purpose, we can define disease as dysfunction that has a significant risk of causing severe harm to the patient.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. How to define overdiagnosis is under dispute. Welch et al. (2011, xiv) define it as occurring “when individuals are diagnosed with conditions that will never cause symptoms or death”. Carter et al define it by saying “An (asymptomatic) person is diagnosed with a condition; that diagnosis does not produce a net benefit for that person” (2015). The reference to net benefit in some definitions may be problematic since ‘diagnoses that do not result in net benefit’ would capture a broader range of cases where there are unintended iatrogenic harms (see Rogers and Mintzker 2016). Some also allow that overdiagnosis can happen to patients with symptoms. We clarify this rough statement in the discussion in the “Overdiagnosis” section.

  2. The term has sometimes been used in a broad sense, to include a set of related problems such as medicalisation, and overtreatment, as well as in the narrower sense we focus on here. See Carter et al (2015); Moynihan, Doust, and Henry (2012).

  3. We limit our discussion to physical disease, as psychiatric disease raises further complexities that are outside our current scope.

  4. For example, while there is some evidence indicating that mammography screening programs can reduce deaths from breast cancer when targeted at women aged 50–69 (Barratt 2015), this is not the case for breast cancer screening that involves women younger that 50 (Autier 2015) or older than 70 (Glas et al 2014).

  5. These are not mutually exclusive types as there are cases where both misclassification and maldetection occur, such as pulmonary embolism.

  6. This is perhaps the difference between overdiagnosis and other cases where a diagnosis causes overall net harm to a patient (see note 1): in overdiagnosis, the condition diagnosed seems to be the same as cases where a diagnosis will benefit the patient. This could indicate that it is the epistemic problems that are definitive of overdiagnosis, though we do not argue this here.

  7. Here we are using ‘metaphysical indeterminacy’ to refer to open causal chains from the currently identified abnormal state, and its future progression or non-progression (we ignore the possibility of metaphysical determinism for the purposes of this paper). We note that this differs from the way that Hofmann (2016) uses ‘indeterminacy’ to refer to the social question of whether or not a condition comes to be considered a disease through the process of medicalisation (i.e. whether some conditions are diseases is resolved by social and political processes rather than by appeal to underlying biological processes). Thus we are not here disputing Hofmann’s analysis of the differences between medicalisation and overdiagnosis.

  8. We thank an anonymous reviewer for reminding us of this point.

  9. We use ‘dysfunction’ in Boorse’s naturalistic sense here and throughout the paper.

  10. It also challenges the link to the imperative to intervene that some have emphasised (e.g., Engelhardt 1975). We leave this aside in this section, as we consider it linked to the features of harm and increased risk of harm.

  11. We will ultimately depart from these theories, in arguing below that ‘disease’ is a vague concept that is not classically structured.

  12. This feature of the BST is demonstrated in the ‘one dead cell’ objection: that the BST implies disease is present where there is just one dead cell, since that cell is failing to make its species-typical contribution to the biological goals of the organism, even if there is no noticeable change in overall functioning (Nordenfelt 1987, 28, cited in Wakefield 2014, 656). Boorse accepts this implication for tissues that do not usually involve regular cell death and regeneration (1987, 365, in Wakefield 2014, 656). For tissues that do involve regular cell death and regeneration, he indicates that one dead cell would not be pathological since it is not statistically atypical (1997, 50–51). Correlatively, one might say that if it turns out to be normal to have microscopic thyroid cancers, or other lesions, they are not disease on the BST. However, Boorse also accepts that there are some ‘universal’ diseases, such as tooth decay, and his ways of dealing with those would also apply to universal maldetected cancers. We leave further discussion of this aside since our focus is assessing the relevance of dysfunction to disease, not statistical frequency.

  13. This is not a satisfying answer since on his theory what counts as a functional deficit is supposed to respond only to the standard of statistical frequency (for more detail on this problem, see Schwartz 2007a). In any case, there does not seem any obvious cut-off point at which the dysfunction involved should be thought unusual enough to indicate the presence of disease.

  14. ‘Harm’ may of course refer to a range of things, including pain and suffering, incapacity, or presence of symptoms. Though we recognise that there are various ways these things might come apart, we will discuss incapacity, pain and suffering simply as ‘harms’ in what follows for reasons of space.

  15. Wakefield uses ‘disorder’ rather than ‘disease’, but states that the term fulfils a similar role in his account to ‘disease’ in other parts of the debate. We thus alter his terminology here for consistency.

  16. One might also think that the presence of such dysfunction itself constitutes a harm. We leave this aside since it could lead to an elision of the two criteria. Thus we are considering harm as an evaluative and not biological notion.

  17. See Schwartz (2007b, 50–56), for a detailed demonstration of how this assumption has influenced the kinds of definitions that have been offered, and the way they are developed, in the philosophical debate on disease definition.

  18. A more detailed discussion of these matters is available in Walker and Rogers (forthcoming b).

  19. One response to this is to consider all of these cases to be disease, and make distinctions about the severity of that disease. Another is to claim that disease itself could be a matter of degree. We do not seek to resolve here which is the preferable response. For a detailed discussion see Rogers and Walker (forthcoming).

  20. Though we focus on physical disease, our précising definition may be of value in conceptualising psychiatric overdiagnosis.

  21. These parameters could, for instance include specified kinds or amounts of dysfunction, as well as certain minimum levels of risk. How and by whom these parameters would be set is a further issue that we will not engage with here.

References

  • Armstrong, D. 1995. The rise of surveillance medicine. Sociology of Health & Illness 17(3): 393–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Autier, P. 2015. Doubtful health benefit of screening from 40 years of age. Nature Reviews Clinical Oncology 12: 570–572. doi:10.1038/nrclinonc.2015.162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barratt, A. 2015. Overdiagnosis in mammography screening: A 45-year journey from shadowy idea to acknowledged reality. BMJ 350: h867.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, W.C. 1998. Advances in radiology and the real versus apparent effects of early diagnosis. European Journal of Radiology 27: 116–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. 1976. Wright on functions. Philosophical Review 85(1): 70–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. 1977. Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science 44: 542–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. 1997. A rebuttal on health. In What is disease?, ed. J. Humber, and R. Almeder, 3–134. New Jersey: Humana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, S.M., W. Rogers, I. Heath, C. Degeling, J. Doust, and A. Barratt. 2015. The challenge of overdiagnosis begins with its definition. BMJ 350: h869.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coon, E.R., R.A. Quinonez, V.A. Moyer, and A.R. Schroeder. 2014. Overdiagnosis: How our compulsion for diagnosis may be harming children. Pediatrics. doi:10.1542/peds.2014-1778.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, H.T. 1975. The concepts of health and disease. In Evaluation and explanation in the biomedical sciences, ed. H.T. Engelhardt, and S.F. Spicker, 125–141. Dordrecht: D Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Esserman, L.J., I.M. Thompson, and B. Reid. 2013. Overdiagnosis and overtreatment in cancer: An opportunity for improvement. Journal of the American Medical Association 310(8): 797–798.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esserman, L.J., I.M. Thompson, B. Reid, P. Nelson, D.F. Ransohoff, H.G. Welch, S. Hwang, D.A. Berry, K.W. Kinsler, W.C. Black, M. Bissell, H. Parnes, and S. Srivastava. 2014. Addressing overdiagnosis and overtreatment in cancer: A prescription for change. Lancet Oncology 15: e234–e242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glas, N.A., et al. 2014. Effect of implementation of the mass breast cancer screening programme in older women in the Netherlands: Population based study. BMJ 349: g5410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godlee, F. 2012. Preventing overdiagnosis. BMJ 344: e3973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harach, H.R., K.O. Franssila, and V. Wasenius. 1985. Occult papillary carcinoma of the thyroid: A “normal” finding in Finland. A systematic autopsy study. Cancer 56(3): 531–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hersch, J., J. Janson, A. Barrat, L. Irwig, N. Houssami, K. Howard, H. Dhillon, and K. McCaffery. 2013. Women’s views on overdiagnosis in breast cancer screening: A qualitative study. BMJ 346: f158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoda, U. 2014. Overdiagnosis of pulmonary emboli by CT pulmonary angiograms. Thorax 69: 925.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofmann, B. 2013. Diagnosing overdiagnosis: Conceptual challenges and suggested solutions. European Journal of Epidemiology 29: 599–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofmann, B. 2016. Medicalization and overdiagnosis: Different but alike. Medicine, Healthcare and Philosophy 19(2): 253–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E., and S. Laurence. 1999. Concepts and cognitive science. In Concepts, ed. E. Margolis, and S. Laurence, 3–81. New Jersey: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moynihan, R.N., G.P.E. Cooke, J.A. Doust, L. Bero, S. Hill, and P.P. Glasziou. 2013. Expanding disease definitions in guidelines and expert panel ties to industry: A cross-sectional study of common conditions in the United States. PLOS Medicine 10(8): e1001500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moynihan, R., J. Doust, and D. Henry. 2012. Preventing overdiagnosis: How to stop harming the healthy. BMJ 344: e3502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moynihan, R., D. Henry, and K.G.M. Moons. 2014. Using evidence to combat overdiagnosis and overtreatment: Evaluating treatments, tests, and disease definitions in the time of too much. PLoS Medicine 11(7): e1001655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordby, H. 2007. The analytic-synthetic distinction and conceptual analysis of basic health concepts. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 9: 169–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordenfelt, L. 1987. On the Nature of health: An action-theoretic approach. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nordenfelt, L. 1993. Concepts of health and their consequences for health care. Theoretical Medicine 14: 277–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, T.G. 2006. Now we are sick: Labelling and hypertension. Journal of Clinical Hypertension 8(1): 57–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, W.A., and Y. Mintzker. 2016. Getting clearer on overdiagnosis. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 22(4): 580–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, W.A., Walker, M.J. Forthcoming. The line drawing problem in defining disease. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy.

  • Sadegh-Zadeh, K. 2000. Fuzzy health, illness, and disease. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25: 605–638.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sadegh-Zadeh, K. 2008. The prototype resemblance theory of disease. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 33: 106–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, P.H. 2004. An alternative to conceptual analysis in the function debate. Monist 87(1): 136–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, P.H. 2007a. Defining dysfunction: Natural selection, design, and drawing a line. Philosophy of Science 74: 364–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, P.H. 2007b. Decision and discovery in defining disease. In Establishing medical reality, ed. H. Kincaid, and J. McKitrick, 47–63. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, P.H. 2008. Risk and disease. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 51: 320–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, E., E. Shoben, and L.J. Rips. 1974. Structure and process in semantic memory: A featural model for semantic decisions. Psychological Review 81(3): 214–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. 2014. The biostatistical theory versus the harmful dysfunction analysis, Part 1: Is dysfunction a sufficient condition for medical disorder? Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 39: 648–682.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walker, M.J., Rogers, W.A. Forthcoming (a). Diagnosis, narrative identity, and asymptomatic disease. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics.

  • Walker, M.J., Rogers, W.A. Forthcoming (b). A new approach to defining disease. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy.

  • Welch, H.G., L. Schwartz, and S. Woloshin. 2011. Overdiagnosed: Making people sick in the pursuit of health. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1953. Philosophical Investigations, trans. G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Worrall, J., and J. Worrall. 2001. Defining disease: Much ado about nothing? Analecta Husserliana 72: 33–56.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Work on this paper was funded by Australian Research Council FT130100346, awarded to Professor Wendy Rogers. Our thanks to Wylie Breckenridge, Tom Campbell, Steve Clarke, Daniel Cohen, Alberto Giubilini, Matthew Kopec, Emma Rush, and Suzanne Uniacke, for comments on an earlier version.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mary Jean Walker.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Walker, M.J., Rogers, W. Defining disease in the context of overdiagnosis. Med Health Care and Philos 20, 269–280 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-016-9748-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-016-9748-8

Keywords

Navigation