Skip to main content
Log in

Moderate eugenics and human enhancement

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Though the reputation of eugenics has been tarnished by history, eugenics per se is not necessarily a bad thing. Many advocate a liberal new eugenics—where individuals are free to choose whether or not to employ genetic technologies for reproductive purposes. Though genetic interventions aimed at the prevention of severe genetic disorders may be morally and socially acceptable, reproductive liberty in the context of enhancement may conflict with equality. Enhancement could also have adverse effects on utility. The enhancement debate requires a shift in focus. What the equality and/or utility costs of enhancement will be is an empirical question. Rather than philosophical speculation, more social science research is needed to address it. Philosophers, meanwhile, should address head-on the question of how to strike a balance between liberty, equality, and utility in cases of conflict (in the context of genetics).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Kevles’ quote of Dr. Joseph S. DeJarnette, who thought that his state—Virginia, the second ranking sterilization state in the US—. was not sterilizing enough people.

  2. Following Dworkin (1994) I am here using the expression 'religious view' broadly—i.e., to refer to comprehensive outlooks that require leap of faith about debatable matters of central importance (whether or not belief in the existence of God is involved).

  3. I do not mean to here imply that such traits are genetically determined. It is plausible, however, that at least some genetic basis for traits like these will be discovered and/or that correlations between such traits and identifiable genetic sequences will be discovered.

References

  • Agar, N. 2004. Liberal eugenics: In defence of human enhancement. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Black, E. 2003. War against the weak: Eugenics and America’s campaign to create a master race. New York: Four Walls Eight Windows.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. 1977. Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science 44: 542–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourne, H., T. Douglas, and J. Savulescu. 2012. Procreative beneficience and in vitro gametogenesis. Monash Bioethics Review 30(2): 29–48.

    PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A., et al. 2000. From chance to choice: Genetics and justice. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, E.A. 2001. The unfit: A history of a bad idea. Cold Spring Harbor, NY: Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press.

  • Chan, S. and J. Harris. 2007. In Support of Human Enhancement. Studies in Ethics, Law, and Technology. 1:art.10.

  • Dworkin, R. 1994. Life’s dominion. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galton, F. 2004. Essays in eugenics. Honolulu: University Press of the Pacific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galton, F. 2006. Hereditary genius. New York: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. 1981. The mismeasure of man. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haller, M.H. 1963. Eugenics: Hereditarian attitudes in American thought. Rahway: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. 1992. Wonderwoman and Superman: The ethics of biotechnology. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. 2007. Enhancing evolution. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. 2011. Enhancements are a moral obligation. In Human enhancement, ed. J. Savulescu, and N. Bostrom, 131–153. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. 1993. Prenatal screening and its impact on persons with disabilities. Clinical Obstetrics and Gynecology 36(3): 605–612.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kevles, D.J. 1985. In the name of eugenics. Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. 1996. The lives to come: The genetic revolution and human possibilities. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mehlman, M.J. 2003. Wondergenes: Genetic enhancement and the future of society. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mehlman, M.J., and J. Botkin. 1998. Access to the genome: The challenge to equality. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Hill, B. 1988. Murderous science: Elimination by scientific selection of Jews, Gypsies, and others in Germany, 1933–1945. New York: Cold Spring Harbor Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parens, E. 1998. Is better always good? The enhancement project. Hastings Center Report 28: s1–s17.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, D.B. 1998. The politics of heredity: Essays on eugenics, biomedicine, and the nature-nurture debate. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Proctor, R. 1988. Racial hygiene: Medicine under the Nazis. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reilly, Philip R. 1991. The surgical solution: A history of involuntary sterilization in the United States. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, J.A. 1994. Children of choice: Freedom and the new reproductive technologies. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, C. 2004. Preaching eugenics: Religious leaders and the American eugenics movement. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J. 2007. Genetic interventions and the ethics of enhancement of human beings. In The Oxford handbook of bioethics, ed. B. Steinbock, 516–535. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J. 2001. Procreative beneficence: Why we should select the best children. Bioethics 15: 413–426.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Selgelid, M.J. 2001. Eugenic abortion, moral uncertainty, and social consequences. Monash Bioethics Review 20(2): 26–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selgelid, M.J. 2002. Societal decision making and the new eugenics. Bad Neuenahr-Ahrweiler: The European Academy (Europaische Akademie) for the Study of Consequences of Scientific and Technological Advance. Available at: http://www.ea-aw.de/fileadmin/downloads/Graue_Reihe/GR_30_Eugenics_042002.pdf. Accessed 23 May 2013.

  • Selgelid, M.J. 2009. A moderate pluralist approach to public health policy and ethics. Public Health Ethics 2(2): 195–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selgelid, M.J. 2012. Moral uncertainty and the moral status of early human life. Monash Bioethics Review 30(1): 52–57. Available at: http://journals.publishing.monash.edu/ojs/index.php/mber/article/view/882/971. Accessed 23 May 2013.

  • Silver, L.M. 1999. Remaking Eden: Cloning, genetic engineering and the future of human kind. London: Phoenix.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Much of the research for this article was conducted during a 2007 visit to the Brocher Foundation, which I thank for support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael J. Selgelid.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Selgelid, M.J. Moderate eugenics and human enhancement. Med Health Care and Philos 17, 3–12 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-013-9485-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-013-9485-1

Keywords

Navigation