Skip to main content
Log in

Intensional Perceptual Ascriptions

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper defends the view that perceptual ascriptions such as “Jones sees a cat” are sometimes intensional. I offer a range of examples of intensional perceptual ascriptions, respond to objections to intensional readings of perceptual ascriptions, and show how widely accepted semantic accounts of intensionality can explain the key features of intensional perceptual ascriptions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, Moore (1905), Ayer (1940), Smythies (1956), Anscombe (1965), Hintikka (1969), Coburn (1977), Harman (1990), Chomsky (1995, p. 52), Moltmann (2008), Brogaard (2012), and Brogaard (2015). Interestingly, Montague (1974, p. 169) has “no serious objection” to distinguishing intensional and extensional readings of perceptual ascriptions but ignores intensional readings as part of his seminal treatment of intensional transitives “for simplicity.” The last section of this paper sketches an extension of his views on intensional transitives to perceptual verbs.

  2. Austin (1962), Dretske (1969), Grice (1989), Soames (2003). Barwise (1981) and Higginbotham (1983) give accounts of the semantics of perceptual verbs that assume complete extensionality.

  3. A better formulation of existence-neutrality would allow that there are non-vacuously existence-neutral readings of constructions involving no names or existential quantifiers (e.g. “I ordered all cars”), but the pursuit of such a formulation would take us too far afield.

  4. If it turned out that the stating-conveying distinction is not viable, this would at best call for a reformulation of my thesis in more precise terms. Ultimately, my view is that perceptual ascriptions involving quantifiers allow narrow scope readings like other mental ascriptions. This view is perfectly intelligible independently of the stating-conveying distinction. I approach the issue in terms of the latter distinction because that is how it has traditionally been formulated.

  5. If we don’t assume this, it is possible that contextual enrichment of literal meaning can yield either an intensional or an extensional proposition, which provides another reason for denying that (b) implies (a). Contextual enrichment is consistent with my position, and consistent with maintaining a stated-conveyed distinction (it simply gives a greater role to pragmatics in determining what is said). However, this is not how I ultimately want to account for the intensional–extensional distinction, so I set this possibility aside for simplicity here.

  6. See the quotes from Austin and Dretske in the next section.

  7. Moore (1905), Ayer (1940), Smythies (1956), Anscombe (1965), Hintikka (1969), Coburn (1977), Harman (1990), Chomsky (1995), Moltmann (2008), Brogaard (2012), and Brogaard (2015).

  8. Note that appearance-neutrality, as stated, is compatible with there being systematic constraints on phenomenology in order for one to see something. For example, appearance-neutrality is compatible with the relatively weak phenomenological constraints outlined by Siegel (2006).

  9. Ayer (1940, ch. 1) makes a similar observation.

  10. None of the alleged IPAs discussed in this section contain names as part of the object of the verb. The reason is that singular perceptual ascriptions such as (18) and (19) elicit mixed intuitions.

    1. (18)

      I see Barack Obama.

    2. (19)

      I see Santa Claus.

    Speaking for myself, I have difficulty hearing (18) intensionally: if it turns out that “Barack Obama” does not refer (not merely that Obama is not within sight), this statement will have turned out to be false or meaningless. However, I can easily see how (19) might be true despite the fact that Santa Claus does not exist.

    One possibility is that singular perceptual ascriptions have intensional readings only when the names occurring in them are not “real names,” i.e. when they are names that, unlike names such as mine or yours, merely stand in for descriptions. There seems to be a reading of “Santa Claus” on which it is treated as (something like) a description along the lines of “a bearded man with a red jacket.” This makes it easy to hear (19) as intensional. However, if “Santa Claus” is taken to be the name of an individual presumed to exist, it is harder to hear the intensional reading of (19). Space being limited, I am going to assume that true names do not lend themselves to IPAs. This simplifies the discussion of possible accounts of the intensional–extensional distinction in Sect. 3. Without this assumption, the approach I suggest needs to be extended to singular ascriptions, which is only possible under the assumption that names are generalized quantifiers (a view widely accepted among semanticists; see Barwise & Cooper 1981 and Westerståhl 2011).

  11. Austin’s extensive discussion of Ayer’s views contains several other objections, but all target idiosyncrasies of Ayer’s views, so I am not going to discuss them here. Several of Austin’s objections target idiosyncratic features of Ayer’s glosses on appearance-neutrality and existence-neutrality. For example, Ayer’s way of characterizing these features seems to commit him to Meinongian objects.

  12. As a historical note, I am doubtful that Ayer’s claims are fairly characterized in terms of “senses.” Ayer talks about the “usage” of perceptual verbs, not their senses.

  13. Some might say that this is due to a necessary connection between lying and stating: an utterance is lie-prone with respect to P if and only if it states P (see Stainton, in press). However, we need not assume such a connection to agree that stating a falsehood exposes one to blame in principle.

  14. Note that “visually hallucinating a pink elephant” does not fit the bill because it also says something about what is going on in the world outside.

  15. Normally, what is communicated is not altered by changes in wording that don’t affect what is stated. In the case of conversational implicatures, this is known as detachability (Grice 1989). There are exceptions to this generalization; it is certainly possible to convey messages with specific word choices. However, when this is the case we can generally use devices such as intonation to reinforce the message. Here it is very hard to see how intonation could be used to reinforce an existence-neutral reading.

  16. As noted earlier, this also seems to be an objection to the view under consideration, but it is not hard to see why Grice might have been more aware of it as an objection to an application of his theory of conversational implicatures than he was aware of it as an objection to the unstated qualification view.

  17. Incidentally, this explains why (21) is a poor choice to convey the content of a hallucination.

  18. One might think that this is not true on a phenomenal reading of “seems” or “appears.” First, I don’t think there are such readings (see the next objection below). Second, even if there were such readings, they would yield the wrong result: (20) expresses that one stands in the first-order mental state of experiencing a pink elephant, not that one stands in the higher-order mental state of experiencing seeing\(_{\mathrm{e}}\) a pink elephant. The content of the higher-order experience would be I am seeing a pink elephant, whereas the content of the first-order experience is There is a pink elephant.

  19. As highlighted in the preceding footnote, a non-epistemic, phenomenal “It appears that” qualification would have other unintended implications.

  20. See Quine (1956), Fodor (1979, Parsons (1990, and den Dikken et al. (1996).

  21. Montague (1973), Barwise and Cooper (1981), Dowty et al. (1981), Moltmann (1997), Stainton (1998a, b), Richard (2001), Forbes (2008), Westerståhl (2011).

  22. ibid.

  23. While I think that non-specificity and referential opacity can be explained in this way, this is not very important for my purposes, because existence-neutrality is the defining feature of intensionality for my purposes. I am skimming over many details for this reason.

  24. One major simplification is that, in Montague’s treatment, the object of the want is the intension of the sublimation of the variable (\({{\hat{}}}\, \lambda P[P(x)]\)).

  25. See Montague (1973).

  26. Perceptual ascriptions complemented by relative clauses (e.g. 33, 34) do not uniformly allow intensional readings.

    1. (33)

      I see that a car is turning.

    2. (34)

      I see who is turning.

    Relative clause ascriptions seem to involve metaphorical uses of perceptual verbs. Consider the fact that “seeing that” constructions are factive while “hearing that” constructions are not, and “smelling that” and “tasting that” constructions seem senseless. Moreover, “seeing that” and “hearing that” imply no perceptual experiences at all, whereas other uses of “to see” and “to hear” do. This heterogeneity suggests that relative clause ascriptions involve metaphorical extensions of the core, perceptual meanings of perceptual verbs.

  27. Sense-datum theory is now considered a marginal view. See Bourget and Chalmers (2014).

  28. I expand on this topic in a companion article entitled “Implications of Intensional Perceptual Ascriptions for Representationalism, Relationalism, and Disjunctivism” (ms). I defend the kind of representationalism motivated by the present approach in Bourget (2010b, a, 2015a) and in press (see also Bourget and Mendelovici (2014). This representationalist view plays a key role in Bourget (2015b).

References

  • Ali, S., Patel, M., Avenido, J., Jabeen, S., & Riley, W. J. (2011). Hallucinations: Common features and causes. Current Psychiatry, 10(11), 22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1965). The intentionality of sensation: A grammatical feature. In R. J. Butler (Ed.), Analytic Philosophy (pp. 158–180). Hoboken: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). Sense and sensibilia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. J. (1940). The foundations of empirical knowledge. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J. (1981). Scenes and other situations. Journal of Philosophy, 78(7), 369–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., & Cooper, R. (1981). Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 4(2), 159–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blanke, O., & Landis, T. (2003). The metaphysical art of Giorgio de Chirico. European Neurology, 50(4), 191–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourget, D. (2010a). Consciousness is underived intentionality. Noûs, 44(1), 32–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourget, D. (2010b). The representational theory of consciousness. PhD thesis, Australian National University.

  • Bourget, D. (2015a). Representationalism, perceptual distortion and the limits of phenomenal concepts. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 45(1), 16–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourget, D. (2015b). The role of consciousness in grasping and understanding. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91(1) (forthcoming).

  • Bourget, D. (in press). Representationalism and sensory modalities: An argument for intermodal representationalism. American Philosophical Quarterly.

  • Bourget, D. (ms). Implications of intensional perceptual ascriptions for representationalism, relationalism, and disjunctivism.

  • Bourget, D., & Chalmers, D. J. (2014). What do philosophers believe? Philosophical Studies, 170, 465–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourget, D., & Mendelovici, A. (2014). Tracking representationalism. In A. Bailey (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: The key thinkers (pp. 209–235). Vancouver: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2012). Seeing as a non-experiental mental state: The case from synesthesia and visual imagery. In R. Brown (Ed.), Consciousness inside and out: Phenomenology, neuroscience, and the nature of experience. Neuroscience Series, Synthese Library.

  • Brogaard, B. (2015). Perceptual reports. In M. Matthen (Ed.), Oxford handbook of the philosophy of perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, S., et al. (1916). On the interpretation of symptoms in the infective exhaustive psychoses. The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 43(6), 518–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1995). Language and nature. Mind, 104(413), 1–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coburn, R. C. (1977). Intentionality and perception. Mind, 86, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • den Dikken, M., Larson, R., & Ludlow, P. (1996). Intentional “transitive” verbs and concealed complement clauses. Revista De Linguistica, 8.

  • Dowty, D. R., Wall, R. E., & Peters, S. (1981). Introduction to Montague semantics. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1969). Seeing and knowing. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • First, M. B., Spitzer, R. L., Gibbon, M., & Williams, J. B. W. (1997). Structured clinical interview for DSM-IV axis I disorders (SCID-I), clinician version, user’s guide. Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Publishing, Inc.

  • Fodor, J. D. (1979). The linguistic description of opaque contexts. Spokane: Garland Pub.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forbes, G. (2002). Intensionality: Graeme Forbes. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 76(1), 75–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forbes, G. (2006). Attitude problems. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Forbes, G. (2008). Intensional transitive verbs. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2015 ed.).

  • French, L. (2011). Seeing schizophrenia from the patient’s viewpoint. Nursing2014, 41(10), 18–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1961). The causal theory of perception, part I. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 121, 121–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1989). Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1990). The intrinsic quality of experience. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 31–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. T. (1983). The logic of perceptual reports: An extensional alternative to situation semantics. Journal of Philosophy, 80, 100–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1969). The logic of perception. In J. Hintikka (Ed.), Models for modalities. Dordrecht: Reidel.

  • Lam, L. C., Leung, S., & Chow, L. (1998). Functional experiential hallucinosis after radiotherapy for nasopharyngeal carcinoma. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery & Psychiatry, 64(2), 259–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landis, B. N., & Burkhard, P. R. (2008). Phantosmias and parkinson disease. Archives of Neurology, 65(9), 1237–1239.

  • Moltmann, F. (1997). Intensional verbs and quantifiers. Natural Language Semantics, 5(1), 1–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, F. (2008). Intensional verbs and their intentional objects. Natural Language Semantics, 16(3), 239–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1973). The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In P. Suppes, J. Moravcsik & J. Hintikka (Eds.), Approaches to natural language (Vol. 49, pp. 221–242). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Montague, R. (1974). Formal philosophy: Selected papers of Richard Montague. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1905). The nature and reality of the objects of perception. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 6, 68–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Naito, E., Matsumoto, R., Hagura, N., Oouchida, Y., Tomimoto, H., & Hanakawa, T. (2011). Importance of precentral motor regions in human kinesthesia: A single case study. Neurocase, 17(2), 133–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1990). Events in the semantics of English: A study in subatomic semantics. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prerost, F. J., Sefcik, D., Smith, B. D., et al. (2014). Differential diagnosis of patients presenting with hallucinations. Osteopathic Family Physician, 6(2), 19–24.

  • Quine, W. V. (1956). Quantifiers and propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 53(5), 177–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richard, M. (2001). Seeking a centaur, adoring adonis: Intensional transitives and empty terms. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 25(1), 103–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartzman, D., Maravic, K., Kranczioch, C., & Barnes, J. (2008). Altered early visual processing components in hallucination-prone individuals. Neuroreport, 19(9), 933–937.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2006). How does phenomenology constrain object-seeing? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84(3), 429–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smythies, J. R. (1956). Analysis of perception. London: Routledge and K. Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (2003). Philosophical analysis in the twentieth century. Vol. 2: The age of meaning. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. (in press). Full-on stating. Mind and Language.

  • Stainton, R. J. (1998a). Quantifier phrases, meaningfulness “in isolation”, and ellipsis. Linguistics and Philosophy, 21(3), 311–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. J. (1998b). Unembedded definite descriptions and relevance. Revista Alicantina de Estudios Ingleses, 11, 231–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westerståhl, D. (2011). Generalized quantifiers. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2015 ed.).

Download references

Acknowledgments

Many thanks to Angela Mendelovici and Rob Stainton for helpful feedback and discussion. Thanks also to Adam Pautz, Alma Kabe, Alex Byrne, Alex Manafu, Berit Brogaard, Cathal O’Madagain, Chang Liu, Daniel Stoljar, David Chalmers, Dimitra Kourmatzis, Helen De Cruz, Helen Saradi, Joel Walmsley, Kati Farkas, Mika Jiang, Pawel Grabarczyk, Pekka Väyrynen, Tim Crane, and Una Jurkevica for their linguistic intuitions and/or other feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Bourget.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bourget, D. Intensional Perceptual Ascriptions. Erkenn 82, 513–530 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9830-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9830-x

Keywords

Navigation