Skip to main content
Log in

How to Undermine Underdetermination?

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The underdetermination thesis poses a threat to rational choice of scientific theories. We discuss two arguments for the thesis. One draws its strength from deductivism together with the existence thesis, and the other is defended on the basis of the failure of a reliable inductive method. We adopt a partially subjective/objective pragmatic Bayesian epistemology of science framework, and reject both arguments for the thesis. Thus, in science we are able to reinstate rational choice called into question by the underdetermination thesis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a nice survey of the literature contending why the underdetermination thesis is wrong see (Norton 2008). This notion of underdetermination is different from the way Kelly has construed the term in his writings. Kelly (1996) writes, “Underdetermination occurs, roughly, when the same data may arise regardless which of the two competing hypotheses is correct. This is just a special way to argue that no logically reliable inductive method exists relative to scientist’s background assumptions. \(\ldots \)I propose to define underdetermination as the impossibility of reliability (in a given sense) relative to the assumptions at hand. \(\ldots \)We may then hope to map out the structure of degrees of underdetermination in a systematic manner.” In his article (Kelly 2000), he distinguishes two kinds of underdetermination, global underdetermination and local underdetermination. He has also discussed different degrees of local underdetermination. Although we will consider an argument for underdetermination from a failure of a reliable method, unlike Kelly we don’t construe underdetermination in terms of its hierarchies corresponding to different notions of reliability.

  2. These two arguments are relatively new and there is not much discussion of them in recent literature on the topic. Representative examples are Kukla (1998), and especially Mayo (1996). Although Mayo discusses and ultimately rejects different versions of the underdetermination thesis, she has not addressed these arguments.

  3. For several recent papers on the debate between Bayesian and non-Bayesian approaches to inference, decision, prediction, simplicity, and automated reasoning see (Bandyopadhyay and Forster 2011a). See also the “Introduction” to the same edited volume (Bandyopadhyay and Forster 2011b) for a review of these approaches.

  4. The term “deductivism” is a misleading term if it is not properly defined. In their jointly edited book, Grunbam and Salmon (1988) use the term in two different ways. Grunbam while reconstructing Coffa’s view on “deductive chauvinism,” writes, “Coffa applied the term ’deductive chauvinism’ to the view that the higher the probability assigned to an explanandum event, the better the explanation yielding it (private communication).” Salmon, on the other hand, says “Deductivism read: deductive chauvinism) is the view that the only logical devices required in the empirical sciences are deductive.” Salmon in his joint article with Earman (1992) uses deductivism in the same sense when he brands Popper as a deductivist. These two notions of deductivism seem to be misleading unless an attempt is made to relate one notion to the other. If we are to be charitable to them, we should accept Salmon’s construal of deductivism, because it is the standard characterization. Salmon’s sense of deductivism has to do with taking deductive method as used in mathematics, logic and geometry as the paradigm method of understanding science. We, however, are not working with this sense of deductivism.

  5. Earman has attributed this example to Laudan and Leplin. (See Laudan and Leplin 1991).

  6. We follow Boyd (1996) in distinguishing the underdetermination thesis from empirical indistinguishability thesis.

  7. For a different kind of criticism against Laudan and Leplin, see Kukla’s papers. (1993,1998)

  8. We are aware that there are serious controversies about the adequacy of Bayesianism for scientific purposes, but obviously we cannot address all such issues in this paper. For more on those issues see Howson and Urbach (1993), and Earman (1992) for further discussion on these topics.

  9. Our claim that “evidence” could include observable consequence is consistent with our previous argument that observable consequence is neither necessary nor sufficient for being supporting evidence. When we say that evidence is not necessarily observable consequences, this merely says that some evidence may be something that is not an observable consequence. In our case, it was something that was not a consequence at all. That, of course, leaves it open that some (or even most) evidence may be observable consequences. Similarly, in denying that being an observable consequence is sufficient for being evidence, we simply asserted that some observable consequences may not be evidence. The claims we make are very week, but suffice to dispose of the view that evidence = logical consequences.

  10. We are three Bayesians who are worried about the subjective nature of prior probability. Several non-Bayesians also find it to be problematic with Bayesianism. For example, one of Mayo’s main criticisms (1996) against the Bayesian is that the latter’s notion of prior smacks of subjectivism. For a defense of Bayesian position, see Howson and Urbach (1993), chapter 15, pp. 417–419. In the following pages especially in Sect. 6, we find fault with her criticism because it is over-simplicistic.

  11. Hawking and Mlodinow (2010), p. 141. They discuss only the probability of the Pope being a Chinese without addressing Bayesianism or a priori probability.

  12. For a different perspective on the notion of simplicity see Sober (1974, 1995, and also Sober in Forster and Sober 1994). In fact, Sober has subscribed to two accounts of simplicity. (1) A theory is simpler than the other with regard to substantive background assumptions. His first notion of simplicity is influenced by Jack Good’s views on confirmation. See Good (1983) (2) According to Sober’s second notion, a theory is simpler than the other just in case the former contains fewer numbers of adjustable parameters than the latter with respect to some background assumptions of the contending mathematical theories. Sober’s second notion draws its strength from his joint work with Forster. We thank Sober for helping us understand his position better. Our view of simplicity overlaps with Swinburne’s view of simplicity. For the latter view see Swinburne (2001).

  13. There are several objective measures of “complexity” in a variety of contexts such as computational, logical (syntactic, semantic, and descriptive), information-theoretic, and statistical. One important notion known as Kolmogorov complexity (see, Li and Vitanyi 2008) actually straddles several of the above contexts, and is also closely related to randomness (see Dasgupta 2011, where further references may be found). See footnote 24 for measures of simplicity from the statistical perspective, which is the one most relevant for our purposes.

  14. One of the referees provided further information about some some automated regression-methods that although do not explicitly involve prior probability, do take into account the degree of simplicity in statistical models. For more on this point, see footnote 24. For evaluation of the use of AIC, see Bandyopadhyay et al. (2013).

  15. See Swinburne’s introduction in Swinburne 2002. See also Sober (2002b) in Swinburne, ed. 2002. Although the former is a Bayesian and the latter is a non-Bayesian, both of them share the same view about the division of Bayesianism under these two heads.

  16. Several papers are already written on non-informative priors. Objective or robust Bayesian accounts for less subjective or even objective ways to assign priors are cases in point (see Berger 1994). This point is due to one of the referees of the paper.

  17. Empirical indistinguishability is sometimes defined in terms of theories entailing (perhaps with background assumptions) the same evidence. Our definition is more general, since it does not specify the relation between evidence and the theory it confirms.

  18. He requires the set to include all but a set of measure 0 of possible worlds from a larger set of possible worlds including all possible values of evidence statements.

  19. The problem related to reliability of scientific methods is Earman’s one live research problem. For his recent position on reliability, see Earman and Roberts [forthcoming]. In this paper, they offer two arguments, epistemological and semantic arguments for the Humean supervenience (HS) thesis. According to HS thesis, there do not exist any two possible worlds that agree with respect to Humean base, but disagree on what the laws are. The central theme of their arguments is that if laws matter to science, then the only way to make sense of that is to assume HS thesis. Their epistemological argument rests heavily on assuming the reliability of scientific methods. This line of defense of HS thesis on the basis of reliability of methods goes against the spirit of Earman’s argument for underdetermination. However, we won’t address this yet to be published Earman’s paper.

  20. Earman’s views on Bayesian subjectivism have undergone changes over the years. In Earman’s Bayes or Bust?, he was prone to Bayesian personalism (subjectivism). However, he made an observation that gave the impression that he also cared for objectivity of scientific inference. To quote, “This [i.e., the value of the crucial factor prob(E/not T & K)] may be acceptable to the thorough going Bayesian personalists, but it is unacceptable to anyone who wants to find a modicum of objectivity in scientific inference.” (p. 168). In 92, he was yet to be a through going personalist. He didn’t seem to endorse full-scale personalism in that context. In 93 during the time Earman wrote (1993), he became converted to personalism. One possible way out of the inconsistent triad (that consists of semantic realism, epistemic realism and the underdetermination thesis together) was to invoke subjective priors. He, however, didn’t adopt that move in that paper. He opted for antirealism instead. In this paper, however, he didn’t consider one possibility, that is, there could be some constraints on priors which need not lead to subjectivism. In his recent book, Hume’s Abject Failure, he has considered both constraints, subjective and objective, on priors. It is clear that he is a full-blown subjectivist (personalist) in this book. According to Earman, satisfying probability calculus provides the only constraint on the structure of an agent’s belief within Bayesianism. He holds further that this rationality constraint of Bayesianism fails to deliver the truth or the objectivity of the agent’s beliefs. We thank Earman for clarifying his position to us through e-mails.

  21. One needs to be careful that a priori probabilities are not the same as prior probabilities although the latter are acquired from the former by conditionalizing prior probabilities on a priori probabilities together with all the evidence and background information an agent has before the prior has been fixed. Those priors in question are found with the help an agent’s a priori probabilities, background information and evidence so far gathered till the prior has been determined.

  22. Some Bayesians might think that our approach to inferential problems, whether one employs estimation technique, or hypothesis testing technique, is completely misguided. According to our Bayesian critics, after all, the purpose of most inferential studies is to provide the statistician or the client with decisions. Hence, for them, it is much more relevant to provide evaluation criteria of decision (for such a position, see Robert (1994, p. 39) However, we disagree with them, because we are primarily interested in non-decision theoretical approach to theory choice.

  23. See Kass and Raftery 1995). However, how BIC approximation has been carried out also becomes crucial. Schwartz’s BIC approximation has a natural probability-based interpretation, whereas some others do not have it (see, Boik 2004 for more on this topic.)

  24. Various statistical methods, such as the Least Absolute Shrinkage and Selection Operator (lasso), adjusted \(R^{2}\), and ridge regression, penalize for number of parameters (complexity) through regularization, or shrinkage. Shrinkage methods are a more continuous alternative to simply retaining or discarding variables and can be used to decrease prediction error. They typically involve penalize the absolute size of the regression coefficient and can be convenient when we want some automatic feature/variable selection or when dealing with highly correlated variables. Lasso uses a data-dependent penalty term (beyond just dependence on sample size), as opposed to model selection criteria such as BIC, BTC, and AIC. (See, Park and Cassella 2008; Kyung et al. 2010) One of the referees of this paper has called out attention to these recent statistical papers on the relevant issue.

  25. We owe this point to one of the referees.

  26. For a Bayesian account of evidence, see Bandyopadhyay et al. (2006; 2007).

  27. We wish to thank J. Allard, R. Boik, G. Brittan, C. Howson, J. Earman, J. Good, K. Intemann, K. Kelly, J. Leplin, S. Levy, E. McIyntre, P. Mukhopadhyay, J. Roberts, S. Roy, E. Sober, S. Vineberg, John Welch, G. Wheeler and several referees of various journals for their suggestions regarding the contents of the paper. We are especially thankful to three referees of this journal for their detailed suggestions and insightful comments on the previous draft of this manuscript. Some versions of the paper were presented at the Society for the Exact Philosophy meetings in Montreal, the Methodology Conference in Santinekatan, and the American Philosophical Association meetings in Chicago. The paper has been financially supported by the NASA’s Astrobiology Biogeocatalysis Research Center (Grant number # 4w 1781) and the Scholarships and Creativity grant from Montana State University.

References

  • Akaike, H. (1973) Information theory and an extension of the maximum likelihood principle. In B. N. Petrov & N. Csaki (Eds.), Second international symposium on information theory (pp. 267–281). Budapest: Akademiai Kiado.

  • Bandyopadhyay, P.S., & Bennett, J. G. (forthcoming). Pragmatic Bayesianism and problems of scientific methodology. In R. Roy Choudhury & B. Mukherjee (Eds.), Sciences and methods. Asiatic Society, Calcutta

  • Bandyopadhyay, P. S., Boik, R. J., & Basu, P. (1996). The curve fitting problem: A Bayesian approach. Philosophy of Science, 63(supplement), 264–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bandyopadhyay, P. S., & Boik, R. J. (1999). The Curve fitting problem: A Bayesian rejoinder. Philosophy of Science, 66(supplement), 391–402.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bandyopadhyay, P. S., & Brittan, G. (2001). Logical consequence and beyond: A close look at model selection in statistics. In J. Woods & B. Hepburn (Eds.), Logical consequence (pp. 1–17). Oxford: Hermes Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bandyopadhyay, P. S., & Brittan, G. (2006). Acceptance, evidence, and severity. Synthese, 148, 259–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bandyopadhyay, P. S. (2007). Why Bayesianism? A primer on a probabilistic philosophy of science. In S. K. Upadhyayay, U. Sing, & D. K. Dey (Eds.), Bayesian statistics and its applications. New Delhi: Anamaya Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bandyopadhyay, P. S., & Brittan, G. (2010). Two dogmas of strong objective Bayesianism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 24, 45–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bandyopadhyay, P. S., & Forster, F. R. (Eds.). (2011a). Introduction. In Philosophy of Statistics. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

  • Bandyopadhyay, P. S., & Forster, M. R. (Eds.). (2011b). Handbook of Philosophy of Statistics. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bandyopadhyay, P. S., Greenwood, M., Brittan Jr, G., & Aho, K. A. (2013). Empiricism and/or instrumentalism? Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-013-9567-8.

  • Berger, J. O. (1994). An overview of Robust Bayesian analysis [with Discussion]. Test, 3, 5–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boik. R. J. (2004). “Commentary”. In Taper and Lele (Eds.), The nature of scientific evidence (pp. 167–180). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Boyd, R. (1996). Realism, approximate truth, and philosophical method. In D. Papineau (Ed.), Philosophy of science (pp. 215–255). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, A. (2011). Mathematical foundations of randomness. In P. S. Bandyopadhyay & M. R. Forster (Eds.), Handbook of philosophy of statistics (pp. 641–710). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J., & Salmon, W., et al. (1992). The confirmation of scientific theories. In M. Salmon, et al. (Eds.), Introduction to the philosophy of science. Berkeley: University of California Press.

  • Earman, J., (1993). Underdetermination, realism, and reason. In P. French, et al. (Eds.), Midwest studies in philosophy, Vol. XVIII (pp. 19–38). Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press.

  • Earman. J., & Roberts. J. (Forthcoming). Contacts with the Nomic: Two challenges for deniers of humean supervinience about Laws of nature.

  • Earman, J. (1992). Bayes or Bust?. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forster, M., & Sober, E. (1994). How to tell when simpler more unified, or less Ad Hoc theories will provide more accurate predictions. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 45, 1–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Good, J. (1992). The Bayes/non-Bayes compromise: A brief review. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 87, 597–606.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grunbam, A., & Salmon, W. (Eds.). (1988). The Limitations of Deductivism. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1997). Pragmatism and reasons for belief. In C. B. Kulp & N. J. Totowa (Eds.), Realism/antirealism and epistemology (pp. 123–147). Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawking, S., & Mlodinow, L. (2010). The grand design. New York: Bantom Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanations and other essays in philosophy of science. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoefer, C., & Rosenberg, A. (1994). Empirical equivalence, underdetermination, and system of the world. Philosophy of Science, 61(1994), 592–607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howson. C., & Urbach. P. (1993) Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian approach, 2nd edition and 3rd edition, Open Court, La Salle, Illinois, 1993 & 2006.

  • Kass, R.E., & Raftery A. F (1995) Bayes factor. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 90(430).

  • Kelly, K. (1996). The logic of reliable enquiry. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, K. (2000). The logic of success. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51, 639–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, A. (1993). Laudan, leplin, empirical equivalence and underdetermination. Analysis, 53(1), 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, A. (1998). Studies in scientific realism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyung, M., Gill, J., Ghosh, M., & Cassella, G. (2010). Penalized regression, standard errors, and Bayesian lassos. Bayesian Analysis, 5, 369–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1995). Damn the consequenences. In Proceedings of American philosophical association, 69:2, Presidential Address. Pacific Division (pp. 27–34).

  • Laudan, L. (1990). Demystifying underdetermination. In C. Wade Savage (Ed.), Scientific theories (Vol. XIV, pp. 267–297). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L., & Leplin, J. (1991). Empirical equivalence and underdetermination. Journal of Philosophy, 88, 449–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defense of scientific realism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Li, M., & Vitanyi, P. (2008). An introduction to Kolmogorov complexity and its applications. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mayo, D. (1996). Error: The growth of experimental knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2008). Must evidence underdetermine theory? In M. Carrier, D. Howard, & J. Kourany (Eds.), The challenge of the social and the pressure of practice: Science and values revisited (pp. 17–44). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, T., & Cassella, G. (2008). The Bayesian Lasso. In Journal of the American Statistical Association, 103, 681–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Press, S., & Tanur, J. (2001). The subjectivity of scientists and the Bayesian statistical approach. New York: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. (1953). Two Dogmas of Empiricism. In from a logical point of view (pp. 20–46). Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

  • Quine, W. (1975). Empirically equivalent systems of the world. Erkenntniss, 9, 313–328.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raftery, A. (1995). Bayesian model selection in social research. In P. V. Marsden (Ed.), Sociological methodology (with Discussion) (pp. 111–195). Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robert, C. (1994). The Bayesian choice. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Royall, R. (1997). Statistical evidence: A likelihood paradigm. New York: Chapman Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz, G. (1978). Estimating the dimension of a model. The Annals of Statistics, 6, 461–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1984). Pragmatism and empiricism. New Heaven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2002a). Comments on Prasanta Bandyopadhyay’s “Simplicity: Our View, Their View. Central Division, Chicago: APA.

  • Sober, E. (2002b). Bayesianism–Its Scope and Limits. In Swinburne (2002).

  • Sober, E. (1974). Simplicity. England: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1995). From a biological point of view. England: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (Ed.). (2002). Bayes’s theorem. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1991). Quantum mechanics: An empiricist view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weirich, P. (2011). The Bayesian decision-theoretic approach to statistics. In P. S. Bandyopadhyay & M. R. Forster (Eds.), Handbook of philosophy of statistics (pp. 233–261). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Prasanta S. Bandyopadhyay.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bandyopadhyay, P.S., Bennett, J.G. & Higgs, M.D. How to Undermine Underdetermination?. Found Sci 20, 107–127 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-014-9353-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-014-9353-3

Keywords

Navigation