Skip to main content
Log in

Does the ethical appropriateness of paying donors depend on what body parts they donate?

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The idea of paying donors in order to make more human bodily material available for therapy, assisted reproduction, and biomedical research is notoriously controversial. However, while national and international donation policies largely oppose financial incentives they do not treat all parts of the body equally: incentives are allowed in connection to the provision of some parts but not others. Taking off from this observation, I discuss whether body parts differ as regards the ethical legitimacy of incentives and, if so, why. I distinguish two approaches to this issue. On a “principled” approach, some but not all body parts are inherently special in a way that proscribes payment. On a “pragmatic” approach, the appropriateness of payment in relation to a specific part must be determined through an overall assessment of e.g. the implications of payment for the health and welfare of providers, recipients, and third parties, and the quality of providers’ consent. I argue that the first approach raises deep and potentially divisive questions about the good life, whereas the second approach invokes currently unsupported empirical assumptions and requires difficult balancing between different values and the interests of different people. This does not mean that any attempt to distinguish between body parts in regard to the appropriateness of payment necessarily fails. However, I conclude, any plausible such attempt should either articulate and defend a specific view of the good life, or gather relevant empirical evidence and apply defensible principles for weighing goods and interests.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I will henceforth use the term ‘provider’ rather than ‘donor’, which has connotations to altruism that may be misleading when money is offered in exchange for what is provided.

  2. Thus, while scholarly debates about paid donation revolve around something like what Eyal calls “body exceptionalism”, i.e. “the view that we should treat the body…differently than we do material resources” (Eyal 2009: 234), there has been little attention in this context to what we might call “body parts exceptionalism”, i.e. the view that certain (but not all) parts of the body warrant such treatment.

  3. These include Spain, Greece, and Ukraine (eggs), Germany (blood), and several states in the US (eggs, sperm, plasma, and bone marrow) (Almeling 2011; NCoB 2011; Williams 2011; Pennings et al. 2014; Harvey 2015). By ‘reward’ I mean payment that (de facto or de jure) “goes beyond ‘recompensing’ the person for the losses incurred in donating” (NCoB 2011: 70).

  4. Thus, my argument is located at a somewhat higher level of abstraction than analyses of the ethics of payment in relation to specific body parts typically are. But it is less abstracted than Fabre’s (2006) excellent exploration of the status of the body in “ideal theory”, where it is assumed that agents fully comply with the demands of justice. By contrast, my discussion explores ethical quandaries arising in our current, decidedly non-ideal world.

  5. Kant is sometimes attributed the first of these views because of his condemnation of all bodily commodification (including of hair and teeth) in his Lectures on Ethics (Kant 1997a), but it is debatable whether this condemnation reflects his philosophy or the prejudices of his time. Andrews (1986) provides a robust defence of the view of the body as personal property, but stops short of endorsing the commodification of all its parts.

  6. Almeling’s (2011) finding that US egg donors explicitly dissociate themselves from their eggs may seem to contradict this assumption, but this dissociation is more reflective of the interests and rhetoric of egg agencies than of some general cultural pattern of identification.

  7. Some such idea underlies the familiar”four principles” approach to bioethics (Beauchamp and Childress 2012), for instance. Largely on the basis of what I here call pragmatic considerations, this approach seeks to articulate ethical principles that people can in principle agree on despite deep normative and metaphysical disagreements.

  8. Since all potentially relevant pragmatic considerations cannot be covered in one paper my discussion will be selective. I will leave out concerns about exploitation, for instance. Although such concerns loom large in this context, they partly overlap with principled concerns of the kind discussed above and/or with the concerns about harm and consent discussed below, and when they do not overlap with such concerns it is unclear whether they support policies against payment (Wilkinson 2003). Also, my discussion of societal consequences will be limited to “crowding out” effects. There may well be other such consequences that matter to the legitimacy of payment, e.g. social and legal pressures on providers that the normalization of payment may create (Andrews 1986; Rippon 2014). But these effects are likely to vary between institutional and cultural contexts at least as much as between body parts, making them difficult to consider on the level of abstraction where my argument proceeds.

  9. There seem to be no studies that directly compare socioeconomic profiles of paid providers across several different body parts and risk/payment levels, and available information on providers of specific parts does not admit of the generalizations and comparisons needed to support this assumption. While poor populations seem to be overrepresented among paid providers in certain settings (Naqvi et al. 2007; Cooper and Waldby 2014), it is unclear that they are (or would be) more overrepresented when the risk/payment is higher.

  10. Some believe that the real worry about inducement is not that it threatens consent but that it might encourage people to overcome their deeply held values. On this account, it is disrespectful to pay people to do things that they have strong objections against, even if the money does not impair their judgment or the voluntariness of their decision (Dickert and Grady 2008). This account is plausible, but it cannot be invoked in support of the argument considered here because it has nothing to do with the level of payment. It seems no less disrespectful to offer somebody a small sum for a pint of blood than a large sum for a kidney if that person has strong objections against donating both.

  11. This support would be strengthened if higher payment could be assumed to attract a larger proportion of poor providers than lower payment because the poor are likely to be especially vulnerable to such pressure (Malmqvist 2015). However, as we have already seen, this is an empirical assumption that has to be backed up by evidence that currently seems unavailable.

  12. I cannot here defend Titmuss’ argument but only explore its implications for the question at hand. For a compelling explication and defence of this argument, see Archard (2002).

  13. In principle any general such conception—utilitarianism, egalitarianism, prioritarianism, etc.—is applicable here. Determining which one is preferable in this context is beyond the scope of this paper.

References

  • Almeling, R. 2011. Sex cells: The medical market for eggs and sperm. Berkely: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, L. 1986. My body, my property. Hastings Center Report 16(5): 28–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Archard, D. 2002. Selling yourself: Titmuss’s argument against a market in blood. The Journal of Ethics 6: 87–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1980. Nicomachean ethics. (trans: Ross W.D) Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Beauchamp, T.L., and J.F. Childress. 2012. Principles of biomedical ethics, 7th ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • CIOMS (Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences). 2002. International ethical guidelines for biomedical research involving human subjects. Geneva: CIOMS/WHO.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, C.B. 1999. Selling bits and pieces of humans to make babies: The gift of the magi revisited. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 24: 288–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, M., and C. Waldby. 2014. Clinical labor: Tissue donors and research subjects in the global bioeconomy. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dickert, N., and C. Grady. 2008. Incentives for research participants. In The Oxford textbook of clinical research ethics, ed. E.J. Emanuel, C.C. Grady, R.A. Crouch, et al., 386–396. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eyal, N. 2009. Is the body special? Review of Cécile Fabre, Whose body is it anyway? Justice and the integrity of the person. Utilitas 21: 233–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fabre, C. 2006. Whose body is it anyway? Justice and the integrity of the person. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gneezy, U., and A. Rustichini. 2000. A fine is a price. Journal of Legal Studies 29: 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goyal, M., R.L. Mehta, L.J. Schneiderman, et al. 2002. Economic and health consequences of selling a kidney in India. Journal of the American Medical Association 288: 1589–1592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, J. 2015. Blood money: Is it wrong to pay donors? The Guardian. http://www.theguardian.com/lifeandstyle/2015/jan/25/wrong-to-pay-blood-donors-safety-compromised. Accessed 25 Apr 2016.

  • Kant, I. 1997a. Lectures on ethics. (trans. Heath P.) Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kant, I. 1997b. Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. (trans. Gregor M.J.). Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.

  • Koplin, J. 2014. Assessing the likely harms to kidney vendors in regulated organ markets. American Journal of Bioethics 14(10): 7–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lundin, S. 2012. Organ economy: Organ trafficking in Moldova and Israel. Public Understanding of Science 21: 226–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malmqvist, E. 2014. Are bans on kidney sales unjustifiably paternalistic? Bioethics 28: 110–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malmqvist, E. 2015. Kidney sales and the analogy with dangerous employment. Health Care Analysis 23: 107–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malmqvist, E., and K. Zeiler. 2016. Bodily exchanges, bioethics and border crossing: Perspectives on giving, selling and sharing bodies. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. 2002. Phenomenology of perception. (trans. Smith C.). London: Routledge.

  • Naqvi, S.A.A., B. Ali, F. Mahzar, M.N. Zafar, and S.A.H. Rizvi. 2007. A socioeconomic survey of kidney vendors in Pakistan. Transplant International 20: 934–939.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • NCoB (Nuffield Council on Bioethics). 2011. Human bodies: Donation for medicine and research. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M.C. 1992. Human functioning and social justice: In defense of Aristotelian essentialism. Political Theory 20: 202–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M.C. 1995. Objectification. Philosophy and Public Affairs 24: 249–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennings, G., J. de Mouzon, F. Shenfield, et al. 2014. Socio-demographic and fertility-related characteristics and motivations of oocyte donors in 11 European countries including supplementary file. Human Reproduction 29: 1076–1089.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radin, M.J. 1996. Contested commodities: The trouble with trade in sex, body parts, and other things. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rippon, S. 2014. Imposing options on people in poverty: The harm of a live donor organ market. Journal of Medical Ethics 40: 145–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, C., and K. Throsby. 2008. Paid to share: IVF patients, eggs and stem cell research. Social Science and Medicine 66: 159–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothman, S.M., and D.J. Rothman. 2006. The hidden cost of organ sale. American Journal of Transplantation 6: 1524–1528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheper-Hughes, N. 2007. The tyranny of the gift: Sacrificial violence in living donor transplants. American Journal of Transplantation 7: 507–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Svenaeus, F. 2012. Organ transplantation and personal identity: How does loss and change of organs affect the self? Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 37: 139–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Svenaeus, F. 2016. The lived body and personal identity: The ontology of exiled body parts. In Bodily exchanges, bioethics and border crossing: Perspectives on giving, selling and sharing bodies, ed. E. Malmqvist, and K. Zeiler, 19–34. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Titmuss, R.M. 1970. The gift relationship: From human blood to social policy. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tong, A., J.R. Chapman, G. Wong, et al. 2012. The experiences of commercial kidney donors: Thematic synthesis of qualitative research. Transplant International 25: 1138–1149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • WHO. 2010. Guiding principles on human cell, tissue and organ transplantation. http://www.who.int/transplantation/Guiding_PrinciplesTransplantation_WHA63.22en.pdf.

  • Wilkinson, S. 2003. Bodies for sale: Ethics and exploitation in the human body trade. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, C. 2011. Pay ban on donor organs doesn’t include bone marrow, court says. Los Angeles Times, Dec 2, 2011.

  • Zargooshi, J. 2001. Quality of life of Iranian kidney “donors”. Journal of Urology 166(5): 1790–1799.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Erica Haimes and Ken Taylor for the opportunity to present an early version of this paper at the 16th PEALS International Symposium in Newcastle, UK, September 22–23, 2015, and other participants in the symposium for valuable feedback. I am also grateful to Lisa Guntram, Hanna Van Parys, András Szigeti, Martin Andersson, and two anonymous reviewers for this journal for helpful comments on later versions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Erik Malmqvist.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Malmqvist, E. Does the ethical appropriateness of paying donors depend on what body parts they donate?. Med Health Care and Philos 19, 463–473 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-016-9705-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-016-9705-6

Keywords

Navigation