Skip to main content
Log in

Language from the Ground Up: A Study of Homesign Communication

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Philosophers are often beholden to a picture of language as a largely static, well-defined structure which is handed over from generation to generation by an arduous process of learning: language, on this view, is something that we are given, and that we can make use of, but which we play no significant role in creating ourselves. This picture is often maintained in conjunction with the idea that several distinctively human cognitive capacities could only develop via the language acquisition process, as thus understood. This paper argues that the phenomenon of homesign, i.e., spontaneous gesture systems devised by deaf children for the purpose of communicating with their non-signing peers, can shed valuable empirical light on these convictions. Contrary to grounding assumptions of Wittgensteinian, Gricean, and Peircean approaches to language, homesign shows how core properties of language—including semantic properties—can be built from the ground up in idiosyncratic ways to serve the communicative needs of individuals.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. James (1892) revisits the question, adding further testimony in support of the conclusion.

  2. See Burge (2010), Part II, for extensive documentation—and rebuttal—of the philosophical idea that even so fundamental a capacity as perception might depend on acquired language.

  3. If this seems surprising, we should bear in mind that it was not until the publication of Stokoe (1960) that even ASL and similar conventionalized sign systems would come to be recognized as full-blown natural languages. See Goldin-Meadow and Brentari (2015) for an account of this development. For accounts of the cultural history of the deaf communities, up to and including the recognition of sign as language, see Sacks (1989) and Ree (1999).

  4. See Goldin-Meadow (2003).

  5. Goldin-Meadow (2003: 111–112).

  6. Goldin-Meadow (1982, 2002) and Hunsicker and Goldin-Meadow (2013).

  7. See Bar-On (2013a, b) for a recent development of such a notion of expressive communication.

  8. Thus, it should come as no surprise that one persistent source of interest in homesign concerns its status as evidence for innate grammatical abilities (see, e.g., Chomsky 1988: 39; Jackendoff 1995: 129–130). After all, these children have never been functionally exposed to any language, so it would seem that whatever grammatical abilities they evince must be innate. This conclusion is controversial, however: for useful contrasting perspectives, see Botha (2007), Tomasello (2008) and Amstrong and Wilcox (2011). Goldin-Meadow (2003: ch. 18) sensibly takes a more cautious approach to the question, substituting a notion of innateness in terms of genetic transmission for one of innateness in terms of developmental resilience: resilient properties of language are simply those that manifest under adverse and favorable developmental conditions alike. Thus, rudimentary grammatical abilities are certainly innate, but not necessarily in any way that would satisfy more expansive genetic accounts of language, such as one might associate with Chomsky (1986) or Pinker (1994).

  9. Wittgenstein (1953).

  10. See Kripke (1982) and McDowell (1984) for further variations on the theme. We might also note that while this line of reasoning clearly draws inspiration from what is often referred to as Wittgenstein’s private language argument, most subsequent developments of the theme are not directed against private languages per se (a language which only the speaker could understand), but rather against what is sometimes termed a “solitary language,” i.e., a language which only one person ever spoke in fact. (On this, see, e.g., Goldfarb 1985: 480). Homesign would clearly not constitute a private language, but it might well constitute a solitary language.

  11. Grice (1967, 1969, 1975).

  12. Sperber and Wilson (1986) and Carston (2002). I should add that what I am reconstructing here is a possible appropriation of Relevance Theory to the problem at hand. I am not supposing that prominent Relevance Theorists would necessarily approve of the appropriation, or, for that matter, be inclined to resist a semantic account of homesign.

  13. See also Carston (2002: 46–47).

  14. Even so, it is not a trivial matter how homesigners can come to be in the cognitive position to form the appropriately reflexive communicative intentions underlying speaker meaning in the first place. I will return to this issue in my final section.

  15. E.g., Schiffer (1972), Lewis (1975) and Burge (1975).

  16. For details, see Carrigan and Coppola (2012).

  17. Though see Carrigan and Coppola (2012) for an account of the limitations on this process.

  18. For overviews of this development, see Senghas (1995), Kegl et al. (1999), Morford and Kegl (2000) and Brentari and Coppola (2012). Although the ISN may be unique in how rapidly it emerged, it is not alone among spontaneously developed sign languages: a recently discovered case is the Al-Sayyid Bedouin Sign Language in Israel’s Negev Desert (see, e.g., Sandler et al. 2005; Senghas 2005, Fox 2007). Indeed, it is overwhelmingly likely that these processes will be set in motion whenever deaf people are allowed to congregate on their own terms for an appreciable amount of time.

  19. I here draw on Tomaszewski (2006), a case study of an emerging peer-group pidgin among Polish homesigners. See also Emmorey (2002: 321–322) and Richie et al. (2014) for studies more specific to the Nicaraguan case.

  20. Note the “maybe”: see Davidson (1986) for a dissenting voice. I develop Davidson-inspired ideas about these and related issues in Begby (2013, 2014, 2016).

  21. The terminology is due to de Saussure (1916), but recognition of the phenomenon goes back at least to Plato’s Cratylus. Unfortunately, however, the literature tends to conflate the properties of arbitrariness and conventionality. For illustration, consider Lyons (1977: 100): “Saussure (1916) made what he called the ‘arbitrariness of the linguistic sign’ (that is to say, the conventionality of the relationship between form and meaning) one of the most basic principles of his whole theory.” But to treat the two notions as though they were identical is clearly mistaken; in fact they are not even co-extensional. Proof: from any arbitrary mapping of words to meanings (say, that of the English lexicon), we can generate another by random reassignment. If the first mapping was conventional, the second is clearly not. But it is no less arbitrary than the original mapping.

  22. See Ree (1999: ch. 13) for an account of these views and their historical background.

  23. Though I will not pursue the matter here, I wish to register that I have serious reservations about Bermudez’s reading of the empirical literature on homesign, specifically regarding the evidence for syntactic and morphological structure. The main thrust of Bermudez’s book, however, is that one class of crucially important and distinctively human cognitive abilities—metarepresentational abilities—could only develop through the acquisition of a conventional public language, and so must presumably remain unavailable to homesigners. On this specific point, I believe contrary evidence can be found, inter alia, in Butcher et al. (1991: 329).

  24. Crudely, they are not referential phenomena, in the sense that so captivates philosophical semanticists, but more like sentential operators (“yes,” “no,” “maybe”). Moreover, these may be among the relatively few conventionalized gestures that the children adopt from their social environment, and so fall outside the scope of the present argument.

  25. See Frishberg (1975).

  26. See, e.g., Tomasello (2008: 147).

  27. For an overview, see Dale and Crain-Thoreson (1993).

  28. See Petitto (1987).

  29. See Camp (2007: 156–157), for illuminating remarks on the informational richness of analog representation as contrasted with linguistic representation.

  30. Goldin-Meadow (2003: 87–89).

  31. See Tomasello (2008: 111–117).

  32. For studies of displaced reference in homesign, see Butcher et al. (1991) and Morford and Goldin-Meadow (1997).

  33. Goldin-Meadow (2003: 138).

  34. Goldin-Meadow (2003: 74).

  35. Another term is “interchangeability” (e.g., Hockett 1960). It is obviously tempting, though probably mistaken, to assume that bidirectionality and conventionality are simply two names for the same property. It is well known that comprehension and production are dissociable aspects of language, and many of us are quite capable of understanding utterances in languages that we do not speak. And so, we cannot rule out that homesign communication can at some point be described as conventional, even though it remains largely non-bidirectional.

  36. See, e.g., Clark and Wilkes-Gibbs (1986) and Schober and Clark (1989).

  37. See, for instance, the recent study by Carrigan and Coppola (2012), which also reveals startling limitations to caregivers’ comprehension of homesign gestures: ASL signers who have had no previous interactions with adult homesigning subjects are shown to have better comprehension of the subjects’ gestures than do the subjects’ own mothers.

  38. For a useful perspective, see Richie et al. (2014).

  39. Though see Morgan and Kegl (2006), Pyers and Senghas (2009) and Gagne and Coppola (2014) for evidence suggesting that adult homesigners (and other language-delayed deaf subjects) may have impaired Theory of Mind-abilities, as shown by their difficulties in passing false belief tests. I have some reservations about the significance of these findings, and hope to address the issue in future work.

References

  • Amstrong, D., & Wilcox, S. (2011). Origins of sign languages. In M. Marschark & P. E. Spencer (Eds.), Oxford handbook of deaf studies, language, and education. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. J. (1954). Can there be a private language? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 28, 63–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-On, D. (2013a). Origins of meaning: Must we ‘go Gricean’? Mind and Language, 28(3), 342–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-On, D. (2013b). Expressive communication and continuity skepticism. Journal of Philosophy, 110(6), 293–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Begby, E. (2013). Semantic minimalism and the ‘miracle of communication’. Philosophical Studies, 165(3), 957–973.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Begby, E. (2014). Lexical norms, language comprehension, and the epistemology of testimony. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 44(3–4), 324–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Begby, E. (2016). Deranging the Mental Lexicon. Inquiry, 59(1), 33–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J. L. (2003). Thinking without words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Botha, R. (2007). On homesign systems as a potential window on language evolution. Language & Communication, 27(1), 41–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brentari, D., & Coppola, M. (2012). What sign language creation teaches us about language. WIREs Cognitive Science, 4, 201–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1975). On knowledge and convention. Philosophical Review, 84(2), 249–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Butcher, C., Mylander, C., & Goldin-Meadow, S. (1991). Displaced communication in a self-styled gesture system: Pointing at the non-present. Cognitive Development, 6(3), 315–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2007). Thinking with maps. Philosophical Perspectives, 21(1), 145–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrigan, E. M., & Coppola, M. (2012). Mothers do not drive structure in adult homesign systems: Evidence from comprehension. In N. Miyake, D. Peebles, & R. P. Cooper (Eds.), Proceedings of the 34th annual conference of the cognitive science society (pp. 1398–1403). Sapporo: Cognitive Science Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2002). Thoughts and utterances: The pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1986). Knowledge of language: Its nature, origin, and use. New York: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1988). Language and problems of knowledge: The Managua lectures. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, H. H., & Wilkes-Gibbs, D. (1986). Referring as a collaborative process. Reprinted in Arenas of language use. Chicago: University of Chicago Press & Center for the Study of Language and Information, 1992.

  • Dale, P. S., & Crain-Thoreson, C. (1993). Pronoun reversals: Who, when, and why? Journal of Child Language, 20(3), 573–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1986). A nice derangement of epitaphs. Reprinted in Truth, language, and history: philosophical papers (Vol. 5). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005.

  • de Saussure, F. (1916). Course in general linguistics (C. Bally & A. Sechehaye (Eds.), R. Harris, Trans.). La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1983.

  • Deacon, T. (1997). The symbolic species: The co-evolution of language and the brain. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2011). The symbol concept. In K. R. Gibson & M. Tallerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of language evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2013). What makes a property ‘semantic’? In A. Capone, F. Lo Piparo, & M. Carapezza (Eds.), Perspectives on pragmatics and philosophy. Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1978). The social character of meaning. In Truth and other enigmas. London: Duckworth.

  • Emmorey, K. (2002). Language, cognition, and the brain: Insights from sign language research. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, M. (2007). Talking hands: What sign language reveals about the mind. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frishberg, N. (1975). Arbitrariness and iconicity: Historical change in American sign language. Language, 51(3), 696–719.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gagne, D. L., & Coppola, M. (2014). Disentangling language and education effects on false belief understanding: Evidence from homesigners, signers, and unschooled spanish speakers. Quebec City: Proceedings of the Cognitive Science Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldfarb, W. (1985). Kripke on Wittgenstein on rules. Journal of Philosophy, 82(9), 471–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldin-Meadow, S. (1982). The resilience of recursion: A study of a communication system developed without a conventional language model. In E. Wanner & L. R. Gleitman (Eds.), Language acquisition: The state of the art. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldin-Meadow, S. (2002). Constructing communication by hand. Cognitive Development, 17(3–4), 1385–1405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldin-Meadow, S. (2003). The resilience of language: What gesture creation in deaf children can tell us about how all children learn language. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldin-Meadow, S., & Brentari, D. (2015). Gesture, sign, and language: The coming of age of sign language and gesture studies. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1–82.

  • Grice, H. P. (1967). Meaning. Reprinted in Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Grice, H. P. (1969). Utterer’s meaning and intentions. Reprinted in Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. Reprinted in Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Grice, H. P. (1982). Meaning revisited. Reprinted in Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Hockett, C. (1960). The origin of speech. Scientific American, 203, 88–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hunsicker, D., & Goldin-Meadow, S. (2013). Hierarchical structure in a self-created communication system: Building nominal constituents in homesign. Language, 88(4), 723–764.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. (1995). Patterns in the mind: Language and human nature. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1890). Principles of psychology (reprint edition, Vol. 2). Mineola, NY: Dover Publications.

  • James, W. (1892). Thought before language: A deaf-mute’s recollections. Philosophical Review, 1(6), 613–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1798). Anthropology from a pragmatic point of view (R. B. Louden, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006.

  • Kegl, J., Senghas, A., & Coppola, M. (1999). Creation through contact: Sign language emergence and sign language change in Nicaragua. In M. deGraff (Ed.), Language creation and language change: creolization, diachrony, and development. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kemmerling, A. (2013). Speaker’s meaning. In M. Sbisa & K. Turner (Eds.), Pragmatics of speech actions. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepore, E., & Ludwig, K. (2005). Donald Davidson: Meaning, truth, language, and reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1969). Convention: A philosophical study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1975). Languages and language. Reprinted in Philosophical papers (Vol. I). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Lyons, J. (1977). Semantics (Vol. 2). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1984). Wittgenstein on following a rule. Reprinted in Mind, value, and reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and world (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1998). Language conventions made simple. The Journal of Philosophy, 95(4), 161–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morford, J. P., & Goldin-Meadow, S. (1997). From here to there and now to then: The development of displaced reference in homesign and English. Child Development, 68(3), 420–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morford, J. P., & Kegl, J. (2000). Gestural precursors to linguistic constructs: How input shapes the form of language. In D. MacNeill (Ed.), Language and gesture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, G., & Kegl, J. (2006). Nicaraguan sign language and theory of mind: The issue of critical periods and abilities. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 47(8), 811–819.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1902). Logic as semiotic: The theory of signs. Reprinted in J. Buchler (Ed.), Philosophical writings of Peirce. New York: Dover.

  • Perry, J. (1997). Indexicals and demonstratives. In B. Hale & C. Wright (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of language. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petitto, L. A. (1987). On the autonomy of language and gesture: Evidence from the acquisition of personal pronouns in American sign language. Cognition, 27(1), 1–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (1994). The language instinct: How the mind creates language. New York: Harper Collins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2003). Language as an adaptation to the cognitive niche. In M. Christensen & S. Kirby (Eds.), Language evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pyers, J. E., & Senghas, A. (2009). Language promotes false-belief understanding: Evidence from learners of a new sign language. Psychological Science, 20(7), 805–812.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ree, J. (1999). I see a voice: Deafness, language, and the senses. New York, NY: Henry Holt and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richie, R., Yang, C., & Coppola, M. (2014). Modelling the emergence of lexicons in homesign systems. Topics in Cognitive Science, 6(1), 183–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sacks, O. (1989). Seeing voices: A journey into the world of the deaf. New York, NY: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandler, W., Meir, I., Padden, C., & Aronoff, M. (2005). The emergence of grammar: Systematic structure in a new language. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 102(7), 2661–2665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1972). Meaning. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schober, M. F., & Clark, H. H. (1989). Understanding by addressees and overhearers. Cognitive Psychology, 21(2), 211–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Senghas, A. (1995). The development of Nicaraguan sign language via the language acquisition process. In D. MacLaughlin, & S. McEwan (Eds.), BUCLD 19: Proceedings of the 19th annual Boston University conference on language development. Boston, MA: Cascadilla Press.

  • Senghas, A. (2005). Language emergence: Clues from a new Bedouin sign language. Current Biology, 15(12), R463–R465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (2008). Drawing the line between meaning and implicature—And relating them both to assertion. Nous, 42(3), 440–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D. & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: Cognition and communication (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell, 1996.

  • Stokoe, W. (1960). Sign language structure: An outline of the visual communication system of the American deaf. Studies in linguistics: Occasional papers (No. 8). Buffalo, NY: Dept. of Anthropology and Linguistics, University of Buffalo.

  • Tomasello, M. (2008). Origins of human communication. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomaszewski, P. (2006). From iconicity to arbitrariness: When do gestures become signs in a peer-group pidgin? Psychology of Language and Communication, 10(2), 27–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, D. (1997). Languages as social objects. Philosophy, 72(282), 499–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Wright, C. (1981). Rule-following, objectivity, and the theory of meaning. In S. H. Holtzman & C. M. Leich (Eds.), Wittgenstein: To follow a rule. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper has been in preparation for a long time, and I have incurred a number of debts of gratitude along the way. For their input and encouragement at various stages, I would like to thank Holly K. Andersen, Josh Armstrong, Dorit Bar-On, Feisal Ben Hassel, Jim Bogen, Emma Borg, Elisabeth Camp, Eve Clark, Marie Coppola, Ingrid Lossius Falkum, Olav Gjelsvik, Martin Hahn, Daniel Harris, Nancy Hedberg, Emily Hodges, Jo-Jo Koo, Şeyda Özçalışkan, David Pereplyotchik, Paul Pietroski, Bjørn Ramberg, Georges Rey, Paula Rubio-Fernandez, Rob Stainton, Susan G. Sterrett, and Nicole Wyatt, as well as audiences at Simon Fraser University, the 2012 meeting of the European Society for Philosophy and Psychology, the 2012 meeting of the Western Canadian Philosophical Association, the Centre for the Study of Mind in Nature (University of Oslo), Ruhr-University Bochum, and the University of Bergen, and students in PHIL 806 (Spring 2013) and PHIL 344 (Spring 2016) at Simon Fraser University. Special thanks are due to three anonymous referees for this journal. Early work on this paper was supported by a post-doctoral grant from the Research Council of Norway.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Endre Begby.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Begby, E. Language from the Ground Up: A Study of Homesign Communication. Erkenn 82, 693–714 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9839-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9839-1

Keywords

Navigation