Skip to main content
Log in

Body matters: rethinking the ethical acceptability of non-beneficial clinical research with children

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

An Erratum to this article was published on 20 December 2014

Abstract

The involvement of children in non-beneficial clinical research is extremely important for improving pediatric care, but its ethical acceptability is still disputed. Therefore, various pro-research justifications have been proposed throughout the years. The present essay aims at contributing to the on-going discussion surrounding children’s participation in non-beneficial clinical research. Building on Wendler’s ‘contribution to a valuable project’ justification, but going beyond a risk/benefit analysis, it articulates a pro-research argument which appeals to a phenomenological view on the body and vulnerability. It is claimed that children’s bodies are not mere physical objects, but body-subjects due to which children, as persons, can contribute to research that may hold no direct clinical benefit to them even before they can give informed consent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This principle is described as the secure child standard and clearly distinguished from the best interest standard which they think is incompatible with non-beneficial research.

  2. To a certain extent Ramsey’s position is more complex: he thinks that pediatric research for the benefit of others is unethical, but allowable if investigators “err bravely” (1976, p. 21). He believes that if researchers are critically aware of the fact that what they are doing is wrong then research will go on, but in a cautious way (Wendler 2010, p. 281).

  3. The aids epidemic presented the pharmaceutical industry with the opportunity to loosen regulations regarding drug evaluation as aids activists sought immediate approval of potential life-saving experimental drugs (Sharav 2003, p. 15).

  4. Although, it is widely held that children should not participate in research that poses greater than a minor increase over minimal risk and does not offer the prospect of direct benefit, U.S. regulations include a category for pediatric research (407/50.54 category) that does not include an explicit limit on risks, raising the question of whether current regulations provide sufficient protection for pediatric research subjects. Since this type of research is only permitted in extremely rare circumstance, we will not discuss it any further here. For a recent critical reflection see Wendler (2013, pp. 1–8).

  5. They develop this interesting critique in regard to the moral development argument, but in our opinion it can also be applied to Wendler’s analysis.

  6. That is not to deny that social research can be ethically problematic (e.g. research on domestic violence, neglect, abuse, pediatric disorders, etc.). The point is rather that children’s participation in social research is not ipso facto problematic. In fact, a great deal of social research (such as on nutrition, life style, school etc.) is often considered quite mainstream.

References

  • Ackerman, T.F. 1980. Moral duties of parents and nontherapeutic clinical research procedures involving children. Bioethics Quarterly 2(2): 94–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartholome, W. 1976. Parens, children and the moral benefits of research. Hastings Center Report 6(6): 44–45.

  • Beecher, H. 1966. Ethics and clinical research. New England Journal of Medicine 274: 1354–1360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T.L., and J.F. Childress. 1979. Principles of biomedical ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brock, D.W. 1994. Ethical issues in exposing children to risks in research. In Children as research subjects: Science, ethics and law, ed. M.A. Grodin, and L.H. Glantz, 81–102. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brook, G. 2000. Children’s competency to consent: A framework for practice: In the first of two articles, Gill Brook introduces a framework of practice designed to help children to make choices in their treatment and care with their parents. Paediatric Care 12: 31–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broström, L., and M. Johansson. 2014. Involving children in non-therapeutic research: on the development argument. Medical Health Care Philosophy 17: 53–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burwood, S. 2008. The apparent truth of dualism and the uncanny body. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7: 263–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, A.V. 2009. The body in bioethics. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, T.M., and M.P. Gutmann. 2011. The limits of autonomy: The Belmont report and the history of childhood. Journal of the History of Medicine and Allied Studies 66(1): 82–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cavarero, A. 2009. Horrorism: Naming contemporary violence. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, C.H. 2009. Vulnerability as regulatory category in human subject research. Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 37(1): 12–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curran, W.J., and H.K. Beecher. 1969. Experimentation in children. A reexamination of legal ethical principles. JAMA (Journal of the American Medical Association) 210: 77–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickenson, D. 2007. Property in the body. Feminist perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, S.D. 2012. Safeguarding children in clinical research. Nursing Ethics 19(4): 530–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fineman, M.A. 2008. The vulnerable subject: Anchoring equality in the human condition. Yale Journal of Law and Feminism 20(1): 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fingerson, L. 2011. Children’s Bodies. In The Palgrave handbook of childhood studies, ed. J. Qvortrup, W.A. Corsaro, and M.-S. Honig, 217–227. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman Ross, L. 2003. Do Healthy children deserve greater protection in medical research. Journal of Pediatrics 142: 108–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman Ross, L. 2004. Children in medical research: Balancing protection and access: Has the pendulum swung too far? Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 47(4): 519–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. 2005. Scientific research is a moral duty. Journal of Medical Ethics 31(4): 242–248.

  • Hurst, S.A. 2008. Vulnerability in research and health care. Describing the elephant in the room? Bioethics 22(4): 191–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kipnis, K. 2003. Seven vulnerabilities in the pediatric research subject. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 24(2): 107–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kottow, M. 2003. The vulnerable and the susceptible. Bioethics 17(5–6): 460–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kottow, M. 2005. Vulnerability: What kind of principle is it. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 7(3): 281–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kodish, E. 2005. Ethics and research with children. A case-based approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kopelman, L.M. 2004. Minimal risk as an international ethical standard in research. Journal of Medical Philosophy 29(3): 351–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leder, D. 1990. The absent body. Chicago, London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, C., R. Faden, C. Grady, D. Hammerschmidt, L. Eckenwiler, and J. Sugarman. 2004. The limitations of “vulnerability” as a protection of human research participants. The American Journal of Bioethics 4(3): 44–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Litton, P. 2008. Non-beneficial pediatric research and the best interest standard: A legal and ethical reconciliation. Yale Journal of Health Policy, Law and Ethics 359: 361–420.

    Google Scholar 

  • Litton, P. 2012. A more persuasive justification for pediatric research. American Journal of Bioethics 12(1): 44–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luna, F. 2009. Elucidating the concept of vulnerability. Layers not labels. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 2(1): 121–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luna, F., and S. Vanderpoel. 2013. Not the usual suspects: Addressing layers of vulnerability. Bioethics 27(6): 325–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, C., and N. Stoljar. 2000. Introduction. Autonomy reconfigured. In Relational autonomy. Feminist perspectives on autonomy, agency and the social self, ed. C. Mackenzie, and N. Stoljar, 3–31. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, C. 2010. Conceptions of the body and conceptions of autonomy in bioethics. In Feminist bioethics: At the center, on the margins, ed. J.L. Scully, L. Baldwin-Ragaven, and P. Fitzpatrick, 71–90. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCormick, R.A. 1976. Experimentation in children: Sharing in sociality. Hastings Center Report 6: 41–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, T. 1996. The moral worth of a child. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. 2002. Autonomy and trust in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Petrăo Neves, M. 2009. Respect for human vulnerability and personal integrity. In UNESCO universal declaration on bioethics and human rights. Background, principles and application, ed. H.A.M. ten Have, and M.S. Jean, 155–164. Paris: UNESCO.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piasecki, J., M. Waligora and V. Dranseika. 2014. Non-beneficial pediatric research: Individual and social interests. Medical Health Care and Philosophy (Epub ahead of print).

  • Ramsey, P. 1970. The patient as person: Explorations in medical ethics. New Haven/London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rendtorff, J.D., and P. Kemp. 2000. Basic ethical principles in European bioethics and biolaw, autonomy, dignity, integrity and vulnerability, I–II ed. Barcelona/Copenhagen: Center for Ethics and Law.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, D.B. 2005. Eliminating the daily life risks standard from the definition of minimal risk. Journal of Medical Ethics 31(1): 35–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. 1992. Oneself as another. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, W. M. and B. T. Unruh. 2008. The hepatitis experiments at the Willowbrook state school. In The Oxford textbook of clinical research ethics, ed. J. E. Ezekiel, 80-85. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Rogers, W., C. Mackenzie and S. Dodds. 2012. Why bioethics needs a concept of vulnerability. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics. Special issue on vulnerability 5(2): 11–38.

  • Roth-Cline, M., J. Gerson, et al. 2011. Ethical considerations in conducting pediatric research. In Handbook of experimental pharmacology, vol. 205, ed. H. Seyberth, A. Rane, and M. Schwab, 219–244. Heidelberg/Dordrecht/London/New York: Springer Verlag.

  • Schroeder, D., and E. Gefenas. 2009. Vulnerability: Too vague and too broad. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 18: 113–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, S., A. Whittle, B. Wilfond, G. Gensler, and D. Wendler. 2004. How do institutional review boards apply the federal risk and benefit standards for pediatric research? Journal of the American Medical Association 291(4): 476–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, S. 2013. Does research with children violate the best interest standard? An empirical and conceptual analysis. Northwestern Journal of Law and Social Policy 8(2): 121–173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharav, V.H. 2003. Children in clinical research: A conflict of moral values. The American Journal of Bioethics 3(1): 12–59.

  • Shildrick, M., and R. Mykitiuk (eds.). 2005. Ethics of the body. Postconventional challenges. Massachusetts: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shirkey, H. 1968. Therapeutic orphans. Journal of Pediatrics 72(1): 119–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P.B. 1990. Risk objectivism and risk subjectivism: When are risks real? Issues in Health and Safety 1: 3–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, B.S. 2006. Vulnerability and human rights. Pennsylvania: Penn State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veatch, R.M. 1987. The Patients as partner. A theory of human experimentation ethics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wachbroit, R. 2012. On Wendler’s new justification for pediatric research. The American Journal of Bioethics 12(1): 40–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisstub, D.N. 1998. Roles in clincal and research ethics. In Research on human subjects. Ethics, law and social policy, ed. D.N. Weisstub, 56–72. Oxford: Pergamon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisstub, D.N., S.N. Verdun-Jones, and J. Walker. 1998. Biomedical experimentation with children: Balancing the need for protective measures with the need to respect children’s developing ability to make significant life decisions for themselves. In Research on human subjects. Ethics, law and social policy, ed. D.N. Weisstub, 380–432. Oxford: Pergamon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendler, D. 2009. Minimal risk in pediatric research as a function of age. Archives of Pediatrics & Adolescent Medicine 163(2): 115–118.

  • Wendler, D. 2010. The ethics of pediatric research. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wendler, D. 2012. A new justification for pediatric research without the potential for clinical benefit. The American Journal of Bioethics 12(1): 23–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wendler, D. 2013. Does U.S regulations allow for more than minor increase over minimal risk pediatric research? Should they? IRB: Ethics and Human Research 35(6): 1–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendler, D., and S. Shah. 2003. Should children decide whether they are enrolled in nonbeneficial research? The American Journal of Bioethics 3(4): 1–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitty-Rogers, J., M. Alex, C. MacDonald, et al. 2009. Working with children in end-of-life decision-making. Nursing Ethics 16(6): 743–758.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G. 2012. Children as means and ends in large-scale medical research. Bioethics 26(8): 422–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolpe, R.W. 1998. The triumph of autonomy in american bioethics: A sociological view. In Bioethics and society: Constructing the ethical enterprise, ed. R. De Vries, and J. Subedi, 38–59. New York: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eva De Clercq.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

De Clercq, E., Badarau, D.O., Ruhe, K.M. et al. Body matters: rethinking the ethical acceptability of non-beneficial clinical research with children. Med Health Care and Philos 18, 421–431 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-014-9616-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-014-9616-3

Keywords

Navigation