Skip to main content
Log in

Changing Society by Scientific Investigations? The Unexpected Shared Ground Between Early Sociology of Knowledge and the Vienna Circle

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I show that there are important but hitherto unnoticed similarities between key figures of the Vienna Circle and early defenders of sociology of knowledge. The similarities regard their stance on potential implications of the study of science for political and societal issues. I argue that notably Otto Neurath and Karl Mannheim are concerned with proposing a genuine political philosophy of science that is remarkably different from today’s emerging interest in the relation between science and society in philosophy of science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Of course, the regained reflection on the relation between science and society/politics is mainly due to the pioneer work of Paul Feyerabend and also to discussions in the sociology of science in the 1970s; feminist philosophy of science needs to be mentioned in this context, too (Harding 1991; Longino 1990).

    These developments led to much debatte and polemics from philosophy of science in the analytical tradition that focused on the questions of relativism and constructivism. Importantly, the more recent developments in analytical philosophy—and Philip Kitcher can serve as witness here—see a reevaluation of the issue from authors from a distinguished realist and anti-relativist point of view.

  2. See especially Reisch (2005) for the historical background.

  3. A notable exemption is Howard (2009).

  4. See especially Uebel (2005, 2009, 2010) and the papers in Heidelberger and Stadler (2003). A good overview is provided by Reisch (2005, chapter 2). The issue of a genuine political philosophy of the Vienna Circle is still debated (see Richardson 2009a, b).

  5. See e.g. Carnap (1963, 23). As testified by a message from Carnap to Marie Neurath, Carnap’s political views in the twenties and thirties were identical with Neurath’s (see Neurath 1973a, xiii).

  6. See e.g. Carnap et al. (1973, 301f.): “[...] endeavors toward a new organization of economic and social relations, toward the unification of mankind, toward a reform of school and education, all show an inner link with the scientific world-conception [...].” and “The vitality that shows itself in the efforts for a rational transformation of the social and economic order, permeates the movement for a scientific world-conception too.” See also the remarks on 304f.

    I am quoting here from the reprinted, translated version from 1973. A very helpful edition is also the edition by Friedrich Stadler and Thomas Uebel that includes translations in four languages (see Stadler and Uebel 2012).

  7. See Carnap et al. (1973, 317).

  8. See Carnap et al. (1973, 301f. and 305). See on the Vienna Circle and Red Vienna: Hacohen (1998).

  9. Unfortunately, this paper is not yet translated into English. I will provide my translation and refer to the German version.

  10. See Neurath (1981, 351). In effect, Neurath applies an argument already stated by Max Weber in his seminal essay ‘Objectivity’ in Social Science and Social Policy: “It can, to be sure, be just as obligatory subjectively for the practical politician, in the individual case, to mediate between antagonistic points of view as to take sides with one of them. But this has nothing whatsoever to do with scientific “objectivity.” Scientifically the “middle course” is not truer even by a hair’s breadth, than the most extreme party ideals of the right or left. Nowhere are the interests of science more poorly served in the long run than in those situations where one refuses to see uncomfortable facts and the realities of life in all their starkness” (Weber 1949, 57f.). See on Weber and Mannheim: Scott (1998).

  11. It should be noted that Neurath’s example is quite unfortunate since Mannheim more than once emphasizes that the contents of the natural sciences and mathematics must be exempted from his thesis of existential determination [he even mentions the equation 2 times 2 equals 4 (see Mannheim 1946, 244)]. Therefore, Mannheim could easily protest that in the case of mathematical truths his idea of a synthesis of viewpoints does not apply.

    Note, however, that this move would rescue Mannheim’s idea only if there is a distinction between the contents of the humanities and the contents of the natural sciences and mathematics in principle. Mannheim, however, denies that there is such a difference in principle (see Seidel 2011a).

  12. See also Neurath (1973b, 297): “It is precisely the proletariat that is the bearer of science without metaphysics”.

  13. See Neurath (1981, 353).

  14. See Neurath (1981, 356).

  15. As Reisch has argued, Carnap’s claim to neutrality of philosophy and science does not imply that the insights of the latter have no political consequences: “Though logic and philosophy of science may remain independent of politics in Carnap’s project, politics is not independent of logic and philosophy of science” (Reisch 2005, 50f.). To my mind the same can be said with respect to Mannheim.

  16. See Endress (2011, 161).

  17. For obvious reasons Neurath’s criticism of Ideology and Utopia from 1930 does not refer to this article. Nevertheless, I focus on this article because the purpose of my paper is not to assess the adequacy and cogency of Neurath’s criticism but to show via the example of Mannheim that around 1930 the idea that a scientific investigation of worldviews and a scientific conception of the world can have political and social consequences was prevalent among many intellectuals in German speaking Europe.

  18. Some notes on the translation of Mannheim’s German works into English: I consider them as mostly inadequate. Just to give one of the most obvious examples: the translation of Mannheim’s essay Historismus (Mannheim 1952a) completely omits five pages of the original (on page 176)!

    However, it has to be noticed that Mannheim himself changed the English translation of Ideologie und Utopie remarkably, because he wanted to adjust the text to the ‘way of thought of the American-English reader’ and was afraid that a more literal translation will not be understood properly by the English reader (see his letters to Louis Wirth from June 18th, 1935, December 24th, 1935, February 15th, 1936, March 23rd, 1936 and June 12th, 1936; all reprinted in Gabor 2003). Notwithstanding this fact, I deliberately also changed the translation of Ideologie und Utopie, since I take it to be very misleading. Just take Mannheim’s discussion on page 271, where Mannheim distinguishes between Seinsverbundenheit and Seinsgebundenheit in the German original by claiming that by discovering Seinsverbundenheit we make a first step to solve Seinsgebundenheit. In the English translation Seinverbundenheit and Seinsgebundenheit are both translated as ‘situational determination’ such that the claim sounds like bootstrapping.

  19. The translation of ‘Seinsverbundenheit’ as ‘existential relatedness’ follows the use of Simonds (1978, 27).

  20. See Mannheim (1946, 271): “the neutralization of existential determination by attempting to rise above it”.

  21. See Neurath (1981, 353).

  22. See Mannheim (1946, 271).

  23. See Mannheim (1971, 266).

  24. See on Mannheim’s supposed elitism Loader (1985, 173).

  25. See Mannheim (1946, 140, 142).

  26. See for the background of this metaphor Kettler et al. (1984, 54).

  27. Mannheim explicitly claims that it is not so much their social middle position but their “experimental outlook” and their attitude (Haltung) that defines the free-floating intellectuals (see Mannheim 1946, 134).

  28. Note that also in the manifesto of the Vienna Circle reference to intuitions as a superior way of knowing is denied. Carnap, Hahn and Neurath do not reject intuition as such but demand that intuitive knowledge must be tested scientifically (see Carnap et al. 1973, 308f.).

  29. Some authors, in my view quite correctly, see in Mannheim’s notion of free-floating intellectuals remarkable similarities to Habermas’ idea of the ‘ideal speech situation’ (see e.g. Baum 1977, 65f., Scott 1998, 117).

  30. See also Scott (1998, 112).

  31. Nemeth (2007, 279) interprets Neurath’s opposition to Mannheim from this perspective: Neurath, she maintains, critizes Mannheim’s ‘humanist’ social theory and aims to defend a modern scientific social theory.

    This is not to suggest that this is the decisive reason—surely the different topics dealed with by these authors are of major importance in explaining the difference.

  32. See Neurath (1973b, 297), Neurath (1981, 350).

  33. See e.g. Fleck (1979, 50, 76), Fleck (1990a, 253). The important difference between a theory of knowledge and a science of knowledge unfortunately gets lost in the translation of Fleck’s Zagadenienie teorii poznawania (Fleck 1986).

  34. See most obviously Fleck (1990b).

  35. See Seidel (2011b) for discussion.

References

  • Baum, G. (1977). Truth beyond relativism: Karl Mannheim’s sociology of knowledge. Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1963). Intellectual autobiography. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (pp. 3–84). London: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R., Hahn, H., & Neurath, O. (1973). Scientific world conception. The Vienna Circle. In O. Neurath (Ed.), Empiricism and sociology (pp. 299–318). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2009). Science, policy and the value-free ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Endress, M. (2011). Methodological relationism. In R. Schantz & M. Seidel (Eds.), The problem of relativism in the sociology of (scientific) knowledge (pp. 157–181). Frankfurt: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleck, L. (1979). Genesis and development of a scientific fact. Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleck, L. (1986). The problem of epistemology. In R. S. Cohen & T. Schnelle (Eds.), Cognition and fact. Materials on Ludwik Fleck (pp. 129–151). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fleck, L. (1990a). Science and social context. In I. Löwy (Ed.), The Polish school of philosophy of medicine. From Tytus Chalubinski (1820–1889) to Ludwik Fleck (1896–1961) (pp. 249–256). Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleck, L. (1990b). Rejoinder to the comments of Tadeusz Bilikiewicz. In I. Löwy (Ed.), The Polish school of philosophy of medicine. From Tytus Chalubinski (1820–1889) to Ludwik Fleck (1896–1961) (pp. 2267–2273). Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer.

  • Gabor, E. (Ed.). (2003). Selected correspondence (1911–1946) of Karl Mannheim, Scientist, Philosopher and Sociologist. Lampeter: Edwin Mellen Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacohen, M. H. (1998). Karl Popper, the Vienna Circle, and Red Vienna. Journal of the History of Ideas, 59(4), 711–734.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harding, S. (1991). Whose science? Whose knowledge? Thinking from women’s lives. Ithaca/NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidelberger, M., & Stadler, F. (Eds.). (2003). Wissenschaftsphilosophie und Politik/Philosophy of science and politics. Vienna: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, D. (2009). Better red than dead—putting an end to the social irrelevance of postwar philosophy of science. Science and Education, 18, 199–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kettler, D., Meja, V., & Stehr, N. (1984). Karl Mannheim. London/New York: Tavistock Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2001). Science, truth, and democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2011). Science in a democratic society. New York: Prometheus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leuschner, A. (2012). (Un)Politische Wissenschaftsphilosophie im 20. Jahrhundert. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 60(2), 285–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loader, C. (1985). The intellectual development of Karl Mannheim. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (1990). Science as social knowledge. Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (2006). The social dimensions of science. In Zalta, E.N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2006 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2006/entries/scientific-knowledge-social/.

  • Mannheim, K. (1946). Ideology and utopia. An introduction to the sociology of knowledge. London: Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mannheim, K. (1952a). Historicism. In Essays on the sociology of knowledge (pp. 84–133). London: Kegan Paul.

  • Mannheim, K. (1952b). Competition as a cultural phenomenon. In Essays on the sociology of knowledge (pp. 191–229). London: Kegan Paul.

  • Mannheim, K. (1956a). The problem of the intelligentsia. An inquiry into its past and present role. In Essays on the sociology of culture (pp. 91–170). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

  • Mannheim, K. (1956b). The democratization of culture. In Essays on the sociology of culture (pp. 171–246). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

  • Mannheim, K. (1971). Problems of sociology in Germany. In K. H. Wolff (Ed.), From Karl Mannheim. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nemeth, E. (2007). Logical empiricism and the history and sociology of science. In A. Richardson & T. Uebel (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to logical empiricism (pp. 278–302). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, M. (1973a). Preface. In O. Neurath (Ed.), Empiricism and sociology (Vol. 13). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, O. (1973b). Personal life and class struggle. In O. Neurath (Ed.), Empiricism and sociology (pp. 249–298). Dordrecht: Reidel.

  • Neurath, O. (1981). Bürgerlicher Marxismus. In Gesammelte philosophische und methodologische Schriften. Band 1. (pp. 349–356). Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.

  • Oreskes, N., & Conway, E. M. (2010). Merchants of doubt. How a handful of scientists obscured the truth about issues from tobacco smoke to global warming. New York: Bloomsbury Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reisch, G. (2005). How the cold war transformed philosophy of science: To the icy slopes of logic. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, S. S. (2009a). The left Vienna Circle thesis, part 1. Carnap, Neurath, and the left Vienna Circle thesis. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 40(1), 14–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, S. S. (2009b). The left Vienna Circle thesis, part 2. The left Vienna Circle, disciplinary history, and feminist philosophy of science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 40(2), 167–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, J. (1998). Relationism, cubism, and reality: Beyond relativism. In T. May & M. Williams (Eds.), Knowing the social world (pp. 103–119). Buckingham, Philadelphia: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seidel, M. (2011a). Karl Mannheim, relativism and knowledge in the natural sciences: A deviant interpretation. In R. Schantz & M. Seidel (Eds.), The problem of relativism in the sociology of (scientific) knowledge (pp. 183–213). Frankfurt: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seidel, M. (2011b). Relativism or relationism? A Mannheimian interpretation of Fleck’s claims about relativism. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 42, 219–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simonds, A. P. (1978). Karl Mannheim’s sociology of knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stadler, F., & Uebel, T. (2012). Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung. Der Wiener Kreis. Wien, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, T. (2005). Political philosophy of science in logical empiricism: The left Vienna Circle. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 36, 754–773.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, T. (2009). Knowing who your friends are: Aspects of the politics of logical empiricism. Science and Education, 18, 161–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, T. (2010). What’s right about Carnap, Neurath and the left Vienna Circle thesis: A refutation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41(2), 214–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1949). ’Objectivity’ in social science and social policy. In The methodology of social sciences (pp. 49–112). Glencoe (Ill.): Free Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to M. Seidel.

Additional information

I would like to thank Reinold Schmücker and the members of his colloquium at the University of Muenster in summer term 2013 for their helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Seidel, M. Changing Society by Scientific Investigations? The Unexpected Shared Ground Between Early Sociology of Knowledge and the Vienna Circle. Found Sci 21, 117–128 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-014-9368-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-014-9368-9

Keywords

Navigation