Skip to main content
Log in

Modelling and the fall and rise of the handicap principle

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The story of the fall and rise of Zahavi’s handicap principle is one of a battle between models. Early attempts at formal modeling produced negative results and, unsurprisingly, scepticism about the principle. A major change came in 1990 with Grafen’s production of coherent models of a handicap mechanism of honest signalling. This paper’s first claim is that acceptance of the principle, and its dissemination into other disciplines, has been driven principally by that, and subsequent modeling, rather than by empirical results. Secondly, there is a vast literature on biological signalling but few studies that make all of the observations necessary to diagnose the handicap mechanism. My final claim is that many of the applications of “costly signalling theory” in other disciplines are conceptually confused. Misinterpretations of what is meant by “costly signalling” are common. Demonstrating that a signal is costly is insufficient and is not always necessary in order to prove that, and explain why, a signal is honest. In addition to the biological modelling of signals, there is an economic literature on the same subject. The two run in parallel in the sense that they have had little mutual interaction. Additionally, it is the biological modelling that has been picked up, and often misapplied, by other disciplines.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is taken from a review of Zahavi and Zahavi’s (1997) The Handicap Principle. Pomiankowski & Iwasa do not actually address the first of the questions that they pose, that is, why the change? They say something on the second along lines similar to my section six, which is that hard evidence of examples is difficult to find.

  2. Arnqvist and Rowe’s Sexual Conflict (2005) does have some history in it but that appears in their chapter that discusses runaway versus indicator (handicap) models.

  3. It provides no information in the statistical sense (Skyrms 2010).

  4. It should be noted that this is the case where individuals are in a “game” in which their interests conflict. As discussed in section five, where interests coincide perfectly, honest signals can be cheap. For now it suffices to note that, when it comes to potential instances of handicap signals, we are dealing with conflicts of interest.

  5. Here and in much of what follows I refer to signallers as “males” and receivers as “females” purely for ease of exposition. Many examples of animal communication do follow this pattern but they need not.

  6. This is a typical and reasonable assumption in population genetic modelling.

  7. See Web of Science counts for Zahavi (1975) and Spence (1973).

  8. Møller (1994) demonstrates that tail size correlates with offspring viability, suggesting that it is a reliable signal of quality. Saunders (2009) points out some methodological problems with this study. Møller and de Lope use survival as a proxy for lifetime reproductive fitness. It is true that the two are not perfectly correlated but use of a proxy is very often unavoidable. He also comments that they do not compare swallows with the same original tail length as should be done to examine costs at the same point on the cost curve.

  9. Searcy and Nowicki (2005) make the same point.

  10. Although this case is striking it has been noted that, compared to its prominence in the literature, there is surprisingly little empirical support, Homo sapiens excepted, for the reciprocal altruism/cooperation models stemming from Robert Trivers’ (1971) early work (Hammerstein 2003). Joan Silk goes so far as to argue that there is slim evidence in humans of the reciprocity of tit-for-tat models (Silk 2003).

  11. Web of Science 24/8/10, 28/5/10 and 30/8/10 respectively.

  12. Web of Science 30/8/10.

  13. Gintis and Bowles are economists who buck the trend but the paper is in The Journal of Theoretical Biology.

  14. My discussion of evidence of the handicap mechanism in action can be fitted into current philosophical debates on modelling in biology and economics. In the case of costly apologies, we find a model purporting to share a common structure with the handicap model but which, in fact, makes different substantive assumptions (Kuorikoski and Lehtinen 2009) about costs and benefits. In other cases, we find an unwarranted inference from observation of the result of the model (honest signalling), to the fact that it must be this model that explains the result. Put another way, to the truth of the model’s substantive assumptions, such as that interests conflict. As Sugden (2009) argues, biologists are typically silent about precisely in what sense their model is similar to, or well-represents, the real world. This is a problem even if we have good reason to think that the substantive assumptions hold. I am arguing that there are “costly signalling” cases where it is clear that the model is not a good representation because even that initial hurdle is not cleared; at least one substantive assumption does not hold, often that there are differential costs. As Kuorikoski and Lehtinen put it, “it is the truthlikeness of the substantial assumptions that ultimately carries the epistemic weight in a model” (2009, 127).

  15. Koziel et al.’s (2010) paper on tattoos as “signals of biological quality” suffers from the same currency ambiguity as the blood donation case.

References

  • Arnqvist G, Rowe L (2005) Sexual conflict. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Bliege Bird R, Smith E, Bird D (2001) The hunting handicap: costly signalling in human foraging strategies. Behav Ecol Sociobiol 50:9–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowles S, Hammerstein P (2003) Does market theory apply to biology? In: Hammerstein P (ed) Genetic and cultural evolution of cooperation. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 153–166

    Google Scholar 

  • Caro T (1995) Pursuit-deterrence revisited. Trends Ecol Evol 10:500–503

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cotton S, Fowler K, Pomiankowski A (2004) Do sexual ornaments demonstrate heightened condition-dependent expression as predicted by the handicap hypothesis? Proc R Soc Lond B 271:771–783

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cronk L (2005) The application of animal signaling to human phenomena: Some thoughts and clarifications. Soc Sci Inf 44:603–620

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David P, Bjorksten T, Fowler K, Pomiankowski A (2000) Condition-dependent signalling of genetic variation in stalk-eyed flies. Nature 406:186–188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis J, O’Donald P (1976) Sexual selection for a handicap: a critical analysis of Zahavi’s model. J Theor Biol 57:345–354

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1989) The selfish gene, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • De Fraja G (2009) The origin of utility: sexual selection and conspicuous consumption. J Econ Behav Organ 72:51–69

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ekman P (1992) Telling lies, 2nd edn. W. W. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher R (1999) The genetical theory of natural selection: a complete variorum edition [1930]. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • FitzGibbon C, Fanshawe J (1988) Stotting in Thomson’s gazelles: an honest signal of condition. Behav Ecol Sociobiol 23:69–74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank R (1988) Passions within reason: the strategic role of the emotions. W W Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Getty T (2006) Sexually selected signals are not similar to sports handicaps. Trends Ecol Evol 21:83–88

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbons R (1992) Game theory for applied economists. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Gintis H (2000) Game theory evolving. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Gintis H, Smith E, Bowles S (2001) Costly signalling and cooperation. J Theor Biol 213:103–119

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giraldeau J, Caraco T (2000) Social foraging theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (1990a) Sexual selection unhandicapped by the Fisher process. J Theor Biol 144:473–516

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (1990b) Biological signals as handicaps. J Theor Biol 144:517–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guilford T, Stamp Dawkins M (1991) Receiver psychology and the evolution of animal signals. Anim Behav 42:1–14

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halliday T (1978) Sexual selection and mate choice. In: Krebs J, Davies N (eds) Behavioural ecology, an evolutionary approach, 1st edn. Blackwell Scientific Publications, Oxford, pp 180–213

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton W (1967) Extraordinary sex ratios. Science 156:477–488

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton W (2001) Narrow roads of gene land, vol 2. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammerstein P (2003) Why is reciprocity so rare in social animals? A Protestant appeal. In: Hammerstein P (ed) Genetic and cultural evolution of cooperation. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 83–94

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnstone RA (1997) The evolution of animal signals. In: Krebs J, Davies N (eds) Behavioural ecology, an evolutionary approach, 4th edn. Blackwell Scientific Publications, Oxford, pp 155–178

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnstone R (2000) Conflicts of interest in signal evolution. In: Espmark Y, Amundsen T, Rosenqvist G (eds) Animal signals. Tapir Academic Press, Trondheim, pp 465–485

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirkpatrick M (1986) The handicap mechanism of sexual selection does not work. Amer Nat 127:222–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirmani A, Rao A (2000) No pain, no gain: a critical review of the literature of signaling unobservable product quality. J Marketing 64:66–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kotiaho J (2000) Testing the assumptions of conditional handicap theory: costs and condition dependence of a sexually selected trait. Behav Ecol Sociobiol 48:188–194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koziel S, Kretschmer W, Pawlowski B (2010) Tattoo and piercing as signals of biological quality. Evol Hum Behav 31:187–192

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krebs J, Davies N (1987) An introduction to behavioural ecology, 2nd edn. Blackwell Scientific Publications, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski J, Lehtinen A (2009) Incredible worlds, credible results. Erkenn 70:119–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lachmann M, Szamado S, Bergstrom C (2001) Cost and conflict in animal signals and human language. Proc Nat Acad Sci 23:13189–13194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LaPorte J (2002) Must signals handicap? Monist 85:86–104

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyle H, Smith E, Sullivan R (2009) Blood donations as costly signals of donor quality. J Evol Psy 7:263–286

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1976) Sexual selection and the handicap principle. J Theor Biol 57:239–242

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1978) The handicap principle—a comment. J Theor Biol 70:251–252

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1991) Theories of sexual selection. Trends Ecol Evol 6:146–151

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J, Harper D (2003) Animal signals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J, Price G (1973) The logic of animal conflict. Nature 246:15–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Møller A (1994) Male ornament size as a reliable cue to enhanced offspring viability in the barn swallow. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 91:6929–6932

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Møller A, de Lope F (1994) Differential costs of a secondary sexual character; an experimental test of the handicap principle. Evolution 48:1676–1683

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ohtsubo Y, Watanabe E (2009) Do sincere apologies need to be costly? Testing a costly signaling model of apology. Evol Hum Behav 30:114–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petrie M (1994) Improved growth and survival of offspring of peacocks with elaborate trains. Nature 371:598–599

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petrie M, Halliday T, Saunders C (1991) Peahens prefer peacocks with more elaborate trains. Anim Behav 41:323–331

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pomiankowski A (1987) Sexual selection: the handicap mechanism does work—sometimes. Proc R Soc Lond B 231:123–145

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pomiankowski A, Iwasa Y (1998) Handicap signalling: loud and true? Evolution 52:928–932

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riley J (2001) Twenty five years of screening and signalling. J Econ Lit 39:432–478

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan M (1997) Sexual selection and mate choice. In: Krebs J, Davies N (eds) Behavioural ecology, an evolutionary approach, 4th edn. Blackwell Scientific Publications, Oxford, pp 179–202

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson L (1998) Evolutionary games and equilibrium selection. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Saunders S (2009) Costly signalling: a work in progress. Biol Philos 24:405–416

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt K, Cohn J (2001) Human facial expressions as adaptations: evolutionary questions in facial expression research. Am J Phys Anthropol, Suppl 33:3–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searcy W, Nowicki S (2005) The evolution of animal communication. Reliability and deception in signalling systems. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Seymour R, Sozou P (2009) Duration of courtship effort as a costly signal. J Theor Biol 256:1–13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shuster S, Wade M (2003) Mating systems and strategies. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Silk J (2003) Cooperation without counting: the puzzle of friendship. In: Hamerstein P (ed) Genetic and cultural evolution of cooperation. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 37–54

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms B (2010) Signals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith E, Bliege Bird R (2000) Turtle hunting and tombstone opening: public generosity as costly signalling. Evol Hum Behav 21:245–261

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spence AM (1973) Job market signalling. Quart J Econ 87:355–374

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2009) Credible worlds, capacities and mechanisms. Erkenn 70:3–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trivers R (1971) The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Q Rev Biol 46:35–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veblen T (1899) The theory of the leisure class. An economic study in the evolution of institutions. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Walther B, Clayton D (2005) Elaborate ornaments are costly to maintain: evidence for high maintenance handicaps. Behav Ecol 16:89–95

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West S (2009) Sex allocation. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi A (1975) Mate selection-selection for a handicap. J Theor Biol 53:205–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi A (1977) The cost of honesty (further remarks on the handicap principle). J Theor Biol 67:603–605

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi A, Zahavi A (1997) The handicap principle, a missing piece of Darwin’s puzzle. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to audiences at The British Society for the Philosophy of Science conference, Dublin 2010 and at the University of Bristol for helpful discussions and to two anonymous referees for very useful comments. Research funded by the Arts and Humanities Research Council project “Evolution, Cooperation and Rationality”. Grant AH/F017502/1.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonathan Grose.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Grose, J. Modelling and the fall and rise of the handicap principle. Biol Philos 26, 677–696 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9275-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9275-1

Keywords

Navigation