Skip to main content
Log in

Empirical Methods in Animal Ethics

  • Articles
  • Published:
Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this article the predominant, purely theoretical perspectives on animal ethics are questioned and two important sources for empirical data in the context of animal ethics are discussed: (mostly qualitative) methods of the social and (mainly quantitative) methods of the natural sciences. Including these methods can lead to an empirical animal ethics approach that is far more adapted to the needs of humans and nonhuman animals and more appropriate in different circumstances than a purely theoretical concept solely premised on rational arguments. However, the potential tension between lay people’s moral judgements and ethical theory must be handled with care. The thorough analysis of qualitative data can lead to a deep insight into e.g. ethical problems with the application of laws and guidelines, practicality issues with ethical theories, personal ambivalence, and cognitive biases. The interaction between animal ethics theory and empirical findings can lead to both a more context-sensitive and applicable ethical theory and a less arbitrary folk moral system. Findings from the natural sciences can also contribute valuable information to animal ethics theory—the more we know about the properties and preferences of nonhuman animals the better we can respect them. Here, however, it is vital not to justify invasive procedures for the sake of “ethical progress”. It might be ethically required to forego some scientific findings about nonhuman animals if it is not clear how much a procedure would harm them. Only with robust empirical methods will light ultimately be shed on the nature of our moral relationship with animals.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this paper “animal ethics” is understood in a rather narrow sense, referring to the philosophical field that developed in the 1970 s with Richard Ryder, Roslind and Stanley Godlovitch, Peter Singer and others who started thinking and writing about animal liberation and animal rights. Consequentialist and deontological approaches are considered to be the predominant ones while acknowledging that there is a broad spectrum of theories involving virtue ethics, care ethics, contractualism and many more (Wolf 2008).

  2. This is e.g. illustrated in case of a project by the Swiss Federal Ethics Committee on Non-Human Biotechnology (ECNH): With publications from both fields, biology and philosophy, they present an interdisciplinary perspective on cognition, consciousness and pain in fish. Thereby, they provide the basis for a more profound ethical discussion about how this group of nonhuman animals should be treated.

  3. Folk morality refers to the way people without a special philosophical education/qualification deal with moral problems. It has gained much attention recently by experimental philosophers or neuroethicists (Nichols and Knobe 2007; Kahane and Shackel 2008; Sytsma and Machery 2012) but it can additionally be investigated in a qualitative way, as suggested in this paper.

  4. The expression „naturalistic fallacy”, also known as “is-ought-fallacy”, refers to several concepts of slightly different meanings (Engels 2008). Here it should be understood as: jumping from empirical, descriptive premises to a normative, evaluative conclusion without an explanation for the normative nature of the conclusion. A biologistic argument of that sort might be as follows: We found an evolutionary trend towards a certain trait, therefore we should prefer this trait/breed organisms with this trait/privilege those who carry this trait or consider this trait as something good.

  5. http://www.projetogap.org.br/en/world-declaration-on-great-primates/.

  6. The “Knobe effect” is the name for the main result of a study by Joshua Knobe in 2003: in his thought experiment he presented the situation of a chairman who decides to start a profitable program knowing that its side effects will in case a) harm and in case (b) help the environment. The man does not care about the environment at all but is just interested in the company’s profit. When the program starts and the environment is in (a) harmed and in (b) helped, the experiment’s participant is asked if the chairman (a) harmed and (b) helped the environment intentionally and if he was to be blamed/praised. Although the modification between (a) and (b) is not immediately related to the concept of intentionality, more than 80 % of the participants thought that the chairman harmed the environment intentionally whereas over 70 % found that he did not help the environment intentionally.

  7. This example is part of the authors` empirical work with thought experiments.

References

  • Aaltola, E. (2013). Skepticism, empathy, and animal suffering. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry, 10(4), 457–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aitken, G. (2004). A new approach to conservation: The importance of the individual through wildlife rehabilitation. London: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti, L. (2007). Disputes over moral status: Philosophy and science in the future of bioethics. Health Care Analysis, 15(2), 153–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broom, D. (2007). Cognitive ability and sentience: Which aquatic animals should be protected? Diseases of Aquatic Organisms, 75(2), 99–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conte, F. S. (2004). Stress and the welfare of cultured fish. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 86(3–4), 205–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, D. K. C., Gollackner, B., & Sachs, D. H. (2002). Will the pig solve the transplantation backlog? Annual Review of Medicine, 53(1), 133–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1989). The selfish gene. 1976, revised edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, M. S. (2008). The science of animal suffering. Ethology, 114(10), 937–945.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, M. S., & Beardsley, T. (1986). Reinforcing properties of access to litter in hens. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 15(4), 351–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Vries, R., & Gordijn, B. (2009). Empirical ethics and its alleged meta-ethical fallacies. Bioethics, 23(4), 193–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, D. (1997). Great apes, dolphins, and the concept of personhood. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 35, 301–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, D. (2011). The ethics of confining animals: From farms to zoos to human homes. In R. Frey & T. Beauchamp (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of animal ethics (pp. 738–768). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, S., & Kymlicka, W. (2011). Zoopolis: A political theory of animal rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donovan, J. (1990). Animal rights and feminist theory. Signs, 15(2), 350–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donovan, J. (2008). Aufmerksamkeit für das Leiden. Migefühl als Grundlage der moralischen Behandlung von Tieren. In Wolf, U. (ed), Texte zur Tierethik. Stuttgart, Philipp Reclam jun. GmbH & Co.

  • Elwood, R. W., Barr, S., & Patterson, L. (2009). Pain and stress in crustaceans? Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 118(3–4), 128–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engels, E.-M. (2008). Was und wo ist ein “naturalistischer Fehlschluss”? In C. E. Brand, E.-M. Engels, A. Ferrari, & L. Kovacs (Eds.), Wie funktioniert Bioethik. Mentis: Paderborn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, D. (1999). Animal ethics and animal welfare science: Bridging the two cultures. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 65(3), 171–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, (2011). Are dolphins too smart for captivity? Science Magazine, 332, 526–529.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruen, L. (2011). Ethics and animals: An introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gruzalski, B. (2008). Warum es falsch ist, Tiere zu essen, die zur Nahrungsgewinnung gezüchtet und geschlachtet wurden. In U. Wolf (Ed.), Texte zur Tierethik. Leipzig: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedgecoe, A. M. (2004). Critical bioethics: Beyond the social science critique of applied ethics. Bioethics, 18(2), 120–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herrera, C. (2008). Is it time for bioethics to go empirical? Bioethics, 22(3), 137–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joy, M. (2003). Psychic numbing and meat consumption: The psychology of carnism. Dissertation, Saybrook Graduate School and Research Centre, San Fransisco.

  • Kahane, G. (2013). The armchair and the trolley: an argument for experimental ethics. Philosophical Studies, 162(2), 421–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G., & Shackel, N. (2008). Do abnormal responses show utilitarian bias? Nature, 452(7185), E5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kavanagh, P. S., Signal, T. D., & Taylor, N. (2013). The Dark Triad and animal cruelty: Dark personalities, dark attitudes, and dark behaviors. Personality and Individual Differences, 55(6), 666–670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2011). The ethical project. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2003). Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis, 63(279), 190–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Nichols, S. (2007). An experimental philosophy manifesto. In J. Knobe & S. Nichols (Eds.), Experimental philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koknaroglu, H., & Akunal, T. (2013). Animal welfare: An animal science approach. Meat Science, 95(4), 821–827.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krones, T. (2009). Empirische Methodologien und Methoden der angewandten und der empirischen Ethik. Ethik in der Medizin, 21(3), 247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lafollette, H. (2011). Animal experimentation in biomedical research. In T. L. B. R. G. Frey (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of animal ethics (pp. 796–825). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, E. D., Mills, D. S., & Houpt, K. A. (2005). Attitudes of veterinary students at one US college toward factors relating to farm animal welfare. Journal of Veterinary Medical Education, 32(4), 481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loughnan, S., Haslam, N., & Bastian, B. (2010). The role of meat consumption in the denial of moral status and mind to meat animals. Appetite, 55(1), 156–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mason, G., & Latham, N. (2004). Can’t stop, won’t stop: is stereotypy a reliable animal welfare indicator? Animal Welfare-Potters Bar Then Wheathampstead, 13, S57–S70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Midgley, M. (1983). Animals and why they matter. Georgia: University of Georgia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mintline, E. M., Stewart, M., Rogers, A. R., Cox, N. R., Verkerk, G. A., Stookey, J. M., et al. (2013a). Play behavior as an indicator of animal welfare: Disbudding in dairy calves. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 144(1), 22–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mintline, E. M., Stewart, M., Rogers, A. R., Cox, N. R., Verkerk, G. A., Stookey, J. M., et al. (2013b). Play behavior as an indicator of animal welfare: Disbudding in dairy calves. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 144(1–2), 22–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2007). Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions. Nous, 41(4), 663–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, S. (2011). Vegetarianism. In T. Beauchamp & R. Frey (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of animal ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Regan, T. (1986). A case for animal rights. In M. W. F. L. D. Mickley (Ed.), Advances in animal welfare science (pp. 179–189). Washington, DC: The Humane Society of the United States.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, K. (2011). Concepts of animal welfare in relation to positions in animal ethics. Acta Biotheoretica, 59(2), 153–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, K. (2012). Naturalizing Ethics. EurSafe, 14(2), 2–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sebastian, M. (2014). In den Schlachthöfen der Welt. In H.-B. S. B. L. M. Diplomatique (Ed.), Fleischatlas 2014 (pp. 18–19). Daten und Fakten über Lebensmittel: Eigenverlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segner, H. (2012). Fish: Nociception and Pain: a Biological Perspective. Federal Office for Buildings and Logistics (FOBL).

  • Signal, T. D., & Taylor, N. (2006). Attitudes to animals: Demographics within a community sample. Society & Animals, 14(2), 147–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (2008). Tierversuche. In U. Wolf (Ed.), Texte zur Tierethik. Leipzig: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sulmasy, D. P., & Sugarman, J. (2001). The many methods of medical ethics (or, thirteen ways of looking at a blackbird.). Methods in Medical Ethics 3–18.

  • Sutton, G. A., Dahan, R., Turner, D., & Paltiel, O. (2013). A behaviour-based pain scale for horses with acute colic: Scale construction. Vet J, 196(3), 394–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2012). The two sources of moral standing. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(3), 303–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Temple, D., Manteca, X., Velarde, A., & Dalmau, A. (2011). Assessment of animal welfare through behavioural parameters in Iberian pigs in intensive and extensive conditions. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 131(1), 29–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, R. E., & Zárate, A. V. (2005). Der Begriff Wohlbefinden in der Nutztierhaltung-Diskussion aktueller Definitionsansätze als Grundlage für praxisorientierte Forschung am Beispiel Mastschweinehaltung. Archiv Tierzucht, Dummerstorf, 48(5), 475–489.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wild, M., & Willemsen, A. (2012). Fische: Kognition. Bundesamt für Bauten und Logistik BBL: Bewusstsein und Schmerz; eine philosophische Perspektive.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. O. (2012). On human nature. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. O., & Kellert, S. R. (1993). The biophilia hypothesis. Washington, DC: Island.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, U. (2008). Texte zur Tierethik. Leipzig: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Würbel, H. (2009). Ethology applied to animal ethics. Applied animal behaviour science, 118(3–4), 118–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

Kirsten Persson’s research is supported in part by the Haldimann Stiftung in Aarau, Switzerland. All other support for all authors came from the University of Basel.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kirsten Persson.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest

There is no conflict of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Persson, K., Shaw, D. Empirical Methods in Animal Ethics. J Agric Environ Ethics 28, 853–866 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-015-9560-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-015-9560-0

Keywords

Navigation