Skip to main content
Log in

Distributive Justice, Feasibility Gridlocks, and the Harmfulness of Economic Ideology

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many political theorists think about how to make societies more just. In recent years, with interests shifting from principles to their institutional realization, there has been much debate about feasibility and the role it should play in theorizing. What has been underexplored, however, is how feasibility depends on the attitudes and perceptions of individuals, not only with regard to their own behaviour, but also with regard to the behaviour of others. This can create coordination problems, which can be described as “feasibility gridlocks”. These problems are interesting from a normative perspective, not only because they arguably play an important role for the feasibility of institutions, but also because they contain a normative element themselves: individual might be willing to cooperate in order change the “feasibility frontier” (Wiens D (forthcoming) Political ideals and the feasibility frontier. Econ Philos), but only if others are also willing to do their bit, which contains a judgment about the fair distribution of burdens. Beliefs about the selfish nature of human beings, however, can make feasibility gridlocks more likely. This is why what I call, for the sake of brevity, “economic ideology”, i.e. an account of human nature as fundamentally self-interested, can be harmful. Finding a way out of such equilibriums therefore is an important task for political theorists and social reformers.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some authors, however, for example Sen 2008 and Wiens (esp. 2012) argue that we can address current injustices and institutional failures directly. This position seems correct with regard to some injustices—in fact, some current injustices might be such that we do not need any theorizing at all—but it does not seem correct with regard to all questions political theorists work on.

  2. There can be indirect connections to questions of motivation, for example via the motivation of public service employees, but I cannot go into these details here.

  3. See also Cohen 2001 for a discussion of G.A. Cohen’s critique of Rawls. One of J. Cohen’s replies is that for Rawls, egalitarian institutions would lead to an egalitarian ethos, which would make high incentives for talented workers less necessary.

  4. One problem in this context is that economic models often work at a level of abstraction that makes it hard to reject their assumptions. For example, they assume that individuals prefer more money to less money, working with an implicit “ceteris paribus” clause: if one can work in exactly the same job for more or less money, it seems plausible that most people would choose more money. But often “ceteris” is not “paribus”; for example, jobs usually differ along more dimensions than the wage level. Thus, the statement that individuals prefer more money to less money may not be very useful for making predictions about their behaviour in real-life situations, and it may be misleading if it implies that this is the only, or the most important, factor determining their decisions.

  5. Whether working harder and earning more actually go hand in hand in our economies is an open question. I here assume it only for the sake of argument.

  6. Of course, there could also be different “economic ideologies”, for example in different historical eras. I use the term “ideology” because such views have wide-reaching implications for how one sees the world, which are based on—at least partly—wrong assumptions and which favour certain interests over others.

  7. If the utility individuals draw from their income also depends on their relative position, this can add to the unwillingness to contribute if others do not do their bit, because in addition to the loss in absolute terms, there would be an even greater loss in relative terms.

  8. In addition, it might also characterize economic failure as a matter of lacking ambitions or bad character, rather than bad luck or structural tendencies in the economy.

  9. One might also imagine that individuals are not only “conditional co-operators”, but also hold certain views about what they are obliged to do depending on what others do. As Lawford-Smith (2013b) discusses, if some task is only feasible for a group, and an individual correctly anticipates that others will fail to do their bit, there can be cases in which individuals do not have an obligation to attempt to do the task on their own, because such an attempt would be futile. The cases I am interested in concern large-scale societies; one can imagine that in them some individuals hold such views, rightly or wrongly, which can exacerbate the problem.

  10. Lawford-Smith (2013a, 247) explicitly notes that “uncoordinated aggregates of individuals” may not have the possibility to “bring about” an outcome that matters for evaluating its feasibility. In 2013b, she analyses various forms of collective action, and how they relate to the individuals’ duties. Wiens (2014, 5) mentions the “problem of assurance” as affecting an individual’s motivation to cooperate, but he does not discuss this point any further.

  11. Of course, individuals might also hold overly positive beliefs about the willingness to cooperate and to behave altruistically. But a person who wrongly believes her peers to be more altruistic than they really are is likely to learn her lesson relatively quickly. In the scenario that underestimates the willing to cooperate, it is more likely to be stuck in an equilibrium in which individuals have no opportunity to find out that their beliefs are wrong.

  12. van Someren Greve (2014) discusses feasibility and fairness from a different perspective, namely whether or not it can be unfair to be required to do something one cannot do, a claim which he rejects. What I am interested in is the question of fairness with regard to some doing their duty and other failing to do so.

  13. I would like to thank Andrew Walton and audiences at the University of Tilburg and the University of Zurich, as well as two reviewers of Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, for their helpful questions and comments.

References

  • Brennan G, Pettit P (2005) The feasibility issue. In: Jackson F, Smith M (eds) Oxford handbook to contemporary philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 258–297

    Google Scholar 

  • Carens JH (1981) Equality, moral incentives, and the market. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Ciepley D (2013) Beyond public and private: toward a political theory of the corporation. Am Polit Sci Rev 107(1):139–158

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen J (2001) Taking people as they are? Philos Public Aff 30(4):363–386

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen GA (2003) Facts and principles. Philos Public Aff 31(3):211–245

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham F (2005) Market economies and market societies. J Soc Philos 36(2):129–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Easterlin RA (1974) Does economic growth improve the human lot? Some empirical evidence. In: David PA, Reder MW (eds) Nations and households in economic growth: essays in honor of Moses Abramovitz. Academic, New York, pp 89–125

    Google Scholar 

  • Estlund D (2011) Human nature and the limits (if any) of political philosophy. Philos Public Aff 39(3):207–237

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Estlund D (2014) Utopophobia. Philos Public Aff 42(2):113–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Fischbacher U, Gächter S (2001) Are people conditionally cooperative? Evidence from a public goods experiment. Econ Lett 71(3):397–404

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldstein M (1995) The effect of marginal tax rates on taxable income. J Polit Econ 103:551–572

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank R, Gilovich T, Regan DT (1993) Does studying economics inhibit cooperation. J Econ Perspect 7(2):159–171

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geuss R (2008) Philosophy and real politics. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gheaus A (2013) The feasibility constraint on the concept of justice. Philos Q 63(252):445–464

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilabert P (2009) The feasibility of basic socioeconomic human rights: a conceptual exploration. Philos Q 59(237):659–681

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilabert P (2012) Comparative assessments of justice, political feasibility, and ideal theory. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 15(1):39–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilabert P, Lawford-Smith H (2012) Political feasibility. A conceptual exploration. Polit Stud 60(4):809–825

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herzog L (2012) Ideal and non-ideal theory and the problem of knowledge. J Appl Philos 29(4):271–288

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hungerford TL (2013) Corporate tax rates and economic growth since 1947. Economic Policy Institute Issue Brief #364, available at http://www.epi.org/publication/ib364-corporate-tax-rates-and-economic-growth/

  • Lawford-Smith H (2013a) Understanding political feasibility. J Polit Philos 21(3):243–259

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawford-Smith H (2013b) The feasibility of collectives’ actions. Australas J Philos 90(3):453–467

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liberman V, Samuels SM, Ross L (2004) The name of the game: predictive power of reputations versus situational labels in determining prisoner’s dilemma game moves. Personal Soc Psychol Bull 30(9):1175–1185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller D (1999) Principles of social justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy LB (2003) Moral demands in nonideal theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy LB, Nagel T (2002) The myth of ownership: taxes and justice. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pink D (2009) Drive: the surprising truth about what motivates us. Penguin, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi K (1944) The great transformation. Beacon, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Räikkä J (1998) The feasibility condition in political theory. J Polit Philos 6(1):27–40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1982) Social unity and primary goods. In: Sen A, Williams B (eds) Utilitarianism and beyond. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 159–185

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ricardo D (1821) On the principles of political economy and taxation. John Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Roemer J (2012) Ideology, social ethos, and the financial crisis. J Ethics 16:273–303

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau JJ (1997) [1762] Second discourse. In The discourses and other early political writings. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Sen A (2008) What do we want from a theory of justice? J Philos 103:215–238

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slemrod J, Bakija J (2000) Taxing ourselves, 2nd edn. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor C (1985) Self-interpreting animals. In: Philosophy and the Human Sciences. Philosophical Papers II. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 45–76

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Valentini L (2012) Ideal vs. nonideal theory: a conceptual map. Philos Compass 7(9):654–664

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Someren Greve R (2014) ‘Ought’, ‘can’, and fairness. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 7(4):433–451

    Google Scholar 

  • Verhaege P (2014) What about me? The struggle for identity in a market-based society. Scribe Publications, London

    Google Scholar 

  • von Hayek FA (1945) The use of knowledge in society. Am Econ Rev 35:519–530

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiens D (2012) Prescribing institutions without ideal theory. J Polit Philos 20(1):45–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiens D (2013) Demands of justice, feasible alternatives, and the need for causal analysis. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 16(2):325–338

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiens D (2014) Going evaluative’ to save justice from feasibility—a pyrrhic victory. Philos Q 64(255):301–307

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lisa Herzog.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Herzog, L. Distributive Justice, Feasibility Gridlocks, and the Harmfulness of Economic Ideology. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 18, 957–969 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-015-9565-9

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-015-9565-9

Keywords

Navigation