Skip to main content
Log in

DSM diagnosis and beyond: on the need for a hermeneutically-informed biopsychosocial framework

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

While often dubbed “the bible of contemporary psychiatry” and widely hailed as providing “a benchmark” for the profession, on closer inspection the DSM is seen to be shot through with philosophical assumptions that restrict its theoretical cogency and limit it clinical efficacy. Hence, in the interests of enhanced patient-care it is important to think critically about the DSM, with a view to maximising its diagnostic strengths while minimising its weaknesses. The critical analysis undertaken in the present paper underscores the importance of not construing the DSM as a self-contained diagnostic tool but of viewing it, rather, as an indispensable component in a more comprehensive, multidimensional diagnostic process. More specifically, the contention is that the DSM’s diagnostic limitations evoke a biopsychosocial framework of application as their necessary corrective, notwithstanding the entrenched tendency to construe these approaches as oppositional. Further, it is contended that a hermeneutically informed biopsychosocial template has particular advantages as an integrating framework.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The fourth edition of the DSM was published in 1994 (and revised in 2000). However, since the core philosophical presuppositions discussed in this paper were introduced with the publication of DSM-III and to date continue to be its predominant philosophical influences, this diagnostic manual will be referred to here simply as “DSM”, without differentiation between DSM-III and DSM-IV unless the context necessitates a more specific reference.

  2. These criteria are often referred to as “Feighner criteria” after the Washington University psychiatrist who initially formulated them. As delineated by Moller (2008, p. 55), the general formulation is that: “in order to make diagnosis D, the patient must present with Symptom A together with one of the symptoms from the series B, C and E, but symptoms P. and O may not be present”.

  3. Preparations for DSM-V are currently advanced, and publication is anticipated around May 2013.

  4. To set these presuppositions in context and to clarify both how they are interrelated and how they pervade this diagnostic model, it is important at this juncture to register their Kraepelinian origins (i.e. deriving from the groundbreaking conceptual innovations introduced by Emil Kraepelin in the late nineteenth century). Referencing the 6th (1899) edition of Kraepelin’s Psychiatrie, Mundt and Backerstrass succinctly epitomise the nature, direction, and extent of Kraepelin’s continued influence on the conceptualisation of the core DSM model as follows (2005, p. 220):

    Emil Kraepelin emphasised the medical model for psychiatric diagnosis, and made this model most pervasive in the history of psychiatry. According to his concept, diagnostic classification was based on the convergence of psychopathological symptoms, aetiology, course, outcome, brain morphology, and pathophysiology. Those patients who show the same characteristics in most of these domains can be considered as belonging to one nosological category which Kraepelin considered a “natural entity”. In his view, the research process follows a continued approximation to perfect accuracy by grouping patients ever tighter according to [these] criteria.

    But notwithstanding his extensive tutelary influence, Kraepelin’s doctrines were not taken over unadulterated, but rather via a nine-point neo-Kraepelinian “credo” (as Harvard psychologist Gerald Klerman termed it) informing the conceptualisation of the DSM model (Decker 2007, p. 248). Of particular relevance for what follows are the emphatic neo-Kraepelinian contentions that: “Psychiatry is a branch of medicine”; “There are discrete mental illnesses”; “The focus of psychiatric physicians should be particularly on the biological aspects of mental illness”; “There should be explicit and intentional concern with diagnosis and classification” (indeed, the neo-Kraepelinians tended toward the view that “classification is diagnosis”); and that “Diagnostic criteria should be [explicitly] codified”.

    For detailed technical analyses of the extent of Kraepelin’s ongoing pervasive influence on the DSM model notwithstanding refinements instantiated in DSM-IV and for textured commentary on possible future directions, the interested reader should consult the recent special issue of the European Archives of Psychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience (Vol. 258, Supp. 2, June 2008) devoted to this topic. The succinct Editors’ Introduction (pp. 1–2) and the contribution by Hans–Jurgen Moller (pp. 48–73) are of particular interest from the perspective of present concerns.

  5. Strong DSM advocates may contend that clinicians could not fail to attend to the experiential, or “phenomenological”, dimension of the patient’s experience. While this may be so in an informal everyday sense, the point at issue here is that given its biomedical proclivities, its categorical focus and positivistic biases, this crucial dimension is not formally part of the DSM model. On the contrary, as already noted, the DSM continues to be motivated by the neo-Kraepelinian credo that “classification is diagnosis”. Moreover, the DSM’s strong biomedical orientation lends itself to treating the experiential as an epiphenomenon, to be quickly transcended in the interests of getting on with the business of concluding a “truly scientific” diagnosis.

  6. “Mental pathology, Kraepelin proposed, could be divided into discrete disorders, distinguishable one from the other. Each with its own symptomatology and course; each with its own specific pathophysiology. Nosology [disease classification], according to Kraepelin should be the principal guideline in exploring the biological roots of mental pathology” (van Praag 2008, p. 29).

  7. The development of a biopsychosocial template in psychiatry is associated with the innovative work of George Engel in particular, and before that of Adolf Meyer (see further Pilgrim 2002; also Borrell-Carrio et al. 2004; Ghaemi 2003, ch. 1).

  8. Briefly stated, Ghaemi’s thesis is that a biopsychosocial orientation has come to stand for an injunction to include a bit of everything, thereby facilitating the formulation of vague and indiscriminate diagnoses and treatment plans; and hence needs to be replaced by a methodologically-aware “pluralism”, which would avoid the problematic eclectic groundlessness. In effect, however, Ghaemi’s thesis is undermined by his conflation of eclecticism (which he rightly criticises) with biopsychosocial thinking, and his consequent rejection of the latter. Although space limitations preclude its comprehensive defence here, my contention—reflected in the delineation of strengths and possibilities that follows--is that a biopsychosocial orientation is in fact altogether compatible with the “pluralism” that Ghaemi advocates as an antidote to both “dogmatic” (biomedical) monism and eclecticism. Hence, in my view, his arguments in favour of pluralism actually reinforce the position defended here, although this is masked by his trenchant (but unjustified) condemnation of the “biopsychosocial model”. Further, I would contend that the hermeneutic framework delineated hereunder is as much needed to give an integrating focus to Ghaemi’s pluralism as to the biopsychosocial template under elaboration here.

  9. Accordingly, I typically use the phrase template (or cognates such as framework, approach, orientation) rather than “model” to characterise a biopsychosocial orientation to psychiatric diagnosis and treatment, both to differentiate it from existing biopsychosocial “models” and because the latter term can have (positivistic, biomedical) connotations more commensurate with the aims and aspirations of the DSM approach than with this more expansive diagnostic framework (cf. McLaren 1998).

  10. Importantly, it should also be borne in mind that, like the DSM itself, the biopsychosocial template needs to be conceptualised as a work in progress in need of continual revision and refinement. Hence, attention needs to be focussed on its strengths and possibilities as a counterbalance to the restrictive DSM model, and not equated with some outdated, or otherwise flawed, historical formulation. Accordingly, the aim here is to highlight some interrelated diagnostic possibilities inherent in this approach as a needed corrective for the DSM’s diagnostic limitations, and to indicate how a hermeneutic underpinning can help give it the requisite theoretical grounding to inure it against charges of groundlessness and eclecticism.

    Cognisant that readers may not already be familiar with core tenets of hermeneutic philosophy, deriving from the work of theorists such as Dilthey, Heidegger, and especially Hans-Georg Gadamer, in what follows I have sought to elucidate the core biopsychosocial implications of a hermeneutic orientation in a way that does not presuppose prior acquaintance. But readers who would like to enhance their understanding of the philosophical background may wish to consult, e.g. Alcoff 1996: chs 1 & 2; Grondin 1994: chs VI & VII; Healy 2005: ch. 2.

  11. In a recent contribution, Tim Thornton has challenged the tenability of the Windelband’s idiographic/nomothetic distinction, and hence the tenability of idiographic understanding as an integral component of comprehensive psychiatric diagnosis (Thornton 2008). While Thornton’s analysis clearly establishes that the idiographic and the nomothetic should not be construed as mutually exclusive and that it is indeed difficult to delimit clearly the boundaries between the two, I would nonetheless contend that, as the World Psychiatric Association enjoins, the distinction can, and should, be used to differentiate in practice between a preoccupation with categorical diagnosis and attention to the particularities of the individual case, and to underscore the point that an adequate diagnosis requires both. Accordingly, it would not do to dispense with this distinction notwithstanding its inevitably fuzzy boundaries.

  12. See further Phillips (2004) for elaboration and defence of its ongoing, albeit evolving, significance in the diagnostic context.

References

  • Alcoff, L.M. 1996. Real knowing. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association. 1994. DSM-IV: Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andreasen, N.C. 2007. DSM and the death of phenomenology in America: An example of unintended consequences. Schizophrenia Bulletin 33: 108–112.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Arnason, V. 2000. Gadamerian dialogue in the patient-professional interaction. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy: A European Journal 3: 17–23.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Bem, S., and H. Looren De Jong. 2006. Theoretical issues in psychology: An introduction. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berganza, C.E., J.E. Mezzich, and C. Pouncey. 2005. Concepts of disease: Their relevance for psychiatric diagnosis and classification. Psychopathology 38: 166–170.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Borrell-Carrio, F., A.L. Suchman, and R.M. Epstein. 2004. The biopsychosocial model 25 years later: Principles, practice, and scientific inquiry. Annals of Family Medicine 2: 576–582.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H.I. 1990. Rationality. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chessick, R.D. 1995. The application of phenomenology to psychiatry and psychotherapy. American Journal of Psychotherapy 49: 159–162.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Decker, H.S. 2007. How Kraepelinian was Kraepelin? How Kraepelinian are the neo-Kraepelinians?—From Emil Kraepelin to DSM-III. History of Psychiatry 18: 337–360.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Eaton, J. 1998. Gadamer: Psychotherapy as conversation. European Journal of Psychotherapy & Counselling 1: 421–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eriksen, K., and V.E. Kress. 2005. Beyond the DSM story: Ethical quandaries, challenges, and best practices. Thousand Oaks, CA US: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fulford, K.W.M. 2005. Values in psychiatric diagnosis: Developments in policy, training and research. Psychopathology 38: 171–176.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H.-G. 1989. Truth and method. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galatzer-Levy, I.R., and R.M. Galatzer-Levy. 2007. The revolution in psychiatric diagnosis: Problems at the foundations. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 50: 161–180.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Ghaemi, S.N. 2003. The concepts of psychiatry: A pluralistic approach to the mind and mental illness. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghaemi, S.N. 2009. The rise and fall of the biopsychosocial model. The British Journal of Psychiatry 195: 3–4.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Ginter, E.J., and A. Glauser. 2001. Effective use of the DSM from a developmental/wellness perspective. In The mental health desk reference, ed. E.R. Welfel, and R.E. Ingersoll, 69–77. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grondin, J. 1994. Introduction to philosophical hermeneutics. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healy, P. 1996. Situated rationality and hermeneutic understanding: A Gadamerian approach to rationality. International Philosophical Quarterly 36: 155–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healy, P. 2005. Rationality, hermeneutics and dialogue: Toward a viable postfoundationalist account of rationality. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablensky, A. 1999. The nature of psychiatric classification: Issues beyond ICD-10 and DSM-IV. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry 33: 137–144.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Jablensky, A. 2005. Categories, dimensions and prototypes: Critical issues for psychiatric classification. Psychopathology 38: 201–205.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kirmayer, L.J. 2005. Culture, context and experience in psychiatric diagnosis. Psychopathology 38: 192–196.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lopez, S.J., L.M. Edwards, J. Teramoto Pedrotti, E.C. Prosser, S. LaRue, S. Vehige Spalitto, and J.C. Ulven. 2006. Beyond the DSM-IV: Assumptions, alternatives, and alterations. Journal of Counseling & Development 84: 259–267.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, J., and J. Thompson. 2003. Psychotherapy as the interpretation of being: Hermeneutic perspectives on psychotherapy. Journal of Constructivist Psychology 16: 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLaren, N. 1998. A critical review of the biopsychosocial model. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry 32: 86–92.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Mezzich, J.E. 2005. Positive health: Conceptual place, dimensions and implications. Psychopathology 38: 177–179.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Mezzich, J.E., and C.E. Berganza. 2005. Purposes and models of diagnostic systems. Psychopathology 38: 162–165.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Mezzich, J.E., C.E. Banzato, and C.E. Berganza. 2005. Epilogue: Philosophical and methodological foundations of psychiatric diagnosis. Psychopathology 38: 228–229.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Moller, H.-J. 2008. Systematic of psychiatric disorders between categorical and dimensional approaches: Kraepelin’s dichotomy and beyond. European Archives of Psychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience 258: 48–73.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Mullen, P.E. 2007. A modest proposal for another phenomenological approach to psychopathology. Schizophrenia Bulletin 33: 113–121.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Muller, R.J. 2007. Doing psychiatry wrong: A critical and prescriptive look at a faltering profession. New York: Taylor and Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mundt, C., and M. Backerstrass. 2005. Psychotherapy and classification: Psychological, psychodynamic, and cognitive aspects. Psychopathology 38: 219–222.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, J. 1996. Key concepts: Hermeneutics. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3: 61–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, J. 2004. Understanding/explanation. In The philosophy of psychiatry: A companion, ed. J. Radden, 180–190. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, J. 2005. Idiographic formulations, symbols, narratives, context and meaning. Psychopathology 38: 180–184.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Pilgrim, D. 2002. The biopsychosocial model in Anglo-American psychiatry: Past, present and future? Journal of Mental Health 11: 585–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polkinghorne, D.E. 2000. Psychological inquiry and the pragmatic and hermeneutic traditions. Theory & Psychology 10: 453–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polkinghorne, D.E. 2004. Practice and the human sciences: The case for a judgement-based practice of care. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryder, M. 2005. Scientism. In Encyclopedia of science, technology, ethics, ed. C. Mitcham, 1735–1736. Detroit: Macmillan Reference.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadler, J.Z. 2005. Values and psychiatric diagnosis. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarbin, T.R. 1997. On the futility of psychiatric diagnostic manuals (DSMs) and the return of personal agency. Applied and Preventive Psychology 6: 233–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shorter, E. 1997. A history of psychiatry: From the era of the asylum to the age of prozac. Oxford, UK: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, D.J. 1991. Philosophy and the DSM-III. Comprehensive Psychiatry 32: 404–415.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, J.S. 2005. Diagnosis and reality: A noun is a terrible thing to waste. Psychopathology 38: 189–191.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Thornton, T. 2008. Should comprehensive diagnosis include idiographic understanding? Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 11: 293–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todres, L. 2008. Being with that: The relevance of embodied understanding for practice. Qualitative Health Research 18: 1566–1573.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • van Praag, H.M. 2008. Kraepelin, biological psychiatry, and beyond. European Archives of Psychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience 258: 29–32.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Widdershoven, G.A. 2000. The doctor-patient relationship as a Gadamerian dialogue: A response to Arnason. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy: A European Journal 3: 25–27.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Widiger, T.A. 2005. A dimensional model of psychopathology. Psychopathology 38: 211–214.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, R.N. 1990. The metaphysic of things and discourse about them. In Reconsidering psychology, ed. J.E. Faulconer, and R.N. Williams, 136–150. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yanchar, S.C., and J.R. Hill. 2003. What is psychology about? Toward an explicit ontology. Journal of Humanistic Psychology 43: 11–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

My thanks are due to the anonymous reviewers of my original manuscript. The paper has benefited significantly from revisions made in response to their comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paul Healy.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Healy, P. DSM diagnosis and beyond: on the need for a hermeneutically-informed biopsychosocial framework. Med Health Care and Philos 14, 163–175 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-010-9284-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-010-9284-x

Keywords

Navigation