Skip to main content
Log in

But is it sociology of knowledge? Wilhelm Jerusalem’s “sociology of cognition” in context

  • Published:
Studies in East European Thought Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper considers the charge that—contrary to the current widespread assumption accompanying the near-universal neglect of his work—Wilhelm Jerusalem (1854–1923) cannot count as one of the founders of the sociology of (scientific) knowledge. In order to elucidate the matter, Jerusalem’s “sociology of cognition” is here reconstructed in the context of his own work in psychology and philosophy as well as in the context of the work of some predecessors and contemporaries. It is argued that while it shows clear discontinuities with the present-day understanding of the sociology of (scientific) knowledge, Jerusalem’s sociology of cognition was not only distinctive in its own day but also anticipated in nuce a much-discussed theme in current history of science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Fleck refers to Jerusalem (1924) and Jerusalem’s edition of Levy-Bruhl (1910[1922]) as sources for his quotations from all four; see Fleck (1935 [1980, 46–50]).

  2. See Scheler (1924a, 4) and compare his (1921).

  3. See Scheler (1926, vii) and compare his (1924b).

  4. For documentation of the debate see Lieber (1974) and Meja and Stehr (1980).

  5. See Mannheim (1925) and (1926).

  6. Stark (1967, 477) on Grünwald (1934).

  7. “Wilhelm Jerusalem, who in his sociological theories agrees with regard to many points with the French sociologists, especially with Durkheim und Lévy-Bruhl, has also developed a sociology of knowledge. His sociology of cognition (which he also designated as ‘sociological epistemology’) constitutes… a part of social psychology. It does not fall into the field of proper sociology and thus does not belong to the discipline that today is called sociology of knowledge. In particular, the concept of the ‘social factor’, which according to Jerusalem the cognition of an individual person depends on, is not identical with the concept of ‘Seinsverbundenheit’ (existential connection), thus with the concept that so indisputably stands at the centre of the current sociology of knowledge that one could define it as the ‘theory of the Seinsverbundenheit (existential connection) of human thought’.” (1934, 20; all translations from sources where no English version is given in the references are by the present author). After the first sentence quoted Grünwald refered to Jerusalem (1923, 286ff), (1909a), (1921) and (1924), after the last one quoted to Mannheim (1931).

  8. See Merton (1942).

  9. The two-page exception is Christian Fleck (1990, 47–48); no discussion in, e.g., Langer (1988).

  10. A prize competition, organised in 1931 by the Sociological and Philosophical Societies in Vienna with the topic “The development of the sociology of cognition and knowledge since Wilhelm Jerusalem” was concluded without any award, having prompted only four inadequate contributions (see Kantstudien 36 (1931) 364 and 38 (1933) 494). No report of the results of the follow-up competition with a changed topic but also focusing on Jerusalem and with a due date at the end of 1934 were published, Kantstudien having been radically gleichgeschaltet as of vol. 40 (1935).

  11. See Daston and Galison (2006).

  12. See Eckstein (1935) and the autobiographical Jerusalem (1922), part one of which was enlarged in (1925b). It may be added that being born a Jew in the multi-national empire of Austria-Hungary (in his case Bohemia), Jerusalem perfectly fits J. C. Nyíri’s profile for founders of the discipline of the sociology of knowledge (1989).

  13. Politically Jerusalem was no socialist and despite his concern for “just social policies” showed certain conservative tendencies; see, e.g., Jerusalem (1897a [1905a, 229–230]).

  14. See James (1907 [1908]) and Jerusalem (1908) and (1909b).

  15. See, e.g., Jerusalem (1909a [1925a, 140]) and (1921, vi–vii).

  16. See, e.g., Kusch (1995, 15) who otherwise considers Jerusalem for his role in the psychologism dispute, or Stadler (1997 [2001, 41) who otherwise locates him in the intellectual background for the emergence of the Vienna Circle.

  17. See Jerusalem (1909a) and Durkheim (1910).

  18. For the latter see Jerusalem (1899a, b, 177–178), (1905a, 213–244) and (1923, 358–365); cf. note 37 below.

  19. For the latter see his (1905b). Even in his later sociological phase he claimed: “Even the most universal propositions of logic and mathematics are regarded”—by the evolutionist in contrast to the apriorist thinker—“only as sedimentations, as condensations (Verdichtungen) of earlier experience. The evolutionist sees in these propositions the adaptation of thoughts to facts and to each other (Mach), he finds in these valuable measures from the point of the economy of thought.” (1909b, 809) For more on Verdichtungen see section “Jerusalem’s sociology of cognition” below.

  20. By contrast, in ontological matters Jerusalem was no naturalist. While Jerusalem subscribed to a conception of Geisteswissenschaft for which sociology was to provide the foundation (1926, 3–17), it is to be noted that he did not understand the distinction between Natur- and Geisteswissenschaften along Windelband’s and Rickert’s lines (1904 [1905a, 59–60]), but as conditioned by the dualism of mind and body (1923, 362–363).

  21. “Evolutionist philosophy is not science without presuppositions…. These presuppositions, however, are not the result of a critical theory of knowledge (Erkenntniskritik), but they are rather heuristic principles, which the results of empirical science made highly probable.” (1909b, 813) Husserl, his opponent in the psychologism dispute, was criticized for taking as essential structures of the mind what are but “associations that have become fixed and social solidifications (Verdichtungen), which are the result of the experiences and systematizing work of past generations” (1914 [1925a, 196]). Again, more on Verdichtungen in section “Jerusalem’s sociology of cognition” below.

  22. Unlike most current naturalists, however, Jerusalem shared with contemporaries of his like Mach and Brentano the conception now known as methodological solipsism, the idea that our knowledge of the world was built up from phenomenalistic building blocks.

  23. Jerusalem presented an interesting example of their continued usefulness at later stages: “In teaching, typical ideas have great significance. All maps, all schematic drawings, models, portraits produce typical ideas of great vivacity and enrich our knowledge much more effectively than could be done by descriptions or definitions.” (1902, 100).

  24. The first of these three elements, the separation of the root into subject and predicate, Jerusalem derived from Gerber (1884), as he himself noted repeatedly (1895, 34, 76–77), (1905b, 148–149), (1922, 19). More on this background in §9 below.

  25. See Jerusalem (1895, 78–180), (1899a, 77–80), (1902, 89–91), (1909a [1925, 142–143]), (1924, 190–191).

  26. Compare Peter Strawson’s proposal that our knowledge of causality develops from imaginative projections on our part: “In a great boulder rolling down the mountainside and flattening the hut in its path we see an exemplary instance of force; and perhaps, in so seeing it, we are in some barely coherent way identifying with the hut (if we are one kind of person) or with the boulder (if we are another): putting ourselves imaginatively in the place of one or the other.” (1985, 123).

  27. Jerusalem had high hopes for “modern ethnology”, namely to replace European enthnocentrism by a “healthy scientific cosmopolitianism” (1897a [1925a, 234])—even though he did not question but saw confirmed, by his theory of cognitive evolution, the widespread idea of a division between Natur- and Kulturvölker as propounded by Vierkandt (1886); see Jerusalem (1905b, 161). For some remarks on the problematical nature of this distinction, see Uebel (2003).

  28. “Religious ideas, mythological interpretations of the course of nature often emerge from the heads of single human beings. Yet they only gain historical significance if they are sustained by some community, become the common property of a clan, a tribe or a people. Once one adds that language too becomes capable of forming and transmitting thoughts only in this fashion, that it is social in its nature of connecting a group of people, then one becomes convinced that in the development of cognition too the social factor plays a role. It would be a task equally meritorious and difficult to characterize this social factor in its historical development.” (1897a [1905a, 238]).

  29. Literally meaning “thickening”, “increase of density” and “compression” in technical contexts and “condensation” in figurative contexts, the translators of Fleck who twice quoted the term from Jerusalem used “consolidation” (1935 [1979, 47, 172]), while the translators of Freud who also used the term used “condensation”; see Laplanche and Pontalis (1967 [1980, 83]).

  30. On Jerusalem’s very first use of Verdichtung in a review of Mach from 1897, see §8 below. For Mach’s “economy of science” see his (1883, Sect. 4.4), or 1872 [1910, 55, 88]) and (1910 [1992, 133–135]).

  31. His paper at the 1908 Heidelberg Congress shows that by then Jerusalem had begun to integrate the social dimension into his developmental psychology: “The biological universal of the typical idea and the economic universal of concept words are modified and condensed in ways hardly yet conceived of by the plain fact which may be neglected but not disputed, namely that the thought structures so formed are the products of common work, of the total experience of the tribe. They confront the individual as something supra-personal, he permanently remains subject to their suggestive effects and so grows unconsciously into the sociological universal which plays a role in building the self that cannot be considered too highly.” (1909b, 812, emphases added).

  32. Jerusalem (1909a [1925, 144–145]); nearly identical in (1923, 295) where the reference to atomic theory is dropped; briefer in (1924, 192) where the reader is referred to Mach’s works on the history of mechanics, the theory of heat and optics.

  33. Agreements in line with “morality and custom” are recognized to license behavioral responses to typical situations, but given Jerusalem’s interest in the present context they are not further discussed (1909a [1925a,150).

  34. In passing we note the potential tension in these passages with others (e.g., 1923, 98, quoted above) where the objective criterion does not altogether replace the intersubjective criterion but rather becomes the decisive one.

  35. That the periodic need for the revision of scientific “auxiliary” concepts played a central role on Mach’s historic-critical conception of science was noted explicitly by Jerusalem, but also independently by Frank (1917). Jerusalem here also credited Mach with the recognition that certain scientific principles (like that of the conservation of energy) are “pre-formed in instinctual, that is wholly socially determined thinking.”

  36. See Jerusalem (1910 [1925a, 158]) and (1925b, 32–33]).

  37. That Jerusalem went further on this basis to develop and recommend the idea of humanity as an aspirational ethical ideal and telos of history, may be noted but cannot be pursued here. See Jerusalem (1923, 328–330, 350–351) and (1924, 204–206).

  38. The term Verdichtung does not, however, appear in Section 4.4 of Mach (1882), which is dedicated to the same topic, the economy of science, though the process and result designated by it is very well described there.

  39. Precisely in this sense it was also employed, for instance, by Friedrich Adler in his German translation of Duhem’s La théorie physique, son object et sa structure when the latter speaks, with reference to Mach, of the “doubling” of the economy of thought first afforded by the replacement of individual facts by laws, namely by “laws being condensed in theories” (Duhem 1906 [1908/1978, 24]).

  40. In his translation of James’s Pragmatism, Jerusalem used the term “verdichtet” for “funded” as in “funded truths” and “experience funded” (1907 [1908/1994, 142, 148, 170]).

  41. For further uses by Simmel of Verdichtung, see (1892a [1989, 28–29]), assigning to it the job of solidifying morals in customs, and (1892b [1989, 318]), implicating it in the empathetic understanding of other minds. Köhnke (1996, 346–348) points to a use which denotes the Verdichtung of intuitive ideas in abstract concepts.

  42. See Köhnke (1990) and (2005a). The characterisation of Völkerpsychologie given here—which restores it against much misrepresentation of varying sorts—is his.

  43. See Mach (1910); on Herrmann, see Haller (1986).

  44. For thoughts on why Dilthey and Simmel, among others may have failed to mention Lazarus, see Köhnke (2005a). One of these is unlikely to apply in the case of Jerusalem. Not only was he, like Lazarus und Steinthal, Jewish himself but his Nachruf for Steinthal made a point of recounting his lectures to the Hochschule für die Wissenschaft vom Judentum (Academy for Jewish Studies) in Berlin (cofounded by Lazarus) and compared him to Lessing’s Nathan the Wise (1899b [1905a, 210–211]).

  45. See Jerusalem (1895, 150). Jerusalem once compared Lazarus to Steinthal as possessing the greater “gift of subtle psychological analysis” and referred to his Das Leben der Seele, Band 2: Geist und Sprache in support (1899b [1905a, 207]). That, of course is just the book in which Lazarus had first formulated the ideas of his later paper on Verdichtung published in 1862: Eckstein (1935, 90) identified Jerusalem’s mention (at 1895, 150) of Lazarus’s origination of the term as pointing to Lazarus (1856–1857, vol. II, 160).

  46. See §4 above. Elsewhere he also criticized Vaihinger for adopting “the mechanics of mental life introduced by Herbart and developed by Steinthal” that unduly postulates wholly separate elements unable to merge with each other (1912 [1925a, 179–180]). Jerusalem also rejected Herbart’s principle— endorsed by Lazarus and Steinthal (1851 [2005, 22])—of the “limitation of the human mind” (Enge des Geistes) and instead accepted Wundt’s “law of the growth of mental energy or the new creation of mental powers,” interpreting the creation of new tools of thought as the “enlargement of mental powers” (1897b [1905a, 173]).

  47. “Nothing is more ridiculous than the attempt to explain the mind of an educated person in terms of his inborn mental powers. Even so, just about everything that’s been said about reason in recent times has to be classed as such patent foolishness.” Herbart (1815 [1821/1993, 318]).

  48. See Köhnke (2005b, 248 n. 440).

  49. Note that, by contrast, Jerusalem criticized Wilhelm Wundt’s later version of Völkerpsychologie not only as still much too individualist but also stated that—unlike with Lazarus and Steinthal—he “missed the constant attention to the social nature of language” (1905c, 281).

  50. See Köhnke (2005a, xl and xxxi).

  51. Of course, Lazarus too employed Wechselwirkung to describe the interaction of individuals in society but not as explicitly as Simmel as constituting both individuals and society. See, e.g., Simmel (1890 [1989, 129–131]), a section summarised elsewhere as: “The unity of society as the reciprocal action of its parts. The condensation of this reciprocal action into objective structures.” (Ibid., 111).

  52. To be sure, Simmel’s project of a sociology of culture in its most general sense is a much richer sociology than Jerusalem’s more anthropological account which, as we saw, mostly leaves off where more modern sociologies of knowledge start, but even the latter pale in comparison with the range of Simmel’s enterprise.

  53. “Only once humans emerge from the herd, once they become individuals, do they begin to create more precise instruments of thought. … In this the most significant alteration in the nature of man is due to the social differentiation by the ever increasing division of labour.” (1909a [1925a, 146]) In his Preface to his edition of Lévy-Bruhl he wrote, referring to the period before Durkheim had reviewed his 1909 paper: “I had already become familiar with the works of the French school of sociologists led by Durkheim and recognized how closely their point of view was related to mine. It was especially the works of Hubert, of Mauss, and those by Durkheim himself, which provided me with rich instruction and stimulation.” (1921, v) This suggests (as does a passage in 1924, 184) that he had been aware of Durkheim and Mauss (1903) for some time though it does not indicate since when exactly. But Jerusalem did not have an infallible grasp of the details of the Durkheim school: Lévy-Bruhl was not a student of Durkheim’s, contrary to Jerusalem’s assertion (1924, 186).

  54. See Durkheim (1898). Although they play a large role there, collective representations do not appear as such in central passages of Durkheim and Mauss (1903)—though “states of the collective mind” do (ibid., 85)—but they do so in Durkheim (1912 [1915, 16, 436–438]).

  55. Significantly, Jerusalem speaks of the typical ideas of early man as “collective representations” only in (1924, 187–188), but not in (1909a). However, that Jerusalem earlier picked up on the Durkheimian idea of collective representations is suggested by his mention of not only Mauss but also Hubert in his recollection (1921a, v). Henri Hubert and Mauss had published “certain seminal observations on time and space which are direct precursors of the [Durkheim-Mauss] essay on classification (Année sociologique, vol. V, 1902, p. 248)” (Needham 1963, xxix–xxx).

  56. See Durkheim and Mauss (1903 [1963, 85)) and Durkheim (1912 [1915, 440)). That Durkheim’s explanation fails is widely acknowledged; see, e.g., Needham (1963) or Bloor (1982), and not that Schmaus’s critique of Bloor’s interpretation of Durkheim does not dispute this point (1994, 66, 259–260; cf. his 2000).

  57. Pickering (2000a, b, 16) also noted the novelty of the first of these points in Durkheim (1912).

  58. Prior to more recent post-Mertonians only Fleck spent much time on the shaping of the perceptual sensibilities of experimental scientists. This marks him out in the classical period of the discipline and links him by anticipation to Kuhn’s idea of the central role exemplary problem solutions in the socialization of scientists and by continuation to Jerusalem’s notion of Verdichtung as a process creative of shared typical ideas and concepts. (For Fleck’s own adoption of Jerusalem’s conception of Verdichtung in his own account, see his (1935 [1980, 37]) where the term is rendered as social reinforcement).

  59. Philipp Frank and Otto Neurath set out to explore how Duhem’s underdetermination of theory by evidence—a phenomenon not taken account of by Jerusalem—allowed social factors to play a role in the acceptance of theories; see Uebel (2000). Neurath’s distinctive addition to this consisted in placing testimony in a central place for the epistemology of science; see Uebel (2009).

References

  • Bloor, D. (1982). Durkheim and Mauss revisited: Classification and the sociology of knowledge. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 13, 267–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daston, L., & Galison, P. (2006). Objectivity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1906). La théorie physique, son objet et sa structure. Paris. Trans. Ziel und Struktur der physikalischen Theorien, Leipzig: Barth, 1908. Repr. Hamburg: Meiner, 1978.

  • Durkheim, E. (1898). Représentations individuelles et représentations collectives. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, 6, 273–302. Trans. Individual and collective representations in Durkheim, Sociology and Philosophy (ed. by D. F. Pollock), London: Cohen and West, 1953.

  • Durkheim, E. (1910). [Review] Wilhelm Jerusalem, ‘Soziologie des Erkennens’. L’année sociologique, 11, 42–45. Trans. in Durkheim, Contributions to L’Année Sociologique (ed. by Y. Nandan), New York: Free Press, 1980, pp. 107–110.

  • Durkheim, E. (1912). Les formes élémentaires de la vie religieuse. Paris. Trans. The elementary forms of the religious life. London: Allen and Unwin. 1915. Repr. 1964.

  • Durkheim, E., & Mauss, M. (1903). De quelques formes primitives de classification: contributions à l’étude des représentations collectives. L’Année Sociologique, 6, 1–72. Trans. Primitive classification (ed. by R. Needham), London: Cohen and West, 1963.

  • Eckstein, W. (1935). Wilhelm Jerusalem. Sein Leben und Wirken. Vienna: Verlag von Carl Gerold’s Sohn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleck, L. (1935). Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache. Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv. Basel: Schwabe & Co. Repr. (ed. by L. Schäfer and T. Schnelle 1980) Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp,. Trans. Genesis and development of a scientific fact (ed. by T. J. Trenn and R. K.Merton), Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979.

  • Fleck, Ch. (1990). Rund um ‘Marienthal’. Von den Anfängen der Soziologie in Österreich bis zu ihrer Vertreibung. Vienna: Verlag für Gesellschafstkritik.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, Ph. (1917). Die Bedeutung der physikalischen Erkenntnistheorie Ernst Machs für das Geisteslebens unserer Zeit. Die Naturwissenschaften, 5. Trans. The importance for our times of Ernst Mach’s Philosophy of Science in Frank (1949), Modern Science and its Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 61–79.

  • Gerber, G. (1884). Die Sprache und das Erkennen. Berlin: Gaertner. Exerpts repr. in S. J. Schmidt 1971 (ed.), Philosophie als Sprachkritik im 19. Jahrhundert. Textauswahl II. Stuttgart: Fromann, pp. 19–60.

  • Grünwald, E. (1934). Das Problem der Soziologie des Wissens (ed. by Walther Eckstein) Wien: Braumüller.

  • Haller, R. (1986). Emmanuel Hermann. In W. Grassl & B. Smith (Eds.), Austrian economics: Historical and philosophical background. London: Croom Helm.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herbart, J. (1815). Lehrbuch zur Einführung in die Philosophie. 2nd ed. 1821. 4th ed. 1837. Repr. Hamburg: Meiner, 1993.

  • James,W. (1907). Pragmatism. A new name for some old ways of thinking. London: Longmans, Green & Co. Trans. Pragmatismus. Ein neuer Name für alte Denkmethoden. Leipzig: Klinkhardt, 1908.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1888). Lehrbuch der psychologie. Wien: Braumüller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jerusalem, W. (1890). Laura Bridgman. Erziehung einer Taubstumm-Blinden, Eine psychologische Studie. Vienna: Braumüller, 2nd ed. 1891.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1895). Die Urtheilsfunction. Eine psychologische und erkenntniskritische Untersuchung. Wien: Braumüller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jerusalem, W. (1897a). Die Volksseele. Neue Freie Presse, 8–9 January, Vienna. Repr. in Jerusalem 1905a, pp. 224–241.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1897b). Wilhelm Wundts Philosophie. Neue Freie Presse 21–22 August, Vienna. Repr. in Jerusalem 1905a, pp. 164–184.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1897c). Ernst Machs ‘Populärwissenschaftliche Vorlesungen’. Neue Freie Presse 27 August, Vienna. Repr. in Jerusalem 1905a, pp 185–193.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1899a). Einleitung in die Philosophie. Wien: Braumüller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jerusalem, W. (1899b). H. Steinthal. Neue Freie Presse, 8 April, Vienna. Repr. in Jerusalem 1905a, pp. 203–211.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1900). Ernst Machs ‘Analyse der Empfindungen’. Neue Freie Presse 5 August, Vienna. Repr. in Jerusalem 1905a, pp. 194–205.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1902). Lehrbuch der Psychologie. Wien: Braumüller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jerusalem, W. (1904). Kants Bedeutung für die Gegenwart. Vienna: Braumüller. Repr. in Jerusalem 1905a, pp. 36–63.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1905a). Gedanken und Denker. Wien: Braumüller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jerusalem, W. (1905b). Der kritische Idealismus und die reine Logik. Ein Ruf im Streite. Vienna: Braumüller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jerusalem, W. (1905c). Anmerkungen. In Jerusalem 1905a, pp. 279–284.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1908a). Der Pragmatismus, Deutsche Literaturzeitung 25 January 1908, Repr. in Jerusalem 1925a, pp. 130–139.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1908b). Philosophenkongress in Heidelberg. Die Zukunft 10 October, pp. 55–61.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1909a). Soziologie des Erkennens, Die Zukunft 15 May 1909, 236ff. Repr. in Jerusalem 1925a, pp. 140–153.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1909b). Apriorismus und Evolutionismus. In Th. Elsenhans (Ed.), Bericht über den III. Internationalen Kongress für Philosophie zu Heidelberg, 1. bis 5. September 1908 (pp. 806–815), Heidelberg: Carl Winter.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1910). William James. Die Zukunft, 5 November. Repr. in Jerusalem 1925, pp. 154–159.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1912). Die Logik des Unlogischen. Die Zukunft, 25 May. Repr. in Jerusalem 1925, pp. 173–186.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1914). Psychologen und Philosophen. Die Zukunft 18 July. Repr. in Jerusalem 1925, pp. 187–200.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1916). Ernst Mach. Die Zukunft, 24 June. Repr. Jerusalem 1925, pp. 202–211.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1921). Vorbemerkungen des Herausgebers. In Lévy-Bruhl 1910 (1921, pp. v–xvii).

  • Jerusalem, W. (1922). Meine Wege und Ziele. In R. Schmidt (Ed.), Die Philosophie der Gegenwart in Selbstdarstellungen (pp. 53–98). Leipzig: Meiner.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1923). Einleitung in die Philosophie (10th ed.). Wien: Braumüller.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1924). Die soziologische Bedingtheit des Denkens und der Denkformen. In Scheler 1924, pp. 182–207. Repr. in Meja and Stehr 1982, p. 27.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1925a). Gedanken und Denker. Gesammelte Aufsätze. Neue Folge. Vienna: Braumüller.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1925b). Meine Wege und Ziele. In Jerusalem 1925a, pp. 1–35.

  • Jerusalem, W. (1926). Einführung in die Soziologie (ed. by W. Eckstein) Wien: Braumüler.

  • Köhnke, K. Ch. (1990). Four concepts of social science at Berlin University: Dilthey, Lazarus, Schmoller and Simmel. In M. Kaern, B. S. Phillips, & R. S. Cohen (Eds.), Georg Simmel and contemporary sociology (pp. 99–107). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Köhnke, K. Ch. (1996). Der junge Simmel in Theoriebeziehungen und sozialen Bewegungen. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt a.M.

    Google Scholar 

  • Köhnke, K.Ch. (2005a). Einleitung des Herausgebers. In Lazarus 2005, pp. ix–xxxvii.

  • Köhnke, K. Ch. (2005b). Anmerkungen des Herausgebers. In Lazarus 2005, pp. 243–274.

  • Kusch, M. (1995). Psychologism. A case study in the sociology of philosophical knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langer, J. (Ed.). (1988). Geschichte der österreichischen Soziologie. Konstituierung, Entwicklung und europäische Bezüge. Vienna: Verlag für Gesellschaftskritik.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laplanche, J., & Pontalis, J. B. (1967). Vocabulaire de la Psychoanalyse. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Trans. The Language of Psychoanalysis, London: Hogarth Press, 1980.

  • Lazarus, M. (1856–1857). Das Leben der Seele in Monographien über seine Erscheinungen und Gesetze (2 Vols.). Berlin: Schindler, 2nd ed., 1876–1878, 3rd ed., 1883–1885.

  • Lazarus, M. (1862). Verdichtung des Denkens in der Geschichte. Ein Fragment. Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft, 2, 54–62. Repr. in Lazarus 2005, pp. 27–38.

  • Lazarus, M. (2005). Grundzüge der Völkerpsychologie und Kulturwissenschaft (ed. by K. Ch. Köhnke). Hamburg: Meiner.

  • Lazarus, M., & Steinthal, H. (1860). Einleitende Gedanken über Völkerspychologie, als Einladung zu einer Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft. Zeitschrift für Völkerpsychologie und Sprachwissenschaft, 1, 1–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévy-Bruhl, L. (1910). Les fonctions mentales dans les sociétés inférieures. Paris. Trans. Das Denken der Naturvölker. Wien: Braumüller, 1921, 2nd ed. 1926, How Natives Think. London: Allen and Unwin, 1926.

  • Lieber, H.-J. (Ed.). (1974). Ideologienlehre und Wissensoziologie. Die Diskussion um das Ideologieproblem in den zwanziger Jahren. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach, E. (1872). Die Geschichte und die Wurzel des Satzes von der Erhaltung der Arbeit, Prague, 2nd ed. Leipzig: Barth, 1909. Trans. History and root of the principle of the conservation of energy, Chicago: Open Court, 1910.

  • Mach, E. (1883). Die Mechanik in ihrer Entwicklung historisch-kritisch dargestellt. Leipzig: Brockhaus. 9th ed. trans. The science of mechanics, La Salle: Open Court, 1960.

  • Mach, E. (1893). The economical nature of physical inquiry. In Mach, Popular scientific lectures, La Salle: Open Court, pb. of 5th ed. 1986, pp. 186–213.

  • Mach, E. (1905). Erkenntnis und Irrtum. Leipzig: Barth. 2nd ed. 1906. Trans. Knowledge and Error, Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1976.

  • Mach, E. (1910). Die Leitgedanken meiner naturwissenschaftlichen Erkenntnislehre und ihre Aufnahme durch die Zeitgenossen. Scientia 7, 2ff. and Physikalische Zeitschrift 11, pp. 599–606. Trans. The leading thoughts of my scientific epistemology and its acceptance by contemporaries. In J. Blackmore (Ed.), Ernst MachA deeper look. Documents and new perspectives. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992, pp. 133–140.

  • Mannheim, K. (1925). Das Problem einer Soziologie des Wissens. Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik 53, 577–532. Repr. Lieber 1974, pp. 170–248. Trans. The problem of a sociology of knowledge in Mannheim 1952, pp. 134–190.

  • Mannheim, K. (1926). Ideologische und soziologische Interpretation der geistigen Gebilde. Jahrbuch für Soziologie, 2, 424–440. Repr. in Lieber 1974, pp. 249–268 and Meja and Stehr 1980, pp. 213–231.

  • Mannheim, K. (1929). Ideologie und Utopie. Bonn: Cohen. Trans. as Parts 2-4 of Mannheim 1936b, pp. 49–236.

  • Mannheim, K. (1931). Wissensoziologie. In Alfred Vierkandt (Ed.), Handwörterbuch der Soziologie, Stuttgart: Enke. Trans. Part V: The sociology of knowledge in Mannheim 1936, pp. 237–280.

  • Mannheim, K. (1936). Ideology and Utopia. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meja, V., & Stehr, N. (Eds.). (1980). Der Streit um die Wissenssoziologie. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt a.M.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. (1942). Science and technology in a democratic order. Journal of Legal and Political Sociology, 1, 115–126. Repr. as The Normative Structure of Science in Merton. The sociology of science. Theoretical and empirical investigations (ed. by N. W. Storer), Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973, pp. 267–278.

  • Needham, R. (1963). Introduction. In Durkheim and Mauss 1903 (1963, pp. vii–xlviii).

  • Nyíri, J. Ch. (1989). Collective reason: Roots of a sociological theory of knowledge. In W. Gombocz et al. (Eds.), Traditionen und Perspektiven der analytischen Philosophie. Festschrift für Rudolf Haller (pp. 600–618). Vienna: Holder-Pichler-Tempsky. Repr. in Nyíri, Tradition and Individuality. Kluwer: Dordrecht, 1992, pp. 25–38.

  • Pickering, W. S. F. (2000a). Representation as understood by Durkheim. In Pickering 2000b, pp. 11–24.

  • Pickering, W. S. F. (Ed.). (2000b). Durkheim and representations. London: Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. (1921). Die positivistische Geschichtsphilosophie des Wissens und die Aufgaben einer Soziologie der Erkenntnis. Kölner Viertelsjahreshefte für Sozialwissenschaften, 1, 22–31. Repr. in Meja and Stehr 1982, pp. 57–67.

  • Scheler, M. (Ed.). (1924a). Versuche zu einer Soziologie des Wissens. Munich: Duncker and Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. (1924b). Probleme einer Soziologie des Wissens. In Scheler 1924a, pp. 1–147. Excerpts repr. in Lieber 1974, pp. 129–169. Enlarged in Scheler 1926, pp. 1–231.

  • Scheler, M. (1926). Die Wissensformen und die Gesellschaft. Leipzig: Der-Neue-Geist Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmaus, W. (1994). Durkheim’s philosophy of science and the sociology of knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmaus, W. (2000). Meaning and representation in the social sciences. In Pickering 2000b, pp. 139–156.

  • Simmel, G. (1890). Über sociale Differenzierung. Sociologische und psychologische Untersuchungen. Leipzig: Duncker and Humblot. Repr. in Simmel 1989, pp. 109–296.

  • Simmel, G. (1892a). Einleitung in die Moralwissenschaft. Eine Kritik der ethischen Grundbegriffe, 2 Vols. Stuttgart: Cotta. Repr. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1989.

  • Simmel, G. (1892b). Probleme der Geschichtsphilosophie. Eine erkenntnistheoretische Studie. Leipzig: Duncker and Humblot, 3rd rev. ed. 1907, 1st ed. Repr. in Simmel 1989, pp. 297–421.

  • Simmel, G. (1898). Die Selbsterhaltung der socialen Gruppe. Sociologische Studie. Jahrbuch für Gesetzgebung, Verwaltung und Rechtspflege des Deutschen Reiches, 22, 589–640. Repr. in Simmel, Aufsätze und Abhandlungen, 18941900 (ed. by H.-J. Dahme and D. P. Frisby), Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1992, pp. 311–372.

  • Simmel, G. (1908). Soziologie. Untersuchungen über die Formen der Vergesellschaftung. Leipzig: Duncker and Humblot. Repr. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1992.

  • Simmel, G. (1989). Aufsätze 18871890. Über sociale Differenzierung. Die Probleme der Geschichtsphilosophie (ed. by H.-J. Dahme). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

  • Simmerl, G. (1920). Grundfragen der Soziologie (2nd ed.). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stark, W. (1967). “Sociology of Knowledge”. In P. Edwards (Ed.), Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Vol. 7, pp. 475–478). New York: Macmillan and Free Press.

  • Strawson, P. (1995). Causation and explanation. In B. Vermaezen & M. B. Hintikka (Eds.), Essays on Davidson: Actions and events (pp. 115–135). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, T. (2000). Logical empiricism and the sociology of knowledge: The case of Neurath and frank. Philosophy of Science, 67, S138–S150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, T. (2003). History of philosophy of science and the politics of race and ethnic exclusion. In M. Heidelberger & F. Stadler (Eds.), Wissenschaftsphilosophie und Politik/Philosophy of science and politics (pp. 91–118). Vienna: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, T. (2009). Neurath’s protocol statements revisited: Sketch of a theory of scientific testimony. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 40, 4–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vaihinger, H. (1911). Die Philosophie des Als-Ob. Leipzig. Excerpts of 6th ed. trans. The Philosophy of As-If, London, 1936.

  • Vierkandt, A. (1886). Naturvölker und Kulturvölker. Ein Beitrag zur Sozialpsychologie. Leipzig: Duncker and Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank Tamas Demeter for his invitation to contribute to this special issue and an anonymous reviewer for thoughtful and constructive criticism.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Uebel.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Uebel, T. But is it sociology of knowledge? Wilhelm Jerusalem’s “sociology of cognition” in context. Stud East Eur Thought 64, 5–37 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11212-012-9156-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11212-012-9156-4

Keywords

Navigation