Skip to main content
Log in

Why is There Something Rather Than Nothing? A Logical Investigation

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

From Leibniz to Krauss philosophers and scientists have raised the question as to why there is something rather than nothing (henceforth, the Question). Why-questions request a type of explanation and this is often thought to include a deductive component. With classical logic in the background only trivial answers are forthcoming. With free logics in the background, be they of the negative, positive or neutral variety, only question-begging answers are to be expected. The same conclusion is reached for the modal version of the Question, namely ‘Why is there something contingent rather than nothing contingent?’ (except that possibility of answers with neutral free logic in the background is not explored). The categorial version of the Question, namely ‘Why is there something concrete rather than nothing concrete?’, is also discussed. The conclusion is reached that deductive explanations are question-begging, whether one works with classical logic or positive or negative free logic. I also look skeptically at the prospects of giving causal-counterfactual or probabilistic answers to the Question, although the discussion of the options is less comprehensive and the conclusions are more tentative. The meta-question, viz. ‘Should we not stop asking the Question’, is accordingly tentatively answered affirmatively.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Lehmann (2002) did not provide rules for vacuously quantified sentences.

  2. There is one important difference between \(N/PFL_{=,\Box }\) on the one hand and \(LPCE + \mathbf {S5}\), the system in (Hughes and Cresswell 1996), on the other hand: \(\phi \leftrightarrow \forall x \phi \) (provided that x is not free in \(\phi \)) is an axiom scheme of \(LPCE + \mathbf {S5}\), whereas only the left-to-right direction is an axiom scheme of \(N/PFL_{=,\Box }\). Semantically, the difference is that in \(N/PFL_{=,\Box }\) the world-relative domains of quantification can be empty, whereas they cannot in \(LPCE + \mathbf {S5}\). The formal relevance of \(\mathbf {S5}\) consists in the fact that one does not need to assume a certain primitive rule called \(UGL\forall ^{n}\). The material relevance of \(\mathbf {S5}\) is due to the fact that it is generally taken to the correct logic for metaphysical or counterfactual necessity—see (Williamson 2013) for an argument. The dialectical relevance of \(\mathbf {S5}\) is that it gives very strong modal resources to those who attempt a deductive explanation.

  3. Note that, even if \(\phi \leftrightarrow \forall x \phi \) (with x not free in \(\phi \)) were one of the axiom schemes (as in \(LPCE + \mathbf {S5}\)—see footnote 4), this would still hold.

  4. Hughes and Cresswell (1996, p. 293) mention three other inference rules. For one of these, see note 4. The two other rules are the rule of necessitation (if \(\vdash _{N/PFL_{=, \Box }} \phi \), then \(\vdash _{N/PFL_{=, \Box }} \Box \phi \)) and the rule of universal generalisation (if \(\vdash _{N/PFL_{=, \Box }} \phi \), then \(\vdash _{N/PFL_{=, \Box }} \forall x \phi \)). For the two others, note the following two things. First, they can be made redundant, e.g. one can stipulate that all the axioms are necessary. (Necessity is closed under modus ponens.) Second, in neither case is the conclusion of the inference of the right syntactic form.

  5. Note that the proved equivalences in Case 3 are unaffected even if one were to add \(\phi \leftrightarrow \forall x \phi \) (with x not free in \(\phi \)) as an axiom scheme.

  6. I say ‘broadly speaking’, because Hintikka (1962) points to some problems that I will not elaborate on.

References

  • Albert, D. (2012). On the origin of everything. New York Times, Sunday Book Review.

  • Bromberger, S. (1966). Questions. Journal of Philosophy, 63(20), 597–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, E., & Olsson, E. J. (2001). The presumption of nothingness. Ratio, 14(3), 203–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Pendergraft, G. (2013). Does the consequence argument beg the question? Philosophical Studies, 166(3), 575–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleming, N. (1988). Why is there something rather than nothing? Analysis, 48(1), 32–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt, T. (Ed.). (2013). The puzzle of existence: Why is there something rather than nothing?. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, A. (2004). The poverty of theistic cosmology. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55(4), 561–614.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. (2012). Interpretations of probability. In: Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, winter 2012 edn. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/probability-interpret/.

  • Halbach, V. (2010). The logic manual. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawking, S., & Mlodinow, L. (2010). The grand design. New York: Bantam Books.

  • Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15(2), 135–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1962). Cogito, ergo sum: Inference or performance? Philosophical Review, 71(1), 3–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J., & Halonen, I. (1995). Semantics and pragmatics for why-questions. Journal of Philosophy, 92(12), 636–657.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, G. E., & Cresswell, M. J. (1996). A new introduction to modal logic. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jacquette, D. (1993). Logical dimensions of question-begging argument. American Philosophical Quarterly, 30(4), 317–327.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1981). Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science, 48(4), 507–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatary unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher & W. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (Vol. 8, pp. 410–505). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotzen, M. (2013). The probabilistic explanation of why there is something rather than nothing. In T. Goldschmidt (Ed.), The puzzle of existence: Why is there something rather than nothing? (pp. 215–234). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koura, A. (1988). An approach to why-questions. Synthese, 74(2), 191–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krauss, L. M. (2012). A universe from nothing: Why there is something rather than nothing. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehmann, S. (2002). More free logic. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic, handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. 5, pp. 197–259). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1714). Principles of nature and grace, based on reason. In: R. S. Woolhouse & R. Francks (Eds.), G. W. Leibniz Philosophical Texts, 1998 (pp. 258–266). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1973a). Causation. Journal of Philosophy, 70(17), 556–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). Causal explanation. In D. Lewis (Ed.), Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 214–240). Oxford: oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linsky, B., Zalta, E. N. (1994). In defense of the simplest quantified modal logic. Philosophical Perspectives 8:431–458.

  • Maitzen, S. (2012). Stop asking why there’s anything. Erkenntnis, 77(1), 51–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, C. (2014). Actualism. In: Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, summer 2016 edn. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/actualism/.

  • Nolt, J. (2014). Free logic. In: Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, winter 2014 edn. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/logic-free/.

  • Parfit, D. (2004). Why anything? Why this? In T. Crane & K. Farkas (Eds.), Metaphysics: A guide and anthology. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rundle, B. (2004). Why there is something rather than nothing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1971). Statistical explanation and statistical relevance. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1992). Scientific explanation. In M. H. Salmon (Ed.), Introduction to the philosophy of science (pp. 7–41). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2005). Explanations in science and the logic of why-questions: Discussion of the Halonen-Hintikka-approach and alternative proposal. Synthese, 143(1–2), 149–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1969). Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language (Vol. 20). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sommers, F. (1966). Why is there something and not nothing? Analysis, 26(6), 177–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2000). Do large probabilities explain better? Philosophy of Science, 67(3), 366–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2004). The causal and unification approaches to explanation unified–causally. Noûs, 38(1), 154–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller, P. (1974). On why-questions. Noûs, 8(4), 371–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P., & Lowe, E. J. (1996). Why is there anything at all? Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 70, 95–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2013). Modal logic as metaphysics. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2014). Scientific explanation. In: Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, winter 2014 edn. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/scientific-explanation/.

  • Woodward, J., & Hitchcock, C. (2003). Explanatory generalizations, part I: A counterfactual account. Noûs, 37(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jan Heylen.

Additional information

Previous versions of this paper have been presented at the Fifth Graduate Student Conference (27 March 2015, Leuven), the SePPhia Seminar (1 April, 2015), the Congress for Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science (7 August 2015, Helsinki), and the CEFISES Seminar in Louvain-la-Neuve (13 January 2016). I would like to thank the audiences for their comments and questions. Furthermore, I would like to thank the anonymous reviewers for their useful reports.

Appendix: Tree Proofs for Lemma 3.2

Appendix: Tree Proofs for Lemma 3.2

Before giving the tree proofs, let me remind the reader that \(\left( \alpha \wedge \beta \right) \) is definitionally equivalent to \(\lnot \left( \alpha \rightarrow \lnot \beta \right) \) and, consequently, \(\lnot \left( \alpha \wedge \beta \right) \) is definitionally equivalent to \(\lnot \lnot \left( \alpha \rightarrow \lnot \beta \right) \), which logically entails \(\left( \alpha \rightarrow \lnot \beta \right) \) (cf. the tree rules for double negation). So, one can use the rules for material implications.

figure b

For convenience, whenever the reductio assumption of a tree proof is a quantified sentence or the negation thereof the marker \(^{*}\) will be added directly.

Proof

(Case 1-i) For convenience and without loss of generality, let us consider only \(P\left( t\right) ^{*}\) and \(\exists x \left( x = t \wedge P\left( x \right) \right) ^{*}\).

figure c

Proof

(Case 1-ii) For convenience and without loss of generality, let us consider only \(P\left( t\right) ^{*}\) and \(\exists x \left( x = t \wedge P\left( x \right) \right) ^{*}\).

figure d

Proof

(Case 3.1)

figure e

Proof

(Case 3.2)

figure f

Proof

(Case 3.3)

figure g

Proof

(Case 3.4)

figure h

Proof

(Case 3.1-ii)

figure i

Proof

(Case 3.2-ii)

figure j

Proof

(Case 3.3-ii)

figure k

Proof

(Case 3.4-ii)

figure l

Proof

(Case 3.4-ii Cont.)

figure m

Proof

(Case 4-ii)

figure n

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Heylen, J. Why is There Something Rather Than Nothing? A Logical Investigation. Erkenn 82, 531–559 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9831-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9831-9

Keywords

Navigation