Skip to main content
Log in

Expressivism About Reference and Quantification Over the Non-existent Without Meinongian Metaphysics

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Can we believe that there are non-existent entities without commitment to Meinongian metaphysics? This paper argues we can. What leads us from quantification over non-existent beings to Meinongianism is a general metaphysical assumption about reality at large, and not merely quantification over the non-existent. Broadly speaking, the assumption is that every being we talk about must have a real definition. It’s this assumption that drives us to enquire into the nature of beings like Pegasus, and what our relationship as thinkers is to them. However, I argue this assumption only holds if you think your language, and in particular that aspect of it to do with referring to entities works in a specific way. This is the specific way generally assumed by the discipline called ‘Semantics’. I sketch out an alternative, call it global expressivism, in which talk of referring is given an expressivist, speech-act theoretic treatment. If we accept that our talk of the non-existent works as the global expressivist tells us it does, then the question of the metaphysical nature of non-existent entities is utterly void. You might say that Pegasus is empty of any metaphysical nature. Since the non-existent lacks any metaphysical nature, the metaphysics of the non-existent, Meinongianism, as a form of inquiry, lacks a subject matter, despite the fact that we talk happily, and indeed unavoidably, of the non-existent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For various versions of the metaphysics of the non-existent see, Meinong (1904), Parsons (1980), Zalta (1988), Priest (2005) to name just a few.

  2. See Barker 2012, for a brief discussion of metaphysical emptiness in relation to truth-makers, and the kind of cognitive, explanatory work that replaces metaphysical explanation, that is, the seeking out of real definitions. A much more ambitious project is attempted in Barker 2007.

  3. For discussion of causal theories see Kripke 1980 and Devitt 1996.

  4. The empirical claim is a conjecture inspired by the work of Kripke (1982).

  5. The idea of files as functional unities is found in Barker (2004), Sainsbury (2005), and recently Recanati (2012).

  6. My approach assumes that files don’t have reference as such—pace Sainsbury (2005) and Recanati (2012). Files are theoretical entities of cognitive science. Reference is not a relation that has any explanatory role in the account of how talk works. Therefore, it won’t appear in the explanatory story featuring files.

  7. There is a treatment of indefinite descriptions linked to this account. I won’t go into it here. See Barker (2004, 2007) for sketches of aspects of this account.

  8. See Sainsbury 2005 and Recanati 2012 for a discussion of file merging.

  9. The speech-act approach in Barker (2004) offers a semantics offers a semantics because identities the meaning of a name with a referring act type—one identitied by a referential tree.

References

  • Barker, S. J. (2004). Renewing meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, S. J. (2007). Global expressivism: Language agency without semantics; reality without metaphysics. Internet Preprint.

  • Barker, S. J. (2012). Expressivism about truth-making. In B. Schnieder & F. Correia (Eds.), Grounding and explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (1996). Coming to our senses. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. New York: Crowell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1973). Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private languages. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, A. (1904). The theory of objects. In Meinong (Ed.), Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandtheorie und Psychologie. Leipzig: Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, C. (1980). Nonexistent objects. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2005). Towards non-being. The logic and metaphysics of intentionality. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2012). Mental files. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2005). Why truthmakers. In J. Dodd & H. Beebee (Eds.), Truthmakers. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sainsbury, M. (2005). Reference without referents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. (1988). Intensional logic and the metaphysics of intentionality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stephen Barker.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Barker, S. Expressivism About Reference and Quantification Over the Non-existent Without Meinongian Metaphysics. Erkenn 80 (Suppl 2), 215–234 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9699-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9699-5

Keywords

Navigation