Skip to main content
Log in

Moral Beliefs for the Error Theorist?

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The moral error theory holds that moral claims and beliefs, because they commit us to the existence of illusory entities, are systematically false or untrue. It is an open question what we should do with moral thought and discourse once we have become convinced by this view. Until recently, this question had received two main answers. The abolitionist proposed that we should get rid of moral thought altogether. The fictionalist, though he agreed we should eliminate moral beliefs, enjoined us to replace them with attitudes that resemble to some extent the attitudes we have towards pieces of fiction. But there is now a third theory on the market: conservationism, the view that we should keep holding moral beliefs, even though we know them to be false. (According to a fourth theory, ‘substitutionism’, we should modify the content of our moral claims in such a way that they become true.) Putting abolitionism (and substitutionism) aside, our aim is to assess the plausibility of conservationism as an alternative to the – relatively dominant – fictionalism that we find in the literature. Given the difficulty of finding a conservationist view that is both (i) plausible and (ii) not merely a terminological variant of fictionalism, we will argue that conservationism fails to constitute a plausible alternative to fictionalism, at least insofar as it purports to be an alternative view as to what we should do with our moral thoughts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Other errors one may attribute to moral discourse include, inter alia, the commitment to the existence of God, to the existence of free will, or to the possibility of a convergence in desires between fully rational agents (Smith 1994).

  2. The typical error theorist has no problem with reasons as such. What he finds objectionable are categorical reasons. As a consequence, the error theorist will be happy to recognize that we have hypothetical reasons to value the most effective means to our ends, whatever they are.

  3. The distinction is often construed as one between two proposals about how we should use moral discourse. As Jonas Olson’s critique of Richard Joyce’s proposal, which will be the focus of this paper, is principally at the psychological level, we prefer to construe the distinction as primarily a psychological one.

  4. These are not intended to be definitions but a characterization of one crucial difference between belief and make-belief (Joyce, personal communication, May 2014). For the sake of simplicity, we will nonetheless call these ‘theories’.

  5. Since fictionalism, as we construe it here, is a view about what we should do once we have accepted the error theory, there is no need to mention that we should have dissented from the proposition Killing is wrong in the past.

  6. Metaethics is here not construed as a discipline only philosophers are concerned about. Thinking that there might not be objective moral truths is doing metaethics, a similar way thinking that there might or might not be a God is engaging in metaphysics (or philosophy of religion). It is clear to us that the folks do philosophy every once in a while.

  7. Another contender is substitutionism, recently defended by Lutz (2014), according to which, roughly, we should modify the content of our moral claims in such a way that they end up being true. Interestingly, Mackie himself may have envisaged just this possibility in his 1976 book, Problems from Locke: “A similar conceptual reform [to the one about personal identity I am proposing], rather than mere analysis of our present concepts, is, I believe, needed for ethics. I hope to discuss this topic in another book” (Mackie 1976, p. 196n27). Thanks to an anonymous referee for drawing our attention to this passage.

  8. See also Brown 2011, for a similar defence.

  9. In a recent article (Suikkanen 2013), Jussi Suikkanen argues, among other things, that both fictionalism and conservationism are problematic given that the conceptions of belief on which they rely are inconsistent with the most appealing theories of belief that we find in the literature. While we think that Suikkanen’s point is ultimately successful – that the prescriptive views in the debate make implausible assumptions about the nature of belief – our purpose in this paper is much narrower in scope: it is to assess the possibility of defending a genuine conservationist alternative to a relatively influential fictionalist position. This project, we take it, can be pursued even if we think that both fictionalism and conservationism are ultimately inadequate.

  10. Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting this interpretation to us.

  11. We take it that, on a plausible interpretation of Joyce’s theory of belief, a context at which one reminds oneself one’s theoretical commitment on some matter counts as a critical context. It is not because the make-believer does not engage in some serious metaethics when reminding herself of the truth of the error theory that she thereby fails to be in a critical context.

  12. Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting the following way of construing Olson’s account of belief.

  13. See in particular, his remarks on ‘compartmentalization’ (2011, p. 199).

  14. Because she wishes to accommodate the ordinary notion of make-belief, or simply because she takes it that the fictionalist would adopt this constraint in drawing a distinction between belief* and make-belief*.

  15. Other paradigmatic examples include children’s games of make-believe, videogames, and role-playing games. For a discussion of make-believe in its paradigmatic forms, see Walton (1990). For a discussion of the emotional and motivational aspects of our engagement in such activities, see Cova & Naar (manuscript).

References

  • Brown P (2011) The error in moral discourse and what to do about it. PhD dissertation, University of Manchester

  • Garner RT (2006) On the genuine queerness of moral facts. Australas J Philos 68(2):137–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garner RT (2007) Abolishing morality. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 10(5):499–513

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene J D (2002) The terrible, horrible, no good, very bad truth about morality, and what to do about it. PhD dissertation, Princeton University

  • Hare RM (1981) Moral thinking: Its levels, method, and point. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Hinckfuss I (1987) The moral society: its structure and effects. Australian National University, Canberra

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce R (2001) The myth of morality. Cambridge University Press, Canberra

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce R (2006) Metaethics and the empirical sciences. Philos Explor 9:133–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lutz M (2014) The ‘now what’ problem for error theory. Philos Stud 171:351–371

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie JL (1976) Problems from Locke. Oxford Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie JL (1977) Ethics: inventing right and wrong. Penguin, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson J (2011) Getting real about moral fictionalism. In: Shafer-Landau R (ed) Oxford studies in metaethics, vol 6. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 182–204

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith M (1994) The Moral Problem. Oxford: Basil Blackwell

  • Suikkanen J (2013) Moral error theory and the belief problem. In: Shafer-Landau R (ed) Oxford studies in metaethics, vol 8. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 168–194

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor SE, Brown JD (1988) Illusion and well-being: a social psychological perspective on mental health. Psychol Bull 103:193–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton KL (1990) Mimesis as make-believe: on the foundations of the representational arts. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Richard Joyce, Richard Dub, Florian Cova, audiences in Geneva and Ovronnaz, Switzerland, and two anonymous reviewers for this journal for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper. We also would like to thank the Swiss National Science Foundation (SNSF) and the Center for Research on Ethics (CRE) for their generous support at various stages of the writing.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to François Jaquet.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jaquet, F., Naar, H. Moral Beliefs for the Error Theorist?. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 19, 193–207 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-015-9609-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-015-9609-1

Keywords

Navigation