Skip to main content
Log in

Similarity Arguments in the Genetic Modification Debate

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the ethical debate on genetic modification (GM), it is common to encounter the claim that some anti-GM argument would also apply an established, ethically accepted technology, and that the anti-GM argument is therefore unsuccessful. The paper discusses whether this argumentative strategy, the Similarity Argument, is sound. It presents a logically valid, generic form of the Similarity Argument and then shows that it is subject to three types of objection: (i) It does not respect the difference between pro tanto reasons and all-things-considered judgments; (ii) it relies on the unproblematic transferability of reasons from one case to another; and (iii) it runs the risk of equivocations, especially in cases where the anti-genetic-modification argument relies on gradable features. The paper then shows how these issues play out in three specific Similarity Arguments that can be found in the literature. Finally, the paper discusses what conclusions we can draw from the fact that genetic modification and established technologies are similar for the ethical status of genetic modification.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. By ‘genetic modification’ I mean technologies that directly alter the genomes of organisms, such as transgenesis, genome editing and synthetic biology. Several ‘borderline’ technologies could be included, e.g. mutagenesis and protoplast fusion. These are rarely discussed, and I will not say anything specific about them in the paper. I am mainly concerned with the debate concerning GM applied to plants and microorganisms, but I presume similarity claims and arguments occur in the case of human- and animal GM as well – and indeed in many other fields of applied ethics.

  2. In a different version of the same article (Pugh 2015b), it is described merely as “familiar”.

  3. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer and Julian Savulescu for pressing me to clarify this.

  4. Or more precisely, other considerations may provide a reason to judge that the original consideration is not, after all, a reason for the original judgment. The notion of exclusion (and enabling) that is the basis of the default view also constitutes Dancy’s grounds for defending particularism. It is thus plausible to take the default view to capture all the worries about transferability that Dancy’s view does.

  5. The relation between excluding considerations and enabling considerations is unclear – they may simply be different ways of describing the same thing. My sense is that the main difference between considerations that are most aptly described as excluders and enablers, respectively, is whether the situations they point to can be described as ‘standard conditions’ or the ‘normal’ state of affairs.

  6. To avoid unnecessary confusion: Note that Paul B. Thompson is a different person from R. Paul Thompson, cited in §1

  7. Histories of such interventions that support this view are provided by Richard W. Bulleit (2005) for the case of animals, and by Denis J. Murphy (2007) for the case of plants. It is plausible, according to these accounts, that early domestication was entirely unintentional, i.e. that humans exercised no conscious control of organisms’ genotype.

  8. Of course, biocentrists within environmental ethics have ways of arguing that our intuitions about the moral standing of microorganisms and plants does not decide the issue of their moral standing.

  9. Tom Douglas has suggested (in conversation) that some similarity arguments are used simply as interpretative tools, designed to bring out what the critic’s view most plausibly is.

References

  • Blackburn S (1996) Securing the nots: moral epistemology for the quasi-realist’. In: Sinnott-Armstrong W, Timmons M (eds) Moral knowledge? new readings in moral epistemology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Boldt J (2013) Life as a technological product: philosophical and ethical aspects of synthetic biology. Biol Theory 8:391–401

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boldt J, Müller O (2008) Newtons of the Leaves of Grass. Nature Biotechnol 26:387–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bulleit RW (2005) Hunters, Herders and Hamburgers: the past and future of human-animal relationships. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen GA (2011) Rescuing Conservatism. In: Wallace RJ, Kumar R, Freeman S (eds) Reasons and Recognition: essays on the philosophy of T.M. Scanlon. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 203–230

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy J (1993) Moral Reasons. Blackwell, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Deckers J (2005) Are scientists right and non-scientists wrong? reflections on discussions of GM. J Agr Environ Ethic 18:451–478

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaskell G et al (2010) Europeans and biotechnology in 2010: Winds of change? Report to the European Commissions Directorate-General for Research. http://ec.europa.eu/public_opinion/archives/ebs/ebs_341_winds_en.pdf. Accessed 17 June 2016

  • Holtug N (2009) Creating and Patenting New Life Forms. In: Kuhse H, Singer P (eds) A companion to bioethics, 2nd edn. Wiley-Blackwell, Malden, pp. 235–244

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Horty JF (2007) Reasons as defaults. The Imprint 7:1–28

  • Horty JF (2012) Reasons as defaults. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Labels for GMO Foods Are a Bad Idea (2013). Editorial, Scientific American, 1 September 2013. http://www.scientificamerican.com/article/labels-for-gmo-foods-are-a-bad-idea/. Accessed 26 January 2016

  • Lee K (1999) The Natural and the Artefactual: the implications of deep science and deep technology for environmental ethics. Lexington Books, Lanham

    Google Scholar 

  • Marris C, Wynne B, Simmons P, Weldon S (2001) Public Perceptions of Agricultural Biotechnologies in Europe. Final Report of the PABE research project. www.csec.lancs.ac.uk/archive/pabe/docs/pabe_finalreport.pdf . Accessed 26 January 2016

  • McKibben B (2003) The End of Nature, revised ed. Random House:London

  • Mielby H, Sandøe P, Lassen J (2013) Multiple aspects of unnaturalness: are cisgenic crops perceived as being more natural and more acceptable than transgenic crops? Agric Hum Values 30:471–480

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy DJ (2007) People, Plants and Genes: the story of crops and humanity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick R (1974) Anarchy, State and Utopia. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston CJ (2012) Synthetic biology: drawing a line in Darwin’s sand. Environ Value 17:23–39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preston B (2013) Synthetic biology as red herring. Stud Hist Phil Biol Biomed Sci 44:649–659

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pugh J (2015a) The Ethics of Genetically Modified Mosquitoes and Gene-Drive Technology, Ethics in the News, 2 December 2015. http://blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk/2015/12/the-ethics-of-genetically-modified-mosquitoes-and-gene-drive-technology/. Accessed 15 June 2016

  • Pugh J (2015b) Playing God with mosquitoes? We humans have loftier aims. The Conversation, 2 December 2015. https://theconversation.com/playing-god-with-mosquitoes-we-humans-have-loftier-aims-51362. Accessed 15 June 2016

  • Rozin P (2005) The meaning of “natural”: process more important than content. Psychol Sci 16:652–658

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rozin P et al (2004) Preference for natural: instrumental and ideational/moral motivations, and the contrast between foods and medicines. Appetite 43:147–154

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rozin P, Fischler C, Shields-Argelès (2009) Additivity dominance: additives are more potent and more often lexicalized across languages than “subtractives”. Judgm Decis Mak 4:475–478

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandler RL (2007) Character and environment. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Swierstra T, Rip A (2007) Nano-ethics as NEST-ethics: patterns of moral argumentation about new and emerging science and technology. Nanoethics 1:3–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson PB (2003) Unnatural farming and the debate over genetic manipulation. In: Gehring VV (ed) Genetic Prospects: essays on biotechnology, ethics and public policy. Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson J (2010) The Apology Paradox. Philos Quart 50:470–475

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson RP (2011) Agro-technology: a philosophical introduction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Whaley BB (1998) Evaluations of rebuttal analogy users: ethical and competence considerations. Argumentation 12:351–365

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Thomas Douglas, Darien Haim, Sune Holm, Martin Marchman Andersen and Julian Savulescu for valuable comments on this and earlier versions of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andreas Christiansen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Christiansen, A. Similarity Arguments in the Genetic Modification Debate. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 20, 239–255 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-016-9757-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-016-9757-y

Keywords

Navigation