Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Honneth, Kojeve and Levinas on intersubjectivity and history

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I explore some of the challenges involved in establishing the intersubjective dynamic as the foundation for a normatively charged philosophy of history. I seek in addition to highlight the value of Levinas’ work for the field of recognition studies. Levinas in effect offers a transitional model of recognition between Kojeve and Honneth, and as such his work harbors the potential for addressing some of the difficulties which beset the work of both when it comes to formulating an understanding of recognition which is capable of explaining historical transformation and of serving as a standard for the critique of historical practices.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See principally Hegel (1975).

  2. Levinas (1979, p. 21).

  3. Levinas (1979, p. 25).

  4. Levinas (1979, p. 86).

  5. Levinas (1979, p. 101).

  6. Levinas (1990, p. 125).

  7. Levinas (1990, p. 110).

  8. Levinas (1979, p. 28).

  9. Rose (1992, p. 250).

  10. Vanni (2004, p. 128).

  11. Horowitz (2008, p. 34).

  12. Kojève (1980, p. 4).

  13. Kojève (1980, p. 6).

  14. Kojève (1980, p. 5).

  15. Kojève (1980, p. 13).

  16. Kojève (1980, p. 94).

  17. Kojève (1980, p. 192).

  18. Levinas (1991, p. 39).

  19. Levinas (1991, p. 38).

  20. Levinas (1991, p. 38).

  21. Levinas (1991, p. 39).

  22. Levinas (1991, p. 41).

  23. Levinas (1991, p. 41).

  24. Levinas (1991, p. 41).

  25. Levinas (1991, p. 34).

  26. Butler (1987, p. 48).

  27. Butler (1987, p. 43).

  28. Williams (1997, p. 389).

  29. Honneth (1995, p. 15).

  30. Levinas (1991, p. 36).

  31. Levinas (1991, p. 46).

  32. Levinas (1979, p. 101).

  33. Fraser and Honneth (2003, p. 177).

  34. Honneth (1995, p. 22).

  35. Honneth (2008, p. 49).

  36. Honneth (2008, p. 84).

  37. Honneth (2007, p. 42).

  38. Honneth (2007, p. 37).

  39. Honneth (1995, pp. 97–107).

  40. Honneth (1995, p. 143).

  41. Honneth (2012b, p. 94).

  42. Honneth (2014, p. 59).

  43. Honneth (1995, p. 44).

  44. Honneth (1995, p. 14).

  45. Honneth (2007, p. 42).

  46. Honneth (2007, p. 70).

  47. Honneth (2007, p. 87).

  48. Honneth (2007, p. 93).

  49. McNay (2008, p. 161).

  50. McNay (2008, p. 138).

  51. I am here extending Patchell’s critique, for whom the fixation on recognition decisively limits in advance the unpredictability of intersubjective communication: the attempt to envisage “a world in which people could all find their own identities accurately and respectfully reflected in the mirror of their shared social and political life” requires us to hold, she argues, to a “paralyzing” and “excessively firm grip” on each other’s identity (see Markel 2003, pp. 20–42).

  52. Fraser and Honneth (2003, p. 174).

  53. Fraser and Honneth (2003, p. 184). Recognition diversifies into the spheres of love, esteem and respect, the first emerging with the idea of the bourgeois family and the latter two as separate offshoots from the aristocratic idea of honor.

  54. Fraser and Honneth (2003, p. 152).

  55. Honneth (1995, p. 24).

  56. Althusser (1970, p. 71).

  57. Althusser (1970, p. 64).

  58. Althusser (1970, p. 67).

  59. Honneth (2012b, p. 95).

  60. Whitebook (2001, p. 281).

  61. Honneth (2012a, p. 199).

  62. Adorno (1970, p. 92).

  63. Honneth (2002, p. 503).

  64. Honneth (2002, p. 509).

  65. We might further add that in Freedom’s Right Honneth no longer appears to invest “anthropological force” in the struggle for recognition, and focuses on how, from institutionalized regimes of recognition, we can extrapolate the mere potential for further growth. The historically transformative struggles which constitute direct forms of reaction to “misrecognition” have indeed fallen out of view and his focus is now on critiquing “misdevelopments” in institutions of recognition which the diverse, unarticulated responses of individuals register symptomatically (Honneth 2014, p. 87).

  66. I explore in greater depth the challenge for recognition theory of Althusser’s critique of interpellation, and the subsequent generation of thinkers such as Butler, Dolar, Laclau, Mouffe and Zizek in Recognition between Philosophical Anthropology and Social Ontology: Honneth and the Critique of Interpellation (forthcoming).

  67. A wider debate on psychoanalytical sources for recognition is possible here which would contrast the Lacanian background which informs the Althusserian reading of recognition, and which is itself informed by the Kojevean reading of Hegel, and the background of object relations theory which informs Honneth’s own reading of recognition. Abid, who follows the concept of recognition which emerges from Lacan’s reading of Kojeve, frames this debate concisely: “While Winnicott conceives human development as a progressive, ameliorative process of the transformation—sublimation—of human drives, Lacan conceives this human development as a process of the progressive deconstruction of, and extraction from, essentially restrictive social relations” (Abid 2012, p. 340).

  68. Kojève (1980, p. 124).

  69. Kojève (1980, p. 155).

  70. Sobel (2004, p. 200).

  71. Honneth (2002, p. 504).

  72. Honneth (2002, p. 504).

  73. Kojève (1980, p. 21).

  74. Kojève (1980, p. 225).

  75. Honneth remarks that, whereas Anerkennung signifies more exclusively the bestowing of an honour, esteem or respect perceived as merited, in French and English reconnaissance and recognition can, among other nuances, take on the sense of identification of what was hitherto misrecognized or concealed from view (Honneth 2012b, p. 138). While Honneth focuses almost exclusively on the former sense, Kojeve brings both into play. An additional difficulty in articulating the perspectives would thus be rendering this aspect of identification compatible with the perspective of Honneth.

  76. Kojève (1980, p. 191).

  77. Levinas (1979, p. 233).

  78. Levinas (1979, p. 225).

  79. Butler (1987, p. 16).

  80. Levinas (1979, p. 275).

  81. Levinas (1979, p. 279).

References

  • Abid, Hammidi. 2012. La dialectique de la reconnaissance: la renaissance d’un thème hégélien dans le discours philosophique du XXème siècle. Archives ouverte. http://tel.archivesouvertes.fr/docs/00/73/82/54/PDF/THESE-Abid.pdf. Accessed 6 June 2014.

  • Adorno, Theodor. 1970. Zum Verhältnis von Soziologie und Psychologie. Gesammelte Schriften. Band 8. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp (vgl. GS 8, S. 42).

  • Althusser, Louis. 1970. Ideology and ideological state apparatuses (notes towards an investigation). In “Lenin and philosophy” and other essays (trans: Brewster, Robert), 154-76. N. New York: Monthly Review.

  • Butler, Judith. 1987. Subjects of desire: Hegelian reflections in 20th century France. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, Nancy, and Axel Honneth. 2003. Redistribution or recognition? A political–philosophical exchange. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, W.F. 1975. Lectures on the philosophy of world history (trans: Nisbet, E.H.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Honneth, Axel. 1995. The struggle for recognition: The moral grammar of social conflicts. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 2002. Grounding recognition: A rejoinder to critical questions. Inquiry 45: 499–520.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 2007. Disrespect: The normative foundations of critical theory (trans: Ganahl, Joseph). Cambridge: Polity Press.

  • Honneth, Axel. 2008. Reification: A new look at an old idea. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 2012a. Facets of the pre-social self: Rejoinder to Joel Whitebrook. In The I in We (trans: Ganahl, Joseph), 217–232. Cambridge: Polity Press.

  • Honneth, Axel. 2012b. Recognition as ideology: The connection between morality and power. In The I in We (trans: Ganahl, Joseph), 56–74. Cambridge: Polity Press.

  • Honneth, Axel. 2014. Freedom’s right: The social foundations of democratic life (trans: Ganahl, Joseph). Cambridge: Polity Press.

  • Horowitz, Asher. 2008. Ethics at a standstill: History and subjectivity in Levinas and the Frankfurt School. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kojève, Alexandre. 1980. Introduction to the reading of Hegel, ed. Allain Bloom (trans: Nichols, James). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 1979. Totality and infinity: An essay on exteriority (trans: Lingis, Alphonso). Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 1990. Difficult freedom: Essays on Judaism (trans: Hand, Sean). London: Athlone Press.

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 1991. Entre-nous: On thinking of the other (trans: Harshav, Benjamin, and Michael Smith). London: Athlone Press.

  • McNay, Lois. 2008. Against recognition. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markel, Patchen. 2003. Bound by recognition. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose, Gillian. 1992. The broken middle: Out of our ancient society. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, Richard. 2004. Travail et reconnaissance chez Hegel: une perspective anthropologique au fondement des débats contemporains sur le travail et l’intégration. Revue du Mauss 23: 196–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanni, Michel. 2004. L’impatience des réponses: l’éthique d’Emmanuel Levinas au risque de son inscription pratique. Paris: CNRS Editions.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitebook, Joel. 2001. Mutual recognition and the work of the negative. In Pluralism and the pragmatic turn, ed. William Rehg and James Bohman, 257–293. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Williams, Robert. 1997. Hegel’s ethics of recognition. Berkley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Terence Holden.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Holden, T. Honneth, Kojeve and Levinas on intersubjectivity and history. Cont Philos Rev 49, 349–369 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-015-9345-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-015-9345-1

Keywords

Navigation