Skip to main content
Log in

A critical review of the statisticalist debate

  • Area Review
  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Over the past decade philosophers of biology have discussed whether evolutionary theory is a causal theory or a phenomenological study of evolution based solely on the statistical features of a population. This article reviews this controversy from three aspects, respectively concerning the assumptions, applications, and explanations of evolutionary theory, with a view to arriving at a definite conclusion in each contention. In so doing I also argue that an implicit methodological assumption shared by both sides of the debate, namely the overconfidence in conceptual analysis as a tool to understand the scientific theory, is the real culprit that has both generated the problem and precluded its solution for such a long time.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See e.g., Okasha (2006) for a derivation of the Price equation.

  2. Hence the model defines fitness as a measure of the actual number of offspring causally related to phenotype, contradicting the common philosophical wisdom according to which fitness is the expected offspring number that supervenes on phenotype and the environment. This discrepancy will be discussed in section “Much ado about fitness”.

  3. An empirical application of the Price equation can be found in Morrissey et al. (2012), but it is for the purpose of a post-hoc check of predicted adaptive responses, and not for predicting evolutionary response or detecting a selective pressure.

  4. For this reason some statisticalists, e.g., Walsh (2007, p. 288), avoid taking this approach.

  5. The precise definition given by Woodward (2003) is more nuanced than this due primary to a possible violation of faithfulness, but these details can be ignored here.

  6. Note that this differs from the question regarding the causal basis or propensity interpretation of fitness as discussed above (section “The causal basis of fitness”), which asks whether phenotype can be a cause of fitness.

  7. Though not mentioned in his paper, a criterion similar to Walsh’s was already proposed by Cartwright (1979) and criticized by Dupré (1984).

  8. Matthen and Ariew attribute this definition to Sober (1984, pp. 21–22), but I couldn’t locate it in the pages they point to.

  9. However, since interventions on these error terms count at the same time as soft-interventions on fitness, they may also affect the rate of adaptive response if they change the mean fitness. I thank Bruce Glymour for pointing this out.

  10. Speed in this case, however, must be causally disconnected (or d-separated; Pearl 2000) from the skin thickness for predators’ attack to be an indiscriminate sampling of the latter. Otherwise there is an indirect selection of skin thickness (Sober 1984).

  11. Environmental factors in the causal graph represent these aspects of environment that are “experienced” by each individual, and are properties of individuals in this sense.

  12. I thank Patrick Forber for bringing my attention to this similarity.

  13. This does not mean, however, the causal exclusion problem does not exist in evolutionary biology. A similar problem, for example, emerges in the debate over levels of selection, i.e., whether group properties may have fitness contribution irreducible to individual properties (Okasha 2006). This is an open interesting question, but should be distinguished from the statisticalist debate.

References

  • Abrams M (2007) How do natural selection and random drift interact? Philos Sci 74(5):666–679

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abrams M (2013) Populations and pigeons: prosaic pluralism about evolutionary causes. Stud Hist Phil Biol Biomed Sci 44:294–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersson M (1982) Female choice selects for extreme tail length in a widowbird. Nature 299:818–820

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew A, Ernst Z (2009) What fitness can’t be. Erkenntnis 71:289–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew A, Lewontin R (2004) The confusions of fitness. Br J Philos Sci 55(2):347–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew A, Rice C, Rohwer Y (2015) Autonomous-statistical explanations and natural selection. Br J Philos Sci 66:635–658

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birch J (2014) Hamilton’s rule and its discontents. Br J Philos Sci 65:381–411

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouchard F, Rosenberg A (2004) Fitness, probability and the principles of natural selection. Br J Philos Sci 55:693–712

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon RN (1978) Adaptation and evolutionary theory. Stud Hist Phil Sci A 9(3):181–206

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon RN (2005) The difference between selection and drift: a reply to Millstein. Biol Philos 20(1):153–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon RN, Ramsey G (2007) What’s wrong with the emergentist statistical interpretation of natural selection and random drift? In: Hull DL, Ruse M (eds) The cambridge companion to the philosophy of biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 66–84

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Caballero A (1994) Developments in the prediction of effective population size. Heredity 73:657–679

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1979) Causal laws and effective strategies. Noûs 13(4):419–437

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coyne JA, Barton NH, Turelli M (1997) Perspective: a critique of Sewall Wright’s shifting balance theory of evolution. Evolution 51(3):643–671

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J (1984) Probabilistic causality emancipated. Midwest Stud Philos 9(1):169–175

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1930) The genetical theory of natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Forber P (2008) Evolution and the levels of selection Phil. Review 117(4):626–630

    Google Scholar 

  • Forber P, Reisman K (2007) Can there be stochastic evolutionary causes? Philos Sci 74(5):616–627

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank SA, Slatkin M (1990) Evolution in a variable environment. Am Nat 136(2):244

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillespie JH (1974) Natural selection for within-generation variance in offspring number. Genetics 76(3):601–606

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour B (2011) Modeling environments: interactive causation and adaptations to environmental conditions. Philos Sci 78:448–471

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1998) Critique of pure reason. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Krantz D, Luce R, Suppes P, Tversky A (1971) Foundations of measurement (additive and polynomial representations), vol 1. Academic Press, San Diego

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewens T (2004) The natures of selection. Br J Phil Sci 61:313–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd EA (1988) The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch M (2007) The origins of genome architecture. Sinauer Associates Inc., Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M (2009) Drift and “statistically abstractive explanation”. Philos Sci 76:464–487

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M (2010) What is drift? a response to Millstein, Skipper, and Dietrich. Philos Theory Biol 2:e102

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M, Ariew A (2002) Two ways of thinking about fitness and natural selection. J Phil 99(2):55–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M, Ariew A (2005) How to understand causal relations in natural selection: reply to Rosenberg and Bouchard. Biol Philos 20:355–364

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M, Ariew A (2009) Selection and causation. Philos Sci 76:201–224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mills SK, Beatty J (1979) The propensity interpretation of fitness. Philos Sci 46:263–286

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein R (2002) Are random drift and natural selection conceptually distinct? Biol Philos 17(1):33–53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein R (2005) Selection vs. drift: a response to Brandon’s reply. Biol Philos 20(1):171–175

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein R (2006) Natural selection as a population-level causal process. Br J Philos Sci 57(4):627–653

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein R (2008) Distinguishing drift and selection empirically: “the great snail debate” of the 1950s. J Hist Biol 41(2):339–367

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein R, Skipper RAJ, Dietrich MR (2009) (Mis)interpreting mathematical models: drift as a physical process. Philos Theory Biol 1:e002

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrissey MB, Kruuk LE, Wilson A (2010) The danger of applying the breeder’s equation in observational studies of natural populations. J Evol Biol 23(11):2277–2288

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrissey MB, Parker DJ, Korsten P, Pemberton JM, Kruuk LE, Wilson AJ (2012) The prediction of adaptive evolution: empirical application of the secondary theorem of selection and comparison to the breeder’s equation. Evolution 66(8):2399–2410

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Northcott R (2010) Walsh on causes and evolution. Philos Sci 77:457–467

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2006) Evolution and the levels of selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Otsuka J (2015) Using causal models to integrate proximate and ultimate causation. Biol Philos 30(1):19–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Otsuka J (2016) Causal foundations of evolutionary genetics. Br J Philos Sci 67:247–269

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Otsuka J, Turner T, Allen C, Lloyd EA (2011) Why the causal view of fitness survives. Philos Sci 78(2):209–224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl J (2000) Causality: models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Pence CH, Ramsey G (2013) A new foundation for the propensity interpretation of fitness. Br J Philos Sci 64:851–881

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M, Kaplan J (2006) Making sense of evolution: the conceptual foundations of evolutionary biology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey G (2013) Organisms, traits, and population subdivisions: two arguments against the causal conception of fitness? Br J Philos Sci 64(3):589–608

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rausher MD (1992) The measurement of selection on quantitative traits: biases due to environmental covariances between traits and fitness. Evolution 46(3):616–626

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reisman K, Forber P (2005) Manipulation and the causes of evolution. Philos Sci 72:1113–1123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rice SH (2004) Evolutionary theory: mathematical and conceptual foundations. Sinauer Associates Inc., Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Robb D, Heil J (2003) Mental causation. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mental-causation/. Accessed 20 March 2016

  • Rosenberg A (1985) The structure of biological science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A, Bouchard F (2005) Matthen and Ariew’s obituary for fitness: reports of its death have been greatly exaggerated. Biol Philos 20(2–3):343–353

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro L, Sober E (2007) Epiphenomenalism - the do’s and the don’ts. In: Wolters G, Machamer P (eds) Thinking about causes: from greek philosophy to modern physics. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, pp 235–264

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1984) The nature of selection: evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1993) Philosophy of biology. Westview Press, Boulder

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (2001) The two faces of fitness. In: Singh RS, Krimbas CB, Paul DB, Beatty J (eds) Thinking about evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 309–321

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (2013) Trait fitness is not a propensity, but fitness variation is. Stud Hist Phil Biol Biomed Sci 44(3):336–341

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spirtes P, Glymour C, Scheines R (2000) Causation, prediction, and search, 2nd edn. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephens C (2004) Selection, drift, and the “forces” of evolution. Philos Sci 71(4):550–570

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wade MJ, Goodnight CJ (1998) Perspective: the theories of Fisher and Wright in the context of metapopulations: when nature does many small experiments. Evolution 52(6):1537–1553

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wade MJ, Kalisz S (1990) The causes of natural selection. Evolution 44(8):1947–1955

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (2010) The measurement theory of fitness. Evolution 64(5):1358–1376

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D (2015) Variance, invariance and statistical explanation. Erkenntnis 80(3):469–489

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2007) The pomp of superfluous causes: the interpretation of evolutionary theory. Philos Sci 74:281–303

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2010) Not a sure thing: fitness, probability, and causation. Philos Sci 77(2):147–171

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM, Lewens T, Ariew A (2002) The trials of life: natural selection and random drift. Philos Sci 69(3):452–473

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward JB (2003) Making things happen: a theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Patrick Forber, Charles Pence, and the members of Griesemer/Millstein philbio lab at UC Davis for their helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jun Otsuka.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Otsuka, J. A critical review of the statisticalist debate. Biol Philos 31, 459–482 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-016-9528-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-016-9528-0

Keywords

Navigation