Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Reconciling Just Causes for Armed Humanitarian Intervention

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Michael Walzer argues that the just cause for humanitarian intervention is not met if there are only “ordinary” levels of human rights abuses within a state because he believes that respecting the right to collective self-determination is more morally important than protecting other individual rights. Several prominent critics of Walzer advocate for a more permissive account of a just cause. They argue that protecting individuals’ human rights is more morally important than respecting a right to collective self-determination. I argue that these two accounts are far more similar than either Walzer or his critics realize because collective self-determination requires the protection of some human rights in order to allow each person the opportunity to participate in collective choices. Consequently, the just cause for intervention is met whenever at least some important human rights of one person are violated and others are being credibly threatened. The counter intuitive conclusion of my argument is that justified interventions can actually promote rather than undermine collective self-determination because just interventions allow innocents, who otherwise would have excluded from this process, the opportunity to contribute to collective choices. Of course, a just cause is insufficient in itself for intervention to be permissible because other just war precepts must also be met.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I exclude discussion of a third, amoral strand of realism, because I am interested in the morality of intervention.

  2. For a view on why democracy requires the protection of certain individual rights, see (Beetham 1999).

  3. Wellman’s ideas about state legitimacy seem to have evolved between his 2009 book that he co-authored with Altman and his 2012 single authored article.

  4. Monty Marshall and Keith Jaggers, “Polity IV Data,” 2010.

  5. An exception to the impermissibility of intentionally targeting just intervening soldiers is when intervening soldiers violate jus in bello rules. For instance, if a fighter pilot who is on the side with a just cause sought revenge for a colleague’s death by intentionally targeting an apartment building in which everyone in it is innocent, it would be permissible for the unjust combatant to intentionally target the pilot. Innocent civilians who would be killed by just combatants as an unintentional although foreseeable result of a just war might also permissibly defend themselves against the just combatants. See respectively, McMahan, Killing in War, 16 and section 2.1.

  6. Walzer allows the intentional targeting of civilians who are involved in efforts that are exclusively involved in war such as building tanks, but not duel use products such as food because food can feed soldiers or civilians (Walzer, Just And Unjust Wars, 145–146.).

  7. Some of these would technically not be interventions because they have the consent of the target state. The typical justification for intervention of saving innocents’ lives is also contestable; the US government generally justifies them by arguing it keeps Americans safer than they would be without such strikes.

  8. For a similar method of argument, see (Christiano 2011).

References

  • Altman A, Wellman C (2009) A Liberal Theory of International Justice. Oxford University Press, USA

  • Annan K (1999) Two Concepts of Sovereignty. The Economist. http://www.economist.com/node/324795

  • Beetham D (1999) Democracy and Human Rights, 1st edn. Polity

  • Beitz C (1980) Nonintervention and communal integrity. Philos Public Aff 9(4):385–391

    Google Scholar 

  • Beitz C (2001) Human rights as a common concern. Am Polit Sci Rev 95(2):269–282

  • Beitz C (2009) The moral standing of states revisited. Ethics Int Aff 23(4):325–347. doi:10.1111/j.1747-7093.2009.00227.x

  • Bellamy A (2011) Global Politics and the Responsibility to Protect: From Words to Deeds. Routledge, New York

  • Christiano T (2011) An instrumental argument for a human right to democracy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 39(2):142–176. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.2011.01204.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen J (2006) Is There a Human Right to Democracy? In: C Sypnowich (ed) The Egalitarian Conscience: Essays in Honour of G. A. Cohen. Oxford University Press, USA, 226–48

  • Doyle M (2009) A few words on mill, walzer, and nonintervention. Ethics Int Aff 23(04):349–369. doi:10.1111/j.1747-7093.2009.00228.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1984) Rights as Trumps. In: Waldron J (ed) Theories of Rights. Oxford University Press, USA, pp 153–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans G, Sahnoun M, Côté-Harper G, Hamilton L, Ignatieff M, Lukin V, Naumann K, et al. (2001) The Responsibility to Protect: The Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty. IDRC Books: Ontario

  • Fabre C (2012) Cosmopolitan War. Oxford University Press, USA

  • Frowe H (2010) A practical account of self-defence. Law Philos 29(3):245–272. doi:10.1007/s10982-009-9062-1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frowe H (2011) The Ethics of War and Peace: An Introduction. Routledge

  • Goodin R (2007) Enfranchising all affected interests, and its alternatives. Philos Public Aff 25:40–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurka T (2005) Proportionality in the morality of war. Philos Public Aff 33(1):34–66

  • Hurka T (2008) Proportionality and Necessity. In: L May (ed) War: Essays in Political Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, 127–44

  • Luban D (1980a) Just war and human rights. Philos Public Aff 9(2):160–181

    Google Scholar 

  • Luban D (1980b) The romance of the nation-state. Philos Public Aff 9(4):392–397

    Google Scholar 

  • Manza J, Uggen C (2006) Locked Out: Felon Disenfranchisement and American Democracy. Oxford University Press, USA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mapel DR (2010) Moral liability to defensive killing and symmetrical self-defense. J Polit Philos 18(2):198–217. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9760.2009.00340.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan J (1994) Innocence, self-defense and killing in war. J Polit Philos 2(3):193–221. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9760.1994.tb00021.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan J (1996) Intervention and collective self-determination. Ethics Int Aff 10(1):1–24. doi:10.1111/j.1747-7093.1996.tb00001.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan J (2005) The basis of moral liability to defensive killing. Philos Issues 15(1):386–405. doi:10.1111/j.1533-6077.2005.00073.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan J (2009) Killing in War, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • McMahan J (2010) Humanitarian Intervention, Consent, and Proportionality. In: Davis A, Keshen R, McMahan J (eds) Ethics and Humanity: Themes from the Philosophy of Jonathan Glover. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Orwell G (1945) Politics and the English Language. In: Essays. Everyman’s Library, pp. 954–67

  • Pattison J (2010) Humanitarian Intervention and the Responsibility To Protect: Who Should Intervene? Oxford University Press, USA

  • Philpott D (2001) Revolutions in Sovereignty: How Ideas Shaped Modern International Relations. Princeton University Press

  • Pogge T (2003) Preempting Humanitarian Interventions. In: Jokic A (ed) Humanitarian Intervention: Moral and Philosophical Issues. Broadview Press, Peterborough, pp. 93–108

  • Quong J (2012) Liability to defensive harm. Philos Public Aff 40(1):45–77. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.2012.01217.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1999) The Law of Peoples: With “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited”, 1st edn. Harvard University Press

  • Rodin D (2002) War and Self-Defense. Oxford University Press, USA

  • Rodin D (2014) Rethinking Responsibility to Protect: The Case for Human Sovereignty. In: D E Scheid (ed) The Ethics of Armed Humanitarian Intervention. Cambridge University Press, 243–60

  • Walzer M (1973) Political action: the problem of dirty hands. Philos Public Aff 2(2):160–180

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer M (1977 [2000]) Just And Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument With Historical Illustrations, 3rd edn. Basic Books

  • Walzer M (1980) The moral standing of states: a response to four critics. Philos Public Aff 9(3):209–229

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer M (2007) The Argument About Humanitarian Intervention. In: Miller D (ed) Thinking Politically: Essays in Political Theory. Yale University Press, New Haven, pp. 237-250

  • Walzer M (2011) The Wrong Intervention. Dissent Magazine. http://www.dissentmagazine.org/online_articles/the-wrong-intervention

  • Wellman C (2012) Debate: taking human rights seriously. J Polit Philos 20(1):119–130. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9760.2011.00407.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eamon Aloyo.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Aloyo, E. Reconciling Just Causes for Armed Humanitarian Intervention. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 19, 313–328 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-015-9594-4

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-015-9594-4

Keywords

Navigation