Skip to main content
Log in

The Emergence of Better Best System Laws

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The better best system account, short BBSA, is a variation on Lewis’s theory of laws. The difference to the latter is that the BBSA suggests that best system analyses can be executed for any fixed set of properties (instead of perfectly natural properties only). This affords the possibility to launch system analyses separately for the set of biological properties yielding the set of biological laws, chemical properties yielding chemical laws, and so on for the other special sciences. As such, the BBSA remains silent about possible interrelations between these freestanding sets of laws. In this paper, I explicate an emergence relation between them which preserves the autonomy or novelty of each special science’s laws but also shows their dependence: the autonomy of each level’s generalisations is given because nomicity is conferred to them system intrinsic, their dependence is established via their supervenience on lower level laws. As will be shown, the autonomy of special science laws is further strengthened by their ceteris paribus character.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Developed, amongst others, by: Taylor (1993, 97), Roberts (1999), Albert (2000), Halpin (2003), Schrenk (2007, 2008, 2014), Loewer (2007), Cohen and Callender (2009) and Callender and Cohen (2010). For valuable discussions and critique of (various aspects of) the BBSA see Frisch (2014), Weslake (2014) and Backmann and Reutlinger (2014).

  2. Mine was to formulate a theory for special science ceteris paribus laws. I come to this specific reason later. Another was to avoid being committed to the existence of (perfectly) natural properties.

  3. It is necessary to fix a set of predicates/properties for and prior to each best system competition. The specific problems that occur if this is not done need not be discussed here but see Schrenk (2017, 139–141) for a detailed exposition.

    Some worries surrounding the BBSA’s laissez-faire policy regarding vocabulary sets might have to be dispelled. There is a certain threat of subjectivity if it is up to us to choose property sets. However, objectivity of systems is secured in two places and, thus, a relativism to the degree of social construction of the laws or other worrisome anti-realistic features that would be very undesirable for a theory of lawhood are avoided: (i) Nature, although she does not dictate the vocabulary, still dictates which discernible patterns can be seen through the lens of each vocabulary. That is, given a vocabulary, the concrete regularities that exist are factually and objectively given by nature. (ii) We can assume (as Lewis does in Lewis 1973, 73) that, for any vocabulary set, the winners of BBSAs already objectively exist as abstract (Platonic) objects (see also the helpful goddess metaphor in the main text). That is, choosing a vocabulary set to be systematised equals picking the according best systems from what is abstractly and objectively there. (Note aside that some vocabularies will possibly be so inapt to systematise the world—because there are no concrete regularities to be seen through their lenses—that no winning system, far ahead of its competitors, will abstractly exist.)

  4. Mill (1843/1916), Alexander (1920) and Broad (1925).

  5. Of course, Lewis acknowledged this: Lewis (1987, 122).

  6. This is a belief shared by most proponents of the BBS theory. A clear statement to the point is in Callender and Cohen (2010, 441–442).

    The autonomy might be substantially weakened if strong reductionist theses turn out to be true, that is, when the so generated special science laws turn out to be also (somehow) entailed by the fundamental laws (plus other assumptions). I come to this point in Sect. 4.6 “Contingency reconsidered”; (cf. again Callender and Cohen 2010, Fn. 13).

  7. Note again that, in (i) and (ii), I explicate what would have to be the case for the higher level laws to be justifiably called dependent on lower level laws. I do not make the factual claim that this is actually the case for all or some of the higher BBSA laws.

  8. Exemplary for such a relation take one of Jaegwon Kim’s definitions: “A-properties […] supervene on B-properties if and only if for any possible world w and any individuals x and y in w, if x and y are B-indiscernible in w, then they are A-indiscernible in w.” (Kim 1993, 109–130).

  9. Note aside that both the implicit order of quantifies (∀x ∃C1–Cn…) and the varying n and m indicate the multiple realisability of Fs and Gs. Being important in its own right this will have a special relevance in 4.4.

  10. For such a move we find again support in the standard literature on emergence: “Put in abstract terms the emergent theory asserts that there are certain wholes, composed (say) of constituents A, B, and C in a relation R to each other; that all wholes composed of constituents of the same kind as A, B, and C in relations of the same kind as R have certain characteristic properties; that A, B, and C are capable of occurring in other kinds of complex where the relation is not of the same kind as R; and that the characteristic properties of the whole R(A, B, C) cannot, even in theory, be deduced from the most complete knowledge of the properties of A, B, and C in isolation or in other wholes which are not of the form R(A, B, C).” (Beckermann 1992, 102) The latter part (about the non-deducibility) is not important here but the first part about wholes being composed of constituents is.

  11. If we so wish we could even define the Fs and Gs and Pi extensionally as subsets of D, D2, D3, etc.

  12. Take, for example, F to be the property of being a haemoglobin molecule (and G the property of being able to bind oxygen). Now, should a macromolecule x1’s (atomic) parts C1,…,Cn and a second macromolecule x2‘s respective (atomic) parts C1′,…,Cn′ share all P i (being a carbon atom, a hydrogen atom, etc. including structural properties of sets of these respective parts) then x1 is a haemoglobin molecule iff x2 is a haemoglobin molecule (likewise for G, i.e., being able to bind oxygen).

  13. Further refinements to the definition might add time variables to the law statement(s): ∀x, t (F(x, t) ⊃ G(x, t + ∆t)). I take it that this complication (which I omit for reasons of simplicity) would not jeopardize the general idea: Consider four-dimensionalism where objects are extended in space and time and where their temporal parts, just as their spatial parts, occupy various subregions of the total region of spaceime. On such a view, the dependence claims from above are simply made on four-dimensional spacetime rather than on our 3D-domain.

    Another extension could widen the supervenience base to entities extrinsic to the Fs and Gs (or turn otherwise to more global supervenience claims instead) for some higher level properties might not supervene as locally and intrinsically as here depicted. (I owe this thought to Toby Friend) Note that this would, per se, not render the more restricted approach here described useless: there would just be even more possibilities for emergence than here envisaged.

  14. It is an interesting question what a biological best system analysis delivers for a lifeless world, that is, for uninstantiated biological properties B1–Bn (i.e., for biological predicates with empty extensions). No universally quantified conditional would be false but it is unclear how one set of such voidly satisfied conditionals would stand out as the simplest and strongest amongst other such sets and, thus, be the winning team of laws. Would it be, for reasons of simplicity, the empty set? This would meet the intuition that in a lifeless world there are no biological laws.

  15. A referee made me realise that whether this point carries weight depends on the nomic status of the initial conditions. On the Albert-Loewer picture the initial conditions are themselves nomic. Therefore, in this view, higher level laws’ dependence on initial conditions just is dependence on fundamental level laws.

  16. Other examples are the Hardy–Weinberg Principle which states that both allele and genotype frequencies in a population remain constant, that is, they are in equilibrium from generation to generation, unless specific disturbing influences are introduced. Mendel’s first law is that every individual possesses a pair of alleles for any particular trait and each parent passes a randomly selected copy (allele) of only one of these to its offspring, ceteris paribus.

  17. See Fenton-Glynn (2016) for a recent valuable analysis of the cp-issue within BBSAs. See also Braddon-Mitchell (2001) who has greatly influenced my view in Schrenk (2007, 92ff). For important critique of both see Kowalenko (2011) and Wheeler (2017).

  18. Or at least not a specific difficulty occurring only for BBSAs with laws with exceptions. If you are in general opposed to a metaphysical approach to laws already Lewis's original best system idea is not for you.

  19. On the same point see also Cohen and Callender (2009, 20) and Callender and Cohen (2010, 441–442).

  20. You could, for sure, opt for sets with F* predicates. As said in the beginning, a BBSA can be launched upon any set of predicates.

  21. If you opt for sets with predicates like F* which, tracing the more fundamental laws and properties, generate strict regularities, more straightforward reductions to systems below are likely.

    Note that my arguing here with Fodor and Dennett against the “F*s-strictification” strategy is in no friction with the “completer-account” I introduced in 4.4.1. This is because the completed strict regularities from 4.4.1 only figure in the omniscient being’s platonic realm. They are, so too speak, the truthmakers of (but not identical to) the down to earth (incomplete) cp-laws. The F* strategy, on the other hand, is meant to turn the scientists’ cp-laws themselves into strict laws.

  22. I wish to thank Max Bialek, Toby Friend, Siegfried Jaag, Christian Loew, all members of the DFG Group FOR1063, and two anonymous referees for their friendly, constructive advice and their valuable comments. Thanks are also due to the participants at the following workshops and colloquia: Stockholm’s and Marburg’s institutes colloquia 2016, the Metaphysics of Science conference in Geneva 2016, the Gesellschaft für Wissenschaftsphilosophie conference in Düsseldorf 2016, the Emergence Workshop in Leeds 2015, Gerhard Schurz’s and Albert Newen’s research colloquia in, respectively, Düsseldorf and Bochum 2015. I am especially grateful to my fellow investigators Alexander Reutlinger and Juha Saatsi for their advice: The paper was written as a contribution to our Emergence and Laws group (2014–2015) which was part of the Durham Emergence Project and financially supported by the John Templeton Foundation.

References

  • Albert, D. Z. (2000). Time and chance (Vol. 114, 453). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, S. (1920). Space, time, and deity. London: Macmillan & Co Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Backmann, M., & Reutlinger, A. (2014). Better best systems—Too good to be true. Dialectica, 68(3), 375–390. doi:10.1111/1746-8361.12070.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beckermann, A. (1992). Supervenience, emergence, and reduction. In A. Beckermann, H. Flohr, & J. Kim (Eds.), Emergence or reduction? Essays on the prospects of nonreductive physicalism (pp. 94–118). Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D. (2001). Lossy laws. Noûs, 35(2), 260–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broad, C. D. (1925). The mind and its place in nature. London: Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C., & Cohen, J. (2010). Special sciences, conspiracy and the better best system account of lawhood. Erkenntnis, 73(3), 427–447. doi:10.1007/s10670-010-9241-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J., & Callender, C. (2009). A better best system account of lawhood. Philosophical Studies, 145(1), 1–34. doi:10.1007/s11098-009-9389-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Real patterns. The Journal of Philosophy, 88(1), 27–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fenton-Glynn, L. (2016). Ceteris paribus laws and minutis rectis laws. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. doi:10.1111/phpr.12277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special sciences or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis. Synthese, 28(2), 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, M. (2014). Why physics can’t explain everything. In A. Wilson (Ed.), Chance and temporal asymmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halpin, J. F. (2003). Scientific law: A perspectival account. Erkenntnis, 58(2), 137–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1993). ’Strong’ and ‘global’ supervenience revisited. In J. Kim (Ed.), Supervenience and mind: Selected philosophical essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2006). Emergence: Core ideas and issues. Synthese, 151(3), 547–559. doi:10.1007/s11229-006-9025-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kowalenko, R. (2011). The epistemology of hedged laws. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42(3), 445–452. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2011.03.004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983/1999). New work for a theory of universals. In Papers in metaphysics and epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1987). Postscripts to “A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. In Philosophical papers (Vol. II, pp. 114–132). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1994/1999). Humean supervenience debugged. In Papers in metaphysics and epistemology.

  • Loewer, B. (2007). Laws and natural properties. Philosophical Topics, 35(1/2), 313–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mader, S. S. (1993). Biology. Dubuque: Wm. C. Brown Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B. (2008). The rise and fall of British emergentism. In M. A. Bedau & P. Humphreys (Eds.), Emergence: Contemporary readings in philosophy and science. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1843/1916). A system of logic. Ratiocinative and inductive. being a connected view of the principles of evidence and the methods of scientific investigation. London: Longmans, Green, and Co.

  • Roberts, J. (1999). “Laws of nature” as an indexical term: A reinterpretation of Lewis’s best-system analysis. Philosophy of Science, 66(3), 511.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrenk, M. (2007). The metaphysics of ceteris paribus laws. Heusenstamm: Ontos.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schrenk, M. (2008). A theory for special science laws. In H. Bohse, & S. Walter (Eds.), Selected contributions to GAP.6, sixth international conference of the society for analytical philosophy, Berlin (pp. 11–14). September 2006. (CD-ROM). Paderborn: Mentis.

  • Schrenk, M. (2014). Better best systems and the issue of CP-laws. Erkenntnis, 79(10), 1787–1799.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrenk, M. (2017). Metaphysics of science: A systematic and historical introduction. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1984). The nature of selection: Evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephan, A. (1992). Emergence—A systematic view on its historical facets. In A. E. A. Beckermann (Ed.), Emergence or reduction? Essays on the prospects of nonreductive physicalism. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stryer, L. (1988). Biochemistry. New York: W.H. Freeman and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, B. (1993). On natural properties in metaphysics. Mind, 102(405), 81–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weslake, B. (2014). Statistical mechanical imperialism. In A. Wilson (Ed.), Chance and temporal asymmetry (pp. 241–257). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, B. (Spring 2017). Idealization, lossy compression and the laws of physics. Preprint. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/11351/. Last retrieved.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Markus Schrenk.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schrenk, M. The Emergence of Better Best System Laws. J Gen Philos Sci 48, 469–483 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-017-9374-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-017-9374-z

Keywords

Navigation