1 Arguments from Presentness

Traditionally, the idea that realism about the passage of time is supported by our experience is taken as obvious and seldom articulated in detail (cf. Craig, 2000; Smith, 1988). More recently, philosophers have started to spell out more carefully various “arguments from experience” that are used in the philosophy of time (Benovsky, 2015). Roughly, the literature presents two of such arguments in favour of the passage of time, although they are rarely distinguished (an exception is Frischhut, 2015 and partially Skow, 2015). The first family infers the reality of the passage of time from a dynamic element in our experience. This view is discussed in Baron et at. (2015), and criticised by Paul (2010), Dainton (2011), Hoerl (2014), Prosser (2016), Frischhut (2017), Deng (2019), Miller (2019). The second family, which is of interest here, infers the passage of time from the sense of presentness in our experience.Footnote 1 Various “arguments from presentness”, which are the focus of this article, are discussed and criticized in Perry (2001), Balashov (2005, 2015), Skow (2011, 2015), Parsons (2015), and endorsed by Baron (2017).

An argument from presentness has the following structure. One takes as premise a claim p on the phenomenology of our experience of presentness, and then concludes on the ground that the best explanation for that phenomenological datum requires a realist take on the idea of a present moment that there is an objective present. Arguments from presentness have thus the form of schema SP below.

SP

(I) p

(II)The best explanation for the fact that p requires that there is an objective present

(REALISMP)There is an objective present

In the literature there are at least two families of arguments from presentness, depending on what kind of claim p is taken as premise (I). If one focuses on what we call perceptual presentness, the focus is on the object of experience and the phenomenological datum is that we are aware of what we perceive as happening in the present. If one focuses on what we call locational presentness, the focus is on the subject of experience. The datum is that we are aware of ourselves as having present experiences. In both families of argument, the idea behind premise (II) is that the present moment is somehow ‘privileged’, it has, in a sense to be specified, ‘special’ experiential status when it is compared to past and future moments, and in order to account for this experiential difference, we need to endorse realism with respect to an objective present.Footnote 2 The claim is thus that a metaphysical thesis is explanatorily crucial to account for an experiential truth.

Although there are various ways to understand REALISMp, both with respect to the ontological background (roughly, whether other times besides the objective present exist), and the details of the metaphysics (roughly, whether the objective present is thus in virtue of instantiating a genuine monadic property of presentness, or for some other reason), our considerations apply regardless of the details. However, for ease of exposition, we will assume an eternalist ontology and talk in terms of a property of objective presentness being temporarily and successively instantiated by times, along the lines of the Moving Spotlight Theory.Footnote 3 We postpone to the last section of the paper how to extend our considerations also to other forms of REALISMp; in particular presentism and the growing block theory.

In the next two sections, we will spell out the two families of arguments from presentness. Both the datum p, and the sense in which REALISMP(“realism” for short henceforth) can be used to provide an explanation of p differ depending on whether the focus is on perceptual or locational presentness. We will see that the most plausible accounts of the phenomenology of presentness do not support the idea that realism is explanatory crucial, and hence cannot be used in abductive arguments of the form SP. In so doing, we will cast some doubts upon the idea that there is a phenomenology of presentness over and above those phenomenological ingredients of our experiences that anyone is prone to admit regardless of their own stance toward presentness; that is, perceptual experiences such as those as of change and movement, and non-perceptual “internal” ones such as emotions and moods. If so, both conceptions of presentness tend to collapse in a form of experiential eliminativism, as we will call it. The last section (Sect. 4) will broaden the discussion of the arguments of presentness in relation to the other realist views on time: presentism and the growing block theory.

2 Perceptual Presentness

The first approach to presentness we consider, perceptual presentness, is object-oriented rather than subject oriented. According to it, our experience of the present is an awareness that what we experience is present, rather than an awareness that we are presently experiencing something. In general, if (and insofar as) an experience is of an object, then what it is like to have that experience is determined by how that object is presented to us. The idea behind perceptual presentness is that there is something in the way objects of perception are presented to us that makes it the case that we experience them as present. That something, the phenomenological element that is responsible for our awareness that what we perceive is present, is perceptual presentness.Footnote 4

As the name suggests, the phenomenological element in question is supposed to be part of perceptual phenomenology, rather than other kinds of experiential states. Intuitively, the present momentFootnote 5 is the one we perceive, we neither remember nor anticipate it. The content of a memory — for example, our journey to Engadina last year — is presented to us as belonging to the past. We are not in Engadina now, we were in Engadina then. And analogous remarks hold for anticipation. Still other experiential states like imagination and emotions do not necessarily present their objects in the present moment: we can imagine a spider to be here now, but I can imagine a spider in the past or the future, or without a particular temporal location. We can be angry because someone is lying to us now, but we can also be angry at someone for having been untruthful to us.

This view of presentness can be used to argue that it is a phenomenological datum that we perceive things as present, and that datum can enter an abductive argument for objective presentness, as in the following exemplification of SP.

SP-1

(I) We perceive things as present

(II)The best explanation for the fact that we perceive things as present requires that there is an objective present

(REALISMP)There is an objective present

Before looking at how SP-1 can be understood, we briefly introduce and set apart the projection interpretation of perceptual presentness.Footnote 6 According to this view, presentness is not a property of the world that it is presented to us in perception, it is rather a sensation that we project onto the world that we perceive. If premise (I’) is read along those lines, any connection between the properties of what we perceive and our experience of presentness is lost, and with it the plausibility of premise (II’). The projection interpretation is thus not one that we will consider here. In order for argument SP-1 to take off, we need to understand our experience of presentness either in representationalist terms or in direct realist terms.Footnote 7 With this in mind, we can now move to the main interpretations of perceptual presentness — the content view and the mode view.

2.1 The Content View of Perceptual Presentness

According to the content view, being present is a property that is presented to us in the contents of our perceptions; as such, we become aware of it in the same way in which we become aware of redness and sphericity by looking at an apple.Footnote 8

If we read premise (I’) along those lines, argument SP-1 has prima facie plausibility. If we perceive presentness in the same way that we perceive colors and shapes, then there must be some objective property that the objects of perception possess and to which our perceptual organs are sensitive. However, the content approach is currently widely discarded on the grounds, roughly, of two kinds of arguments: the causal inertia arguments and the contrastability arguments. The analysis of perceptual contents by Braddon-Mitchell (2013) and the detection arguments by Prosser (2016) are examples of the first kind. It is generally accepted that a condition for a perceptual content to be veridical is that certain causal connections of the right sort must be in place, and they must at least in part involve the object the perception is about.Footnote 9 However, if presentness was a property of things or events around us, it would be causally inert. Think of any cluster of causally efficacious properties, nothing changes in the history of their effects if we add presentness to the cluster (but for their temporal location relative to us). Given that causally inert properties cannot be perceived, we cannot perceive presentness.Footnote 10 This criticism of the content approach to perceptual presentness can be used against the premise (I’) of SP-1.

The second kind of arguments are based on the idea of contrastability. The idea is that in order for a property to be perceived, it must be contrastable; that is, in order for us to be presented with an entity as possessing that property, there must be other perceptual experiences that differ from it in that respect.Footnote 11 For example, circularity is a property whose perceptual experience can be contrasted. In the content of our perceptual experience, we deal with things that are circular, and others that are not circular; and we can contrast perceptual experience of the first kind and of the second kind, and find them different with respect to shape. However, so the argument goes, everything in our perception is presented as present, and nothing is presented as non-present. Thus, it cannot be the case that being-present is a contrastable property. It would be necessary that some things are presented (in perception) as present while others are presented (in perception) as non-present for presentness to be contrastable.Footnote 12 Given that contrastability is necessary for being a content property, presentness cannot be a property that is presented to us in the content of a perception. And if being a content property is the only way for a property to be perceived, then presentness is not perceivable after all. When we talk and think in terms that entail or suggest that we perceive present things, we are somehow mischaracterizing our experience.Footnote 13

The argument from contrastability may be challenged in a “Husserlian” fashion by denying that everything in perception is experienced as present. According to what we call the theory of intervallic content, perception makes us aware of a succession of moments.Footnote 14 A supporter of intervallic contents may further suppose that only one of these moments is presented as present. A position of this kind is supported by, among the others, Jan Almäng (2014), who claims that presentness is contrastable because perceptual contents present pastness and futurity along with it. We grant that the view vindicates the idea that presentness can be contrasted phenomenally. However, it does not help us to reinforce arguments such as SP-1. The contrast is between the ways different parts of the content are presented to us in perception, rather than in what properties are presented to us. Therefore, as Almäng also seems to acknowledge, an objective present is neither necessary nor sufficient for the contrast.Footnote 15 Moreover, as we will argue more extensively in Sect. 2.3, a position of this kind still suffers from the problem of causal inertia of the present. Even if there is a contrast between what is perceived as present and what is perceived as just past (or in the very near future), an objective present could not be responsible for such a contrast.

Another way to challenge the argument from contrastability is to appeal to the difference between memory and perception and construe it as a phenomenal difference. Our perceptual experience of the mountains of Engadina, for instance, presents the landscape in a different, let us say ‘more vivid’ way, than our memory of the same mountains. Unfortunately this suggestion does not help the realist about the objective present. Even if we admit a salient phenomenal difference between our perceived contents and our remembered contents, it is still the case that that premise (II’) of the argument is false. As Frischhut (2015) convincingly argues, this difference is better explained by the fact that perception and memory are two different faculties. And it seems that this alleged vividness is just the observation that the same content, the mountain, feels different when presented to the two faculties. This opens up the suggestion that this phenomenological ingredient of “vividness” (or, “presentness”) is much more an element of the faculty—or mode—rather than of the content. The “vividness” account ultimately collapses in a form of mode view we are about to analyse in the following section.

2.2 The Mode View of Perceptual Presentness

According to the mode view (Almäng, 2012; Kriegel, 2015; Recanati, 2007), presenting things as present is a feature that certain mental states have in virtue of being perceptual states (as opposed to other kinds of mental states), rather than in virtue of what they present to us. Again, we can use memory for contrast: there is a sense in which our perception of Engadina and our memory of Engadina present us with the same thing, a beautiful landscape. However, perception presents-as-present Engadina, memory presents-as-past Engadina. Thus, two modes of presentation (of Engadina) are involved here, one specific to perception (the one oriented towards the present), and one specific to memory (the one oriented towards the past).

The mode view can be articulated in various ways, depending on what we take a mode of presentation to be. The driving idea is that contents are associated with what the mental state is about, while modes are associated with how the subject relates to the content, and this last piece of information in the case of perception comes with an awareness of being related with present things. Consider again our previous example. Our sight of Engadina and our memory of Engadina have the same content, since they are about the same beautiful landscape. But my visual experience relates to that content in a different way than my memory does. Vision puts, as it were, the content in the present, memory puts it in the past.

Recanati (2007: 141) articulates the idea by introducing two contents, one temporally neutral (the explicit content), which can be shared by various modes (for instance, memory and perception), and another one tensed (the complete content), which is mode-specific. In the case of memory, the complete content is past-tense. In the case of perception, it is present-tense and leads to experiencing a sense of presentness. According to Almäng (2012: 436–437), both the explicit content and the complete content are present-tensed. However, the evaluation of the explicit content changes depending on the mode. When we remember, the evaluation requires that we consider a time in the past (roughly as if we were treating the content like an utterance in the historical present). When we perceive, the evaluation requires taking into account the present time, which leads to experiencing a sense of presentness.

As Kriegel (2015), who defends it, convincingly argues, the mode view cannot be used to motivate arguments such as SP-1. In any of its articulations, the core thesis is that we are aware of presentness as the mode of presentation of the content specific to perception. It is thus sufficient that a perception is somehow triggered in a subject in order for them to perceive an object as located in the present. In other words, according to the mode view, it is the fact that we perceive something, rather than remember or imagine it, that matters for having an awareness of it as present. What we perceive, and thus whether what we perceive is objectively present, is irrelevant to account for such an awareness. Hence, if the mode view is correct, (II’) is false and we do not need to posit any objective presentness to explain the perceptual phenomenology of presentness.Footnote 16

2.3 Whither Perceptual Presentness?

So far we have argued that any reading of premise (I’) of the argument SP-1 debunks premise (II’). We tried several notions of perceptual presentness, but none of them helps making the argument convincing. In this section we want to push the point a bit further and show that there is no perceptual presentness at all. This is to say, there is no genuine sense of presentness in perception over and above the phenomenology of experiencing features such as shape, colour, and movement.

Let us begin by noticing that the idea of perceptual presentness naturally leads to a sort of “Euthyphro style” dilemma: do we perceive an object because it is located in the present (as the realist usually has it), or do we locate an object in the present because we perceive it (as the antirealist usually has it)?

If the latter direction of explanation is correct, as our discussion so far suggests, the denial of any genuine phenomenology of presentness is just one step ahead. Indeed, if we experience an object as present because we perceive it, rather than vice versa, it is natural to think that being presented in perception is a way of being experienced as present. More precisely, it is the way that is specific to perception (as we will see in the next sections, there are plausibly also non-perceptual ways of being experienced as present). In other words, if the reason for which we postulate a genuine phenomenology of presentness in perception is to explain our awareness of the temporal location of the object of our perception, then it is a poor reason. The mere fact that we are aware of it as an object of perception — rather than memory or imagination — is sufficient to explain why we judge it to be located in the present. Taking this stance seriously amounts to maintaining that we do not perceive objects as located in the present, we simply perceive them. We call this position experiential eliminativism about presentness (eliminativism, for short).

To elaborate on our point, let us go back to the issue of intervallic contents. The leading question of the debate is whether the content of perceptual experience is temporally extended or (virtually) instantaneous. Indeed, starting from fairly uncontroversial phenomenological facts, namely that we have a genuine perceptual phenomenology of temporally extended events, like motion, change and rest, many philosophers (Soteriou, 2013; Almäng, 2014; Sattig, 2019; Power 2012) argue that perception presents us durations, rather than “snapshots” of the world as it is at an instant. An evaluation of the various positions of the debate is clearly beyond the scope of this paper. Luckily for us, both the tenet that perception’s content are temporally extended and its negation are in tension with the idea that there is a genuine perceptual phenomenology of presentness, and thus eliminativism is the more natural option no matter what.

Let’s assume contents are intervallic, and that motions are presented to us in perception. For instance the motion of a rolling ball down a slope from location l1 to l3, during the temporal interval t1 to t3. If we assume that perceptual presentness is genuine, the whole interval is perceptually presented as located in the present. As Benovsky (2012) notices, according to this view, there is a mismatch between the present temporal location attributed by perception to the rolling ball, which spans over an interval, and the real instantaneous present (if any). But then, what is responsible for the “extra” presentness that we experience, the one involving moments outside the objective present? Assuming that the objective present is responsible for the experience of the objective present as present, it must be “the mind”, in some sense, that bestows such extra presentness on the past (and perhaps future) bits of the perceived event.

This hypothesis runs into the very same problems that we have seen while discussing the attempts to defend arguments of the form SP-1, since it requires a non-causally-inert present, and, crucially, insofar as it requires a projectionist interpretation of the “extra” presentness it cannot be used in an argument from experience. However, one may insist that this “amodal” interpretation of the intervallic content, in which the whole interval is presented as present, is not the only one. In literature we find what we may call inflationist versions of the theory of intervallic content, according to which perception comes with a genuine sense of presentness, along with a sense of (very recent) pastness, and possibly a sense of (very near) futurity. According to the inflationist, when we see the whole motion of the ball, we see certain parts of its movement as occurring in the present, certain others as occurring in the past, (and possibly others as occurring in the future). We have discussed such positions while arguing against the attempts to resist the augment for contrastivity (2.i).Footnote 17

Now, in order for inflationism to be an alternative to eliminativism, it has to be committed to the thesis that we are aware of a difference in the way past (and future) parts of the perceived interval on the one side, and present parts are perceptually presented to us. Typically, the difference is captured in terms of tense. While the eliminativist that endorses intervallic content characterises the content as tenseless, something along the lines of [A before B], the inflationist must characterize it as tensed content, something along the line of [A is past and B is present] (see Connor & Smith, 2019). The information encoded in inflationist contents is richer because they inform us not only about the temporal order in the succession A-B, but also about the temporal location of the experience of the succession A-B; it tells us that it is roughly simultaneous with B.Thus, this theory predicts that information about the subject’s temporal location is manifest in perceptual experience. In other words, inflationism is committed to the claim that the experience itself enters the content.

But that perceptual content is in this respect reflexive, that is, it contains its own perception as part, seems wrong to many people (e.g. Falk, 2003: 221, Balashov, 2005, Callender, 2017: 188–189), and it is explicitly denied by philosophers believing in the temporal transparency of experience, namely the idea that no temporal property of the perceptual experience itself is manifest in introspection (Connor & Smith, 2019; Hoerl, 2018; Soteriou, 2013). Transparency in the case of temporal (perceptual) presentness is particularly convincing, since unlike the case of perception of spatial locations, there does not seem to be phenomenal distinguishability between the temporal location of the perceiver and the object of perception. At any rate, it is doubtful that inflationism fares better than eliminativism on the ground that it explains our awareness of the temporal location of our object of perception, or our judgments that they occur in the present.

Finally, if perceptual contents are not intervallic, but (virtually) instantaneous, eliminativism seems to be the best option still. The rejection of genuine perceptual presentness is particularly in line with the rejection of intervallic contents, that is, the thesis that perceptual contents are (virtually) instantaneous and we always perceive only one moment and never a succession of moments. If in perception we are presented with only one moment as present, it is unclear why we should think of that moment as phenomenally privileged. If it is privileged in some sense, it is not in virtue of some properties that it displays, but rather it is so in virtue of being perceived, as opposed to remembered or anticipated. If so, it is unclear why we should think of perception as delivering any sense of presentness: to be privileged in the sense required by perceptual presentness is to be the only moment singled out in perception.Footnote 18

3 Locational Presentness

Perceptual presentness leaves out cases in which we are aware of the present even if we are not perceiving anything as present. Think of lying in a sensory deprivation chamber. At a certain point you have a random thought. It seems plausible to maintain that this mere fact makes you aware that your thought occurs in the present. More generally, we seem to be aware of our temporal location as present, simply by having an experience (not necessarily a perceptual experience) and regardless of what the experience presents to us (if anything), or “where in time” it is presented to us. Given the sensitivity of this kind of presentness to the temporal location of the experience, we call it locational presentness. We notice here that there is a potential ambiguity in the terminology. One may understand “locational presentness” as expressing an aspect of our inner phenomenology that characterises experiences as occurring in the present, as opposed to the past and the future; or it can be understood as expressing the awareness of its occurring simpliciter. We begin with understanding the expression in the first sense, and then move to the second interpretation in Sect. 3.1 and 3.2.

A realist can exploit at their advantage locational presentness in an argument such as SP-2 below.

SP-2

(I’’)We are aware of our own experiences as present

(II’’)The best explanation for the fact that we are aware of our own experiences as present requires that there is an objective present

(REALISMP)There is an objective present

The rationale behind SP-2 can be reconstructed in two steps. Firstly, we are aware of our own experiences as present; experiences that occurred in the past/will occur in the future do not carry the same awareness status (premise I”). Secondly, only if we assume that there is an objective present, we can explain why past, present and future experiences do not have the same awareness status. By doing so, one accounts for the fact that past and future experiences do not exhibit presentness. In contrast, an antirealist lacks the resources to account for this disparity, since apart from the difference in content, according to them, present experiences should not differ in awareness status from past and future ones. Therefore, the best explanation for experiencing the present is the realist one.

Upon closer scrutiny however, this line of reasoning cannot succeed to establish the truth of realism. Let us ask how exactly an objective present would “break the parity” between present experiences and non-present experiences. A natural answer is that objective presentness somehow makes present experiences phenomenally different from past and future ones (Skow, 2015: 205). If so, premise (I’’) has to be read as saying that we are aware of a phenomenological element, a “woosh” (Falk, 2003) that characterises the present experiences to the exclusion of past and future ones.

Now, spelling out what this phenomenological element amounts to is difficult. One suggestion is to adopt Almäng (2012)’s inflationist proposal that we saw in Sect. 2.ii and 2.iii, and characterise locational presentness in terms of a reflexive element in the content — i.e., an element that involves an awareness of the experience itself (cf. Peacocke, 1999: 280). Even if we ignore the fact that (as pointed out above already) many find it phenomenologically dubious that there is a reflexive element in our experience of the present (cf. Falk, 2003, Perry, 2013, Callender, 2017: Chap 9, Connor & Smith, 2019: 822–5), this attempt would be vain, because there is a general problem with interpreting premise (I”) in terms of a phenomenal element that is characteristic of locational presentness. Suppose that the moment in which you read this line of The Ways of Presentness you feel pleasure. Does your pleasant experience exhibit locational presentness, while your experience of boredom, which occurred twenty minutes ago, before you began reading this paper, does not? You (as anybody else) do not seem to be in a position to answer this question, since at the moment you were reading that line, you had no access to experiences occurring at different times, such as the ones you had twenty minutes before or the one that you are having now while reading this other line; so you cannot be aware of the difference.Footnote 19 But as long as locational presentness is a property that characterises the phenomenology of present experiences as opposed to non-present ones (as in the first interpretation of the expression), locational presentness requires awareness of a difference in phenomenology between present and past (and future) experiences. Therefore, we cannot read premise (I’’) in terms of an alleged characteristic phenomenology of present experiences.

Note that, also in this case, an eliminativist interpretation of presentness seems to suggest itself. If a contrast case between experiences exhibiting locational presentness and experiences which do not exhibit it is necessary for having phenomenology of presentness in the first place, but we cannot experience such a contrast, then there is no such a phenomenal ingredient in our experience. The fact that we are aware that the experience that we are having now (as opposed to the ones that we had and the ones that we will have) are present is not due to some phenomenal aspect of our experience.

3.1 Absolute and Relativised Experiential Availability

The realist might interpret premise (I”) in line with the second reading of locational presentness, as awareness of the occurrence of the experience. She can thus run the argument accepting eliminativism and therefore without assuming that present experiences are phenomenally special. Indeed, we have just pointed out that an important difference between present and past/future experience is that I only have access to experiences located in the present moment and not to past or future ones. Only present experiences are available to me in some absolute, non-time relative sense. How this suggestion can be put to work in an argument like SP-2 can be understood by looking at two classical papers by Prior (1957) and Hestevold (1990).

Hestevold considers the case of a patient of the dentist who feels pain now, and who also felt pain two years ago in similar circumstances. If there is no objective present, both pains exist, and are felt tenselessly by the same subject. However, only the current pain matters for the present behavior of the patient, which is why he asks the dentist for more anesthetic. Hestevold’s point is that the best explanation for this difference is that only the present pain is experienced, past (and future) pains are simply non-experienced pains. And the best explanation for this phenomenal difference is that only the present pains (as opposed to past and future pains) exist, and their occuring at the objective present is therefore necessary for their being available to me.

Analogously, Prior complains that if there is no objective present, we cannot make sense of the feeling of relief that we typically have when the pain is over after a dental surgery. If the event of the surgery and its accompanying pain exist tenselessly, then what brings into existence the relief? Without an objective present that “moves along” and delivers the unpleasant experience to ‘metaphysical oblivion’, the existence of a state of relief would be utterly unexplained. The experiences that have locational presentness have changed from encompassing my pain to encompassing my lack of pain, and this change brings about my state of relief.Footnote 20

However, the antirealist has a rejoinder (cf. Prosser, 2016; Skow, 2015). The property of being available (for a certain subject) is not different from any other property in the metaphysical framework of antirealism. Persisting entities such as ourselves possess properties only relative to a time. Therefore, attributions of possession of the property of being available must be evaluated with respect to a time (whether an instant or a period): the time of occurrence of the experience to which we are attributing availability. In this framework, we can explain the difference in availability between this experience, that we happen to have now, and the experiences we had before it without appealing to an objective present.

According to the antirealist, at any time t we have access only to experiences occurring at t. It is true that other experiences exist at tn…tm, but only those occurring at t are accessible for me with respect to t (Mellor, 1998; Skow, 2011). And this limitation in accessibility is all that it takes to explain my timely behaviour. The success conditions for my behaviour to be timely are just that it occurs at the time t when it is needed, and the conditions for my motivation to act at t, rather than at previous or future times, is that only at t I have access to the experience that occur at t, and not to those that happen at past and future times. Thus the complaints by Hestevold seem easily met: when I am with the doctor in 2020 only the 2020 pain is accessible to me. In the same way, the sense of relief which Prior refers to can be motivated without appealing to objective presentness, since relief occurs at a time (at 13.35, say) that is posterior to—hence unavailable at—the time at which the dental operation happens (between 12:30 and 13:30, say). The important lesson to learn from these considerations is that while the realist endorses a notion of absolute experiential availability, the antirealist conceives of locational presentness as irreducibly relativised to times, that is, as relativised experiential availability. But explanatorily there does not seem to be any substantive difference between the two notions, given the respective assumptions on what kind of questions we should ask to account for a timely behaviour. For the realist is: what should one do simpliciter? For the anti-realist: what should one do relative to a time t? In the last section, we discuss this apparent stalemate and the options for the anti-realist to come out of the impasse.

3.2 The Antirealist Take on Absolute Experiential Availability

The dialectic between the realist and the antirealist at this point seems to have come to a dead end. Although some antirealists complain that the notion of absolute experiential availability is unintelligible (Callender, 2008, 2017: Chap. 5) or not explanatory important (Prosser, 2016: 56–57), the overall impression is that both realist’s absolute experiential availability and the antirealist’s relativised experiential availability seem effective at explaining why we do not have access to our past or future experiences (see end of last section). The deadend is not a complete stalemate though. The abductive argument SP-2 cannot take off unless one adds the further premise that only the experiences that occur at all are those at the present moment. But this is not something that our experience informs us about: there is no way to know whether this experience I am currently having is the only one in reality or whether other experiences of mine occur at other times.Footnote 21 The only way in which I may come to know it is by coming to believe a (true) metaphysical theory that binds the occurrence of experiences to the occurrence of the objective present moment. In other words, in order to launch the argument from locational presentness for realism, one has to assume realism, while in order to debunk arguments of the form SP-2, one just needs to allow for the possibility of antirealism.

In the literature we find attempts to introduce a version of absolute experiential availability that is compatible with antirealism (Balashov, 2005, 2015, Skow, 2011, 2015: 216–221, Parsons, 2015). An antirealist may agree that there is a sense in which certain experiences are the only ones available simpliciter (i.e. in a non-time-relative manner) to a subject s, and at the same time she may maintain that other experiences of s exist tenselessly at other times. The “trick” is to appeal to those theories of persistence according to which objects have temporal parts or stages (see Sider, 2011; Hawley, 2020; Parsons, 2000), and apply them to the subject s. The idea is that a subject-stage of s is presented with certain experiences simpliciter. The price to pay for this is that the notion of identity through time must be loosened à la Parfit, given that the stage of me that exist at 09:00 and to which the experience of enjoying the breakfast is available simpliciter is not numerically the same than the stage of me that exist at 13:00 and to which the experience of enjoying the lunch is available simpliciter. But this is a price one may be willing to pay.Footnote 22

A problem with this proposal, as we see it, is that it seems to implicitly rely on the very notion of relativised availability that it is supposed to explain away. The temporal location of the subject to which experiences are available simpliciter—that is, the temporal stage of s—is just a fraction of the span of existence of the subject s in question. Thus, with respect to s, the attribution of availability (and thereby of locational presentness) is relativized to a specific moment of her life.Footnote 23

More importantly for our purposes, the attempt to resort to a non-relativised notion of experiential availability that does not collapse into the realist notion of absolute experiential availability seems to be motivated by a mixture of two assumptions, a correct one and an incorrect one. The correct assumption is that there is no reflexive character that is revealed in introspection when we consider our presently occurring perceptual experiences. The wrong assumption is that locational presentness has a distinctive phenomenological character nonetheless. In order to make sense of this distinctive ingredient in a way that does not bring in reflexive elements, the antirealist may resort to a non-relativised notion of experiential availability, and adjust their theory of personal persistence accordingly. But it is not clear that there is a phenomenological aspect to be accounted for; after all, the idea that the experiences that we are presently having (as opposed to the past and future ones) are privileged because they are the only ones that occur is compatible with eliminativism — as already pointed out. Indeed, the antirealist endorsers of non-relativised experiential availability fails to recognise that as soon as the argument from presentness is understood along the lines of experiential availability, an important switch in the dialectic occurs. Experiential availability has been introduced by the realist to give an impersonal reading to the argument from presentness. What matters for the argument framed in this way is merely whether a subject has a certain experience or not, rather than what it is like to have such an experience. And this aspect of our experience (viz., the mere fact of having them) can be accounted for with no reference to any genuine phenomenology of presentness.

4 Mainstream Realist Options and the Arguments from Presentness

A final point, before wrapping up. As stated at the beginning, we have so far worked on the assumption that the background metaphysics is that of the moving spotlight view, that is an eternalist ontology together with a form of tense realism. We now consider other forms of realism with respect to presentness, and argue that the reasons we have marshalled against the arguments from presentness in the case of the moving spotlight apply mutatis mutandis to the other cases too. More precisely, we will ask whether either the content view, or the locational presentness view can be exploited by non-eternalist forms of tense realism, since the mode view, which assumes presentness to be ultimately an experiential property with no role played by how the world is, cannot favour any form of realism.

The first alternative we consider is Presentism, according to which there is an equivalence (at least at the extensional level) between what exists and what occurs at the present moment.Footnote 24 It seems obvious that this equivalence does not change the status of the arguments from perceptual presentness. Either the only existing entities also possess an objective property of presentness, and then our reasonings apply as before, or there is no such objective presentness property, and thus the position does not support the premise (II’) in SP-1. What about locational presentness? Within a presentist background, we do not need to characterize locational presentness in terms of an objective notion of presentness (which identifies the moment at which our experience is located), but we can think of it in terms of the experience occurring simpliciter, in some absolute sense.Footnote 25 In the previous section, we have indeed characterized the experience of locational presence in these terms. But as there are no good reasons to conclude from an experience so-characterised there is an objective present time, there equally are no good reasons to conclude that there exists a unique present time. Remember that the crucial part of our argument against SP-2 is based on the idea of (metaphysical) accessibility to times other than the one at which we are located. We argue that we have no access to past and future times while granting to our opponent their existence. But if this assumption is false and there are no other times beside the one at which we happen to be located, a fortiori we have no access to other times. In other words, if there is no experience outside the present time, subjects cannot have access to past or future experiences to feel the “woosh!” of the present.

The second alternative is the Growing Block view, according to which the “objective” present is (or at least is coextensive with) a topological property, that of being at the edge of an ever-growing reality. In this scenario, there are past entities, but there are not future ones. Present entities are the last that have come into existence. With respect to the arguments based on perceptual presentness, this view as well does not bring anything new into the picture. Either there is no property of objective presentness (since it is reduced to the topological property just mentioned) and thus no such property can be part of our perceptual contents; or, if there is, the arguments against entering the perceptual content are untouched by the change in ontology. The case of locational presentness is only superficially more complex. To debunk the arguments from locational presentness, we need to look at B-theoretic eternalism if we consider times in the past, and notice that we have the same form of lack of access to past experiences; we need to look at presentism if we consider future times, and notice that we do not have access to future experiences, because they do not exist.

5 Conclusions

The current debate on whether experience favors a realist stance towards the present shows there is no univocal way in which the notion of presentness is understood. As a consequence, the various arguments from presentness that aim to establish the truth of realism have to be evaluated by taking into account all the different shades that the notion of presentness may take. However, as soon as they are distinguished and carefully articulated, the force of the argument plummets. This upshot may be due to the fact that any putative phenomenology of presentness can be captured by the phenomenology of our (perceptual or non perceptual) experiences with no reference to presentness, as for the thesis that we called elimininativism about presentness.Footnote 26