Skip to main content
Log in

Fun in Go: The Timely Delivery of a Monkey Jump and its Lingering Relevance to Science Studies

  • Empirical Study/Analysis
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper offers an ethnomethodological exploration of fun in Go (the ancient board game), the timely delivery of a ‘Monkey Jump’ (a particular move in Go), and its lingering relevance to science studies (where Go has provided an early analogy for laboratory work). In Go terms, the paper makes a ‘pincer’ move: on the one hand, it explores the analytic potential of ‘fun’ for ethnographic purposes and, on the other hand, it questions its manifest abandonment in some quarters of science studies. In particular, the paper challenges their “curious seriousness” (Garfinkel in Réseaux Hors Sér 8(1):69–78, 1990) whenever grand ontological claims are mixed up with suspended empirical inquiry. That said, the latter criticism does not take the form of a scholarly exercise in conceptual clarification, but remains part and parcel of the author’s ethnography of playing amateur Go, including his dealing with and delivery of a Monkey Jump and reading of Go literature and replaying of professional games (as most amateurs do). The key point of the paper, then, is to demonstrate the heuristic interest of adopting a practitioner’s stance, not only for understanding a technical domain such as Go in its own terms (Livingston in Ethnographies of reason, Ashgate, Aldershot, 2008), but also for launching a phenomenological critique of analytic discretion in science studies. Therefore, the second part of the paper re-examines, from an amateur Go player’s stance, Latour and Woolgar’s Go analogy in and for Laboratory Life (1979, 1986a)—an early exemplar of science studies’ ontological bent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9
Fig. 10
Fig. 11
Fig. 12

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As Kierkegaard put it, “irony is a disciplinarian feared only by those who do not know it, but loved by those who do” (Kirkegaard 2006: 255).

  2. The city names do not correspond to the cities where the ethnography has been (and still is) conducted. The names of participants and places have been altered and anonymized as well.

  3. The target of my ‘pincer’ move has been most aptly identified by J.R. Zammito when he questions science studies qua “hyperbolic ‘theory’ threaten[ing] especially the prospect of learning anything from others that we did not already presume” (Zammito 2004: 275), including any actor’s presumed “politics,” “ontology,” or “metaphysics” (see, e.g., Latour 2006: 73f.).

  4. The broader ‘pincer’ move consists in challenging any “hyperbolic ‘theory’” (or “eccentric ontology,” Collin 2011: 199) in science studies by drawing upon the sustained practice of amateur Go, on the one hand, and its technical terms as part of that self-same practice, on the other. This latter move, as we shall see, results in a phenomenological critique “beneath” existing conceptual clarifications of scholarly interest (see, e.g., Hutchinson et al. 2008; Lynch 2013; Quéré 2012; Tsilipakos 2012).

  5. In the existing literature on (and in) ethnomethodology, H. Garfinkel’s requirement to engage in technical self-instruction has often been referred to as a professional distraction, if not unnecessary pain. Early on, M. Lynch (1985: 128) acknowledged the “monstrously difficult strictures of Garfinkel’s program” (quoted in Latour, Woolgar 1986b: 286, note 5). This section, in turn, tries to convey the instructive fun (or, one might say, surprising pleasure) of engaging in this program, even in and for a “tough case” such as Go, whether amateur or professional.

  6. The tautological point marks the reflexive availability of the setting(s). For the seminal account of this “uninteresting” notion of reflexivity, see Garfinkel (1967:6f.).

  7. Though not always favorably so: “Go is to Western chess what philosophy is to double entry accounting” (from Shibumi, a bestseller by Trevanian, quoted on a leading Go book publisher’s website, see http://www.kiseido.com/).

  8. For approximately four months (from February to May 2004), I went playing Go and observing its playing at the mentioned Magic pub. Later that year, I pursued the ethnography on a weekly basis for almost a year at Geneva Go Club (from September 2004 onwards). In 2007, I attended a four-day workshop with a Japanese Go professional, including one amateur tournament, after having attended several training sessions at the Japanese consulate in Geneva. Only recently, however, have I been able to take up participant observation at Linz Go Club (from September 2013 onwards). The reasons for the only recent “revival” of the ongoing ethnography, as well as the delayed finalization of this paper, are not without analytic interest (as outlined in the conclusion to this paper).

  9. These partly embodied members’ methods, we may say, establish the “natural home” of their talk (see Goffman 1964).

  10. “Natural accountability” denotes the “accountability to the populational cohort and the scene in which one does something” (Editor’s note, in Garfinkel 2002: 173, note 2)—for instance, ‘starting another game of Go’. Garfinkel contrasts this “natural accountability” with the “[classical] accountability to the populational cohort to which one reports a description of what has been done” (Garfinkel 2002: 173).

  11. For a detailed analysis of “turn-generated” and “turn-generating” membership categories in conversational talk and otherwise institutionalized interaction, see Sacks (1992) and Watson (1994). On ranking rules in Go, see http://www.gokgs.com/help/rank.html.

  12. “Although the normal size of a Go board is 19 by 19 lines, it is possible to use smaller sizes. Beginners can learn the basics on a 9 by 9 board and quick games can be played on a 13 by 13 board without losing the essential character of the game” (BGA 2001: 6). Visual representations of 9 × 9 and 19 × 19 Go boards are used below.

  13. For a recent investigation of this reflexive, mutually elaborating relationship between rule and instance in other board games, see Liberman (2013, chap. 3).

  14. In Go, one can manifestly “kill” an opponent’s group and still keep its members as “prisoners”. This may go against the military saying (“take no prisoners”), yet it does not prevent one from playing Go, even though the game is often presented in military terms (e.g., “chess is a battle, Go is war”).

  15. Not all of the basic rules of Go have been explained, among which “ko” rules which prevent situations of virtually eternal, mutual recapturing (“ko” meaning “eternity” in Japanese). For an explanation of the handicap system and the differences in the Japanese and Chinese rules of Go, see BGA (2001: 10f.). The “dotted” intersections on the Go board, also visible on its presently used figures, mark the positions where handicap stones are placed.

  16. The hyphenated expression hints at the form of the sought answer.

  17. After the “nasty surprise” game, the 3 dan player showed us several possible responses to the Monkey Jump problem on the board. All of them seemed to be “sensitive” to the actual situation: the slightest alterations in the constellation of the stones modified the preferred moves to play. He demonstrated different solutions (or “preference rules”; Garfinkel 1963), yet with the crucial caveat that the adequacy of each would remain contingent upon the particular game under way. For a Monkey Jump textbook that takes into account such game-bound contingencies, see Hunter (2002).

  18. To disregard the “direction of play” of an unfolding game is a typical flaw of amateur players—at least according to longstanding professionals (e.g., Kajiwara 1979: 19). I shall get back to this point (in the next section below) when examining the Go analogy in and for Laboratory Life (Latour and Woolgar 1979: 247–250).

  19. “I see exactly what you mean, but whether it is better, I don’t know” (A. Sormani, personal remark). This was the reaction of a more experienced player to my game analysis. The latter could and can thus be continued.

  20. The same holds for the sequel to the commented episode. As readers can glean from the Kifu in Appendix 1, in answer to Black’s Monkey Jump (move 141), White surrounded and enclosed Black’s group even more severely in the upper-left corner (see moves 142–153), thus canceling Black’s project of minimizing White’s territory on the left-hand side. Did I lose or win the game in the end? The Kifu sheet may assist interested readers in finding an answer to this question.

  21. In all of the investigated Go clubs books were made available to their members. These books, in contrast to manuals, were typically signed by “professionals” and designed for “amateurs”. Garfinkel (1990): 77 alluded to the “curious seriousness of professional sociology” as a phenomenon to be discovered (and not predefined) in the particular course of an ethnomethodological inquiry. This section tries to exemplify his allusion and how it might apply to science studies and their renewed interest in ontology (see Woolgar and Lezaun 2013). On the “renewed” character of this interest, see the conclusion to this paper.

  22. In professional science studies, in turn, the incongruity seems not to have been noticed. This may not be surprising, given their indebtedness to Laboratory Life (e.g., Law 2009: 144; Sismondo 1993: 532). This unquestioned indebtedness may be considered as a second expression of “curious seriousness”. For a related criticism of technically complex, yet potentially empty analogies, see Gingras (2007).

  23. That is, “at the beginning of the game, any move appears as possible, or as good, as any other” (Latour and Woolgar 1979: 42, note 5).

  24. L&W use the expression “model,” rather “ontology,” when writing of “(created) pockets of order” (1979: 246). Yet their argument seems to be ontological, as it bears on (scientific) reality and its constructed character, rather than on the methods and concepts used for its investigation (Latour and Woolgar 1979:244–252). If the latter were brought into focus, the “Go” analogy might have been dropped altogether, as well as the conflation between probabilistic notions and game preferences regarding contingency and necessity (see also Coulter 1996). This manifest conflation, in turn, has (or had) the advantage of providing L&W with a local motive for rhetorical work.

  25. Kawabata received the Nobel Prize in 1968 for his life work. For further information on this author and his Master of Go, see the translator’s introduction to Kawabata (1996/1972: vi–vii).

  26. The numbering of moves corresponds to the moves shown in Fig. 12.

  27. In other words, given their interpretive discretion, L&W could not but miss the “relationship between the first two moves” (Kajiwara 1979: 56) and how (and why!) “move two lost the game” perhaps (Kajiwara 1979: 55–78). The conservative character of the commented opening move is related to its placement at R-16, in the upper right-hand corner: “a quiet, restrained move that can easily be turned into profit” (Kajiwara 1979: 8).

  28. Crucially, L&W missed the ordered opening of the game (i.e., its “conservative” and then “diagonal” opening, via moves 1–3), which made possible its incidental, yet incongruous commentary in terms of “initial disorder” (i.e., as presumably illustrated by Fig. 12). As one reviewer suggested, L&W might not have been very serious about the “Go” analogy, though perhaps about the general picture of lab work (see though Latour and Woolgar 1986b: 284f.). Is that to say that the end (conveying this or that general picture) justifies the means (using this or that dodgy analogy)? Obviously, the present paper has argued against this view, an instrumentalist view which seems to have been L&W’s too (see Collin 2011: 114).

  29. With A. Louch, we may note more generally that “in a limited and ordinary employment of game, a [wo]man must understand the rules in order to play. But when we come to apply this concept analogically or metaphorically this requirement is no longer met. In fact, anthropologists want to claim the right to revise the participants’ account of their performances. In such a case, is the anthropologist’s diagnosis of the rules a generalization upon observed actions, or a directive to act? Is [s]he umpire or observer?” (Louch 1969: 225).

  30. No “resistance to theory” (Hutchinson et al. 2008: 92) was cultivated in this paper, however. Rather, a “member’s theory” (e.g., opening theory in Go) was to be recovered as part of a “member’s practice” (i.e., amateur Go), as already suggested by Garfinkel and Sacks (1986/1970).

  31. At a recent workshop on “actor-network theory,” I asked one of its leading figures “but why, as an ethnographer, should one ‘ontologize’, ‘epistemologize’, or otherwise ‘theorize’ phenomena, instead of describing them in their self-identifying features, and stick to the understanding that such description can provide?” He called the question “a tough one” and declined to answer it.

References

  • Baccus, M. D. (1986). Multipiece truck wheel accidents and their regulations. In H. Garfinkel (Ed.), Ethnomethodological studies of work (pp. 20–59). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • BGA. (2001). Play go. The most challenging game in the world. Market Drayton: The British Go Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Button, G. (Ed.). (1991). Ethnomethodology and the human sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callon, M. (1986). Some elements of a sociology of translation: Domestication of the scallops and the fishermen of St Brieuc Bay. In J. Law (Ed.), Power action and Belief. A new sociology of knowledge (pp. 196–233). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicourel, A. (1964). Method and measurement in sociology. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collin, F. (2011). Science studies as naturalized philosophy. Synthese library. Studies in epistemology logic, methodology, and philosophy of science. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coulter, J. (1996). Chance, cause and conduct: probability theory and the explanation of human action. In S. Shanker (Ed.), Philosophy of science, logic and mathematics. History of philosophy (Vol. IX, pp. 266–291). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, J. (1975). Life and death: Elementary go series (Vol. 4). Tokyo: The Ishi Press Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descombes, V. (1989). Philosophie par gros temps. Paris: Ed. de Minuit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doing, P. (2008). Give me a laboratory and I will raise a discipline: The past, present, and future politics of laboratory studies in STS. In E. J. Hackett, et al. (Eds.), The handbook of science and technology studies (3rd ed., pp. 279–318). Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, H. (1952). The perception of the other. A study in social order. PhD thesis. Cambridge: Harvard.

  • Garfinkel, H. (1963). A conception of, and experiments with, ‘trust’ as a condition of stable concerted actions. In O. J. Harvey (Ed.), Motivation and social interaction (pp. 187–238). New York: Ronald Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, H. (1967). Studies in ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice–Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, H. (1990). The curious seriousness of professional sociology. Réseaux Hors Sér, 8(1), 69–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, H. (1991). Respecification: Evidence for locally produced, naturally accountable phenomena of order*, logic, reason, meaning, method, etc. in and as of the essential haecceity of immortal ordinary society (I) an announcement of studies. In G. Button (Ed.), Ethnomethodology and the human sciences (pp. 10–19). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, H. (2002). Ethnomethodology’s program: Working out Durkheim’s aphorism. Edited and introduced by Anne Rawls. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, H., Sacks, H. (1986(1970)). On formal structures of practical actions. In H. Garfinkel (Ed.) Ethnomethodological studies of work (pp. 160–193). London: Routledge.

  • Gingras, Y. (2007). Everything you did not necessarily want to know about gravitational waves. And why. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 38, 268–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goffman, E. (1961). Fun in Games, encounters: Two studies in the sociology of interaction (pp. 17–81). Indianapolis, New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goffman, E. (1964). The Neglected Situation. American Anthropologist, New Series, The Ethnography of Communication, Part 2, 66(2), 133–136.

  • Guggenheim, M. (2011). The proof is in the pudding—On ‘truth to materials’ in the sociology of translations, followed by an attempt to improve it. Science, Technology and Innovation Studies, 7(1), 65–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1988). The participant irrealist at large in the laboratory. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 39(3), 277–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1999). The social construction of what?. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunter, R. (2002). Monkey jump workshop. Richmond: Slate and Shell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson, P., Read, R., & Sharrock, W. (2008). Seeing things for themselves: winch, ethnography, ethnomethodology and social studies, there is no such thing as a social science (pp. 91–112). Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jasanoff, S. (2004). The idiom of co-production. In S. Jasanoff (Ed.), States of knowledge. The co-production of science and social order (pp. 1–12). London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kajiwara, T. (1979). The direction of play. Tokyo, Santa Monica and Amsterdam: Kiseido.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kawabata, Y. (1996 (1972)). The master of Go. New York: Vintage International.

  • Krämer, S. (2010). Is there a language ‘behind’ speaking? How to look at 20th century language philosophy in an alternative way. In V. Munz, et al. (Eds.), Language and world part II: Signs minds and actions (pp. 39–50). Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasker, E. (1960(1934)). Go and Go-moku. The oriental board games. New York: Dover Publications, Inc.

  • Latour, B. (1992). One more turn after the social turn: Easing science studies into the non-modern world. In E. McMullin (Ed.), The social dimensions of science (pp. 272–292). Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (2006). Changer de société, refaire la sociologie. Paris: Ed. de la Découverte.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1979). Laboratory life: The social construction of scientific facts. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1986a). Laboratory life: The construction of scientific facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1986b). Postscript. Laboratory life: The construction of scientific facts (pp. 273–290). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Law, J. (2009). Actor network theory and material semiotics. In B. S. Turner (Ed.), The New Blackwell Companion to social theory (pp. 142–158). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Law, J., & Lien, M. E. (2013). Slippery: Field notes in empirical ontology. Social Studies of Science, 43(3), 363–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lezaun, J., & Woolgar, S. (2013). The wrong bin bag: A turn to ontology in science and technology studies? Social Studies of Science, 43(3), 321–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liberman, K. (2013). More studies in ethnomethodology. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Livingston, E. (2008). Ethnographies of reason. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Louch, A.R. (1969). Games and Metaphors. In Explanation and Human Action (pp. 209–232). Berkeley, Los Angeles: University of California Press.

  • Lynch, M. (1982). Technical work and critical inquiry: Investigations in a scientific laboratory. Social Studies of Science, 12, 499–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M. (1985). Art and artifact in laboratory science: A study of shop work and shop talk. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M. (1993). Scientific practice and ordinary action: ethnomethodology and social studies of science. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M. (2011). Ad hoc special section on ethnomethodological studies of science, mathematics, and technical activity: Introduction. Social Studies of Science, 41(6), 835–837.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M. (2013). Postscript ontography: Investigating the production of things, deflating ontology. Social Studies of Science, 43(3), 444–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, D., & Bogen, D. (1997). Sociology’s asociological core: An examination of textbook sociology in light of the sociology of scientific knowledge. American Sociological Review, 62(3), 481–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, C. (1999). Teach Yourself Go. London: Hodder & Stoughton/McGraw-Hill.

  • Mol, A. (1999). Ontological politics. A word and some questions. In J. Law & J. Hassard (Eds.), Actor network theory and after (pp. 74–89). OxfordKeele: Blackwell and The Sociological Review.

  • Otake, H. (2002). Opening theory made easy. Twenty strategic principles to improve your opening game. Tokyo: Kiseido.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parcero Oubiña, O. (2006). ‘Controlled Irony’…Are you serious? Reading Kierkegaard’s irony ironically. In N. J. Cappelorn & H. Dreuser (Eds.), Kierkegaard Studies (pp. 241–260). Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quéré, L. (2004). Il faut sauver les phénomènes! Mais comment? Espaces Temps, 84–86, 24–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quéré, L. (2012). Is there any good reason to say goodbye to ‘Ethnomethodology’? Human Studies, 35(2), 305–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sacks, H. (1992). Lectures on conversation (Vol. 1). London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schindler, L. (2009). The production of ‘vis-ability’: an ethnographic video analysis of a martial arts class. In U. TikvahKismann (Ed.), Video interaction analysis: Methods and methodology (pp. 135–153). Wien: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharrock, W., & Anderson, R. J. (2011). Discovering a practical impossibility. The internal configuration of a problem in mathematical reasoning. Ethnographic Studies, 12, 47–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sismondo, S. (1993). Some social constructions. Social Studies of Science, 23, 515–553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sogoe, K. (1960). Go proverbs illustrated. The Nihon Ki-in (The Japan Go Association): Tokyo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sormani, P. (2014). Respecifying lab ethnography. An ethnomethodological study of experimental physics. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsilipakos, L. (2012). The poverty of ontological reasoning. Journal of the Theory of Social Behavior, 42(2), 201–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, R. (1994). Catégories, séquentialité et ordre social. In B. Fradin, L. Quéré & J. Widmer (Eds.), L'enquête sur les categories (Raisons pratiques 5, pp. 151–184). Paris: Ed. de l’EHESS.

  • Watson, R. (2009). Analysing practical and professional texts. A naturalistic approach. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolgar, S., & Cooper, G. (1999). Do artifacts have ambivalences? Moses’ bridges, winner’s bridges and other urban legends in S&TS. Social Studies of Science, 29(3), 433–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woolgar, S., Lezaun, J. (eds.) (2013) Special Issue: A turn to ontology in science and technology studies?, Social Studies of Science, 43(3).

  • Zammito, J. H. (2004). A nice derangement of epistemes post—Positivism in the study of science from Quine to Latour. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Special acknowledgments are due to the Go club members whose game moves are studied in this paper, as well as to Jon Diamond from the BGA and to Princeton University Press for granting me permission to use visual illustrations under their copyright. A prior version of the paper was presented at the 2005 conference of the International Institute of Ethnomethodology and Conversation Analysis at Bentley College, Waltham, MA. I would like to thank its participants for their comments, especially Larissa Schindler who also encouraged me to write up the paper. Two anonymous reviewers helped me to improve the manuscript. So did the comments and criticisms by Andrew P. Carlin, Anna Pichelstorfer, Leonidas Tsilipakos, and Rod Watson. I thank all of them. As ever, none of them can be held responsible for polemic points or remaining mistakes. Neither can André Sormani who first introduced me to Go and still beats me almost every time.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Philippe Sormani.

Appendices

Appendix 1

Fig. 13
figure 13

Kifu sheet, as used to record game moves, including Monkey Jump at 141

Appendix 2

Fig. 14
figure 14

Cover of Laboratory Life (Latour and Woolgar 1986a)

Appendix 3

Fig. 15
figure 15

Reproduction of the first figure of the Go game described by Kawabata (1996 (1972):36)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sormani, P. Fun in Go: The Timely Delivery of a Monkey Jump and its Lingering Relevance to Science Studies. Hum Stud 38, 281–308 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-015-9340-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-015-9340-x

Keywords

Navigation