Skip to main content
Log in

Explaining social norm compliance. A plea for neural representations

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

How should we understand the claim that people comply with social norms because they possess the right kinds of beliefs and preferences? I answer this question by considering two approaches to what it is to believe (and prefer), namely: representationalism and dispositionalism. I argue for a variety of representationalism, viz. neural representationalism. Neural representationalism is the conjunction of two claims. First, what it is essential to have beliefs and preferences is to have certain neural representations. Second, neural representations are often necessary to adequately explain behaviour. After having canvassed one promising way to understand what neural representations could be, I argue that the appeal to beliefs and preferences in explanations of paradigmatic cases of norm compliance should be understood as an appeal to neural representations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Decision theorists tend to talk of ‘preferences’ instead of ‘desires.’ In what follows, ‘preference’ and ‘desire’ are used interchangeably, consistently with the accounts of norms I consider.

  2. Interestingly, some psychological theories seem to take into account some features of both representationalism and dispositionalism: e.g. Daniel Kahneman’s dual-process theory, and the distinction between systems 1 and system 2 (cf. Kahneman 2003). I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer to draw my attention to this point.

  3. The following parallels an example in Haugeland (1998, p. 143).

  4. Different types of agents in Ray et al. (2009) account of the Trust Game were defined by the extent to which they were averse to unequal outcomes and by their level of strategic thinking.

  5. Recall that in their account beliefs about your cognitive and volitional profile influence my preferences about payoffs in the game. Interestingly, also in Bicchieri’s (2006) account of norm compliance preferences are dependent on beliefs. On her model, an agent’s preferences are conditional on his or her own beliefs regarding other people’s actions and expectations. So one prefers to follow a norm if he or she believes that certain conditions occur.

References

  • Beer, R. D. (2008). The dynamics of brain-body-environment systems: a status report. In P. Calvo & A. Gomila (Eds.), Handbook of cognitive science: an embodied approach (pp. 99–120). San Diego: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bicchieri, C. (2006). The grammar of society: the nature and dynamics of social norms. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bicchieri, C., & Xiao, E. (2009). Do the right thing: but only if others do so. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 22(2), 191–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C. (2003). Behavioral game theory: experiments on strategic interaction. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2000). Anti-representationalism and the dynamical stance. Philosophy of Science, 67, 625–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1980). Rules and representations. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 1–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1992). The computational brain. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2002). Skills, spills, and the nature of mindful action. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 385–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2000). Making moral space. A reply to Churchland. In: Campbell R, Hunter B (Eds.), Moral epistemology naturalized: Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary VolumeXXVI, 307–312.

  • Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101, 401–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombo, M. (2010). How ‘authentic intentionality’ can be enabled: a neurocomputational hypothesis. Minds and Machines, 20(2), 183–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombo, M., & Seriès, P. (2012). Bayes in the brain. On Bayesian modelling in neuroscience. The British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 63, 697–723.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dayan, P., & Abbott, L. (2001). Theoretical neuroscience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • deCharms, R. C., & Zador, A. (2000). Neural representation and the cortical code. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 23, 613–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1982/83). Styles of mental representation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, LXXXIII, 213–26.

  • Dreyfus, H. (2002a). Intelligence without representation: Merleau-Ponty's critique of mental representation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 367–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (2002b). Refocusing the question: can there be skillful coping without propositional representations or brain representations? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 413–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliasmith, C. (2003). Moving beyond metaphors: understanding the mind for what it is. Journal of Philosophy, C(10), 493–520.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1989). Social norms and economic theory. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 3(4), 99–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engel, P. (2005). Tacit Belief. In W. Østreng (Ed.), Synergies: interdisciplinary communications (pp. 98–100). Oslo: Center for Advanced Study.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1968). The appeal to tacit knowledge in psychological explanation. Journal of Philosophy, 65, 627–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: a critical analysis. Cognition, 28, 3–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, W. J. (1991). The physiology of perception. Scientific American, 264, 78–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, W. J., & Skarda, C. A. (1990). Representations: who needs them? In L. McGaugh & N. M. Weinberge (Eds.), Brain organization and memory: cells, systems, and circuits (pp. 375–380). London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K., & Stephan, K. E. (2007). Free energy and the brain. Synthese, 159, 417–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gershman, S. J., & Daw, N. D. (2012). Perception, action and utility: the tangled skein. In M. Rabinovich, K. Friston, & P. Varona (Eds.), Principles of brain dynamics: global state interactions. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1998). Having thought: essays in the metaphysics of mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubel, D. H., & Wiesel, T. N. (1962). Receptive fields, binocular interaction and functional architecture in the cat’s visual cortex. The Journal of Physiology, 160, 106–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2003). A perspective on judgment and choice: mapping bounded rationality. American Psychologist, 58, 697–720.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kawato, M. (2008a). From "Understanding the brain by creating the brain" towards manipulative neuroscience. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 363, 2201–2214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kawato, M. (2008b). Brain controlled robots. HFSP Journal, 2, 136–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King-Casas, B., Tomlin, D., Anen, C., Camerer, C. F., Quartz, S. R., & Montague, P. R. (2005). Getting to know you: reputation and trust in a two-person economic exchange. Science, 308, 78–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King-Casas, B., Sharp, C., Lomax-Bream, L., Lohrenz, T., Fonagy, P., & Montague, P. R. (2008). The rupture and repair of cooperation in borderline personality disorder. Science, 321, 806–810.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knill, D. C., & Richards, W. (Eds.). (1996). Perception as Bayesian inference. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1969). Convention: a philosophical study. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKay, D. J. C. (2003). Information theory, inference and learning algorithms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A., & Simon, H. (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (1990). Virtus Normativa: rational choice perspectives. Ethics, 100, 725–755.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pouget, A., Dayan, P., & Zemel, R. S. (2003). Inference and computation with population codes. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 26, 381–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. M. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ray, D., King-Casas, B., Montague, P. R., & Dayan, P. (2009). Bayesian model of behaviour in economic games. In D. Koller, D. Schuurmans, Y. Bengio, & L. Bottou (Eds.), Advances in neural information processing systems (Vol. 21, pp. 1345–1352). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rust, N. C., & Stocker, A. A. (2010). Ambiguity and invariance: two fundamental challenges for visual processing. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 20, 382–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sato, H., & Maharbiz, M. M. (2010). Recent developments in the remote radio control of insect flight. Frontiers in Neuroscience, 4(199), 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2006/2010). Belief. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/belief. Accessed 14 Jan 2013.

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2002). A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief. Nous, 36, 249–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shannon, C. (1948). A mathematical theory of communication. Bell Systems Technical Journal, 27(279–423), 623–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (1986). The economics of rights, cooperation and welfare. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tenenbaum, J. B., Kemp, C., Griffiths, T. L., & Goodman, N. D. (2011). How to grow a mind: statistics, structure and abstraction. Science, 331, 1279–1285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ullmann-Margalit, E. (1977). The emergence of norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanderbeeken, R., & Weber, E. (2002). Dispositional explanations of behavior. Behavior and Philosophy, 30, 43–59.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am sincerely grateful to Andy Clark, Dave Des Roches-Dueck, Angelica Kaufmann, Julian Kiverstein, Suilin Lavelle, Ray Debajyoti and Mark Sprevak for their generous feedback on previous versions of this paper, and/or for fun discussion of specific ideas in the paper. A special thank you to two anonymous reviewers of this journal for their constructive comments and helpful suggestions. This work was supported by a grant from the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG) as part of the priority program “New Frameworks of Rationality” (SPP 1516). The usual disclaimers about any error or mistake in the paper apply.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matteo Colombo.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Colombo, M. Explaining social norm compliance. A plea for neural representations. Phenom Cogn Sci 13, 217–238 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-013-9296-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-013-9296-0

Keywords

Navigation