Skip to main content
Log in

Discounting axioms imply risk neutrality

  • Published:
Annals of Operations Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Although most applications of discounting occur in risky settings, the best-known axiomatic justifications are deterministic. This paper provides an axiomatic rationale for discounting in a stochastic framework. Consider a representation of time and risk preferences with a binary relation on a real vector space of vector-valued discrete-time stochastic processes on a probability space. Four axioms imply that there are unique discount factors such that preferences among stochastic processes correspond to preferences among present value random vectors. The familiar axioms are weak ordering, continuity and nontriviality. The fourth axiom, decomposition, is non-standard and key. These axioms and the converse of decomposition are assumed in previous axiomatic justifications for discounting with nonlinear intraperiod utility functions in deterministic frameworks. Thus, the results here provide the weakest known sufficient conditions for discounting in deterministic or stochastic settings. In addition to the four axioms, if there exists a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function corresponding to the binary relation, then that function is risk neutral (i.e., affine). In this sense, discounting axioms imply risk neutrality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Alexander, J. C., & Sobel, M. J. Risk neutrality and ordered vector spaces. Social Science Research Network (2006). http://ssrn.com/abstract=896201

  • Altug, S., & Labadie, P. (1994). Dynamic choice and asset markets. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amaral, P. S., & Quintin, E. (2010). Limited enforcement, financial intermediation, and economic development: a quantitative assessment. International Economic Review, 51, 785–811.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J., Karlin, S., & Scarf, H. (1962). Studies in the mathematical theory of inventory and production. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balcer, Y., & Lippman, S. A. (1984). Technology expectations and adoption of improved technology. Journal of Economic Theory, 34, 292–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackorby, C., Primont, D., & Russell, R. R. (1978). Duality, separability, and functional structure: theory and economic applications. New York: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackorby, C., Primont, D., & Russell, R. R. (1998). Separability: A survey. In S. Barbera, P. J. Hammond, & C. Seidl (Eds.), Handbook of utility theory: Vol. 1. Principles. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackwell, D. (1962). Discrete dynamic programming. Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 33, 719–726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackwell, D. (1965). Discounted dynamic programming. Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 36, 226–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair, C. E. (1984). Axioms and examples related to ordinal dynamic programming. Mathematics of Operations Research, 8, 345–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cochrane, J. H. (2000). Asset pricing. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Denardo, E. V. (1967). Contraction mappings in the theory underlying dynamic programming. SIAM Review, 9, 165–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Derman, C. (1962). On sequential decisions and Markov chains. Management Science, 9, 16–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Derman, C. (1970). Finite state Markovian decision processes. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derman, C., & Katehakis, M.N. (1986). Computing optimal sequential allocation rules in clinical trials. In J. Van Ryzin (Ed.), Adaptive statistical procedures and related topics, Lecture notes-monograph series (Vol. 8). Hayward: Institute of Mathematical Statistics

    Google Scholar 

  • Duffie, D. (2001). Dynamic asset pricing theory (3rd ed.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyer, J. S., & Sarin, R. (1979). Measureable multiattribute value functions. Operational Research, 27, 810–822.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L. G. (1983). Stationary cardinal utility and optimal growth under uncertainty. Journal of Economic Theory, 31, 133–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farquhar, P. H. (1977). A survey of multiattribute utility theory and applications. In M. K. Starr & M. Zeleny (Eds.), Multiple criteria decision making (pp. 59–89). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, E., & Schwartz, A. (1994). Markov decision models with weighted discounted criteria. Mathematics of Operations Research, 19, 152–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C. (1970). Utility theory for decision making. Huntington: Krieger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C. (1978). A survey of multiattribute/multicriterion evaluation theories. In S. Zionts (Ed.), Multiple criteria problem solving (pp. 181–224). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C., & Rubinstein, A. (1982). Time preference. International Economic Review, 23, 677–694.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, S., Loewenstein, G., & O’Donoghue, T. (2002). Time discounting and time preference: a critical review. Journal of Economic Literature, 40, 351–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Furukawa, N. (1980). Characterization of optimal policies in vector-valued Markovian decision processes. Mathematics of Operations Research, 5, 271–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausner, M. (1954). Multidimensional utilities. In R. M. Thrall, C. H. Coombs, & R. L. Davis (Eds.), Decision processes (pp. 167–180). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausner, M., & Wendel, J. G. (1952). Ordered vector spaces. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 3, 977–982.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henig, M. I. (1983). Vector-valued dynamic programming. SIAM Journal on Control and Optimization, 21, 490–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ho, T. S. Y., & Lee, S.-B. (1986). Term structure movements and pricing interest rate contingent claims. The Journal of Finance, XLI, 1011–1029.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, T. H., & Donaldson, J. B. (1985). The structure of intertemporal preferences under uncertainty and time consistent plans. Econometrica, 53, 1451–1458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, L. E., & Schoonbroodt, A. (2010). Complements versus substitutes and trends in fertility choice in dynamic models. International Economic Review, 51, 671–699.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jorgenson, D. W., McCall, J. J., & Radner, R. (1967). Optimal replacement policy. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keeney, R. L., & Raiffa, H. (1976). Decisions with multiple objectives. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T. C. (1960). Stationary ordinal utility and impatience. Econometrica, 28, 287–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T. C., Diamond, P. A., & Williamson, R. E. (1964). Stationary utility and time perspective. Econometrica, 32, 82–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T. C. (1972). Representation of preference orderings over time. In C. B. McGuire & R. Radner (Eds.), Decisions and organizations. Amsterdam: North-Holland. Chap. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D. M., & Porteus, E. L. (1979). Temporal von Neumann-Morgenstern and induced preferences. Journal of Economic Theory, 20, 81–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lancaster, K. J. (1963). An axiomatic theory of consumer time preference. International Economic Review, 4, 221–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Linnemann, L., & Schabert, A. (2010). Debt nonneutrality, policy interactions, and macroeconomic stability. International Economic Review, 51, 461–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machina, M. J. (1989). Dynamic consistency and non-expected utility models of choice. Journal of Economic Literature, 27, 1622–1668.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magill, M., & Quinzii, M. (2010). A comoment criterion for the choice of risky investment by firms. International Economic Review, 51, 723–744.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrattan, E. R., & Ohanian, L. E. (2010). Does neoclassical theory account for the effects of big fiscal shocks? Evidence from World War II. International Economic Review, 51, 509–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNamara, J. M. (1990). The policy which maximises long-term survival of an animal faced with the risks of starvation and predation. Advances in Applied Probability, 22, 295–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mendelssohn, R. (1979). Using Markov decision models for purposes other than simple optimization: analyzing the consequences of policy alternatives on the management of salmon runs. Fisheries Bulletin, 78, 35–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, R. F. (1976). Preferences over time. In R. L. Keeney & H. Raiffa (Eds.), Decisions with multiple objectives: preferences and value tradeoffs. New York: Wiley. Chap. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miyamoto, J. M., & Wakker, P. (1996). Multiattribute utility theory without expected utility foundations. Operational Research, 44, 313–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monahan, G. E. P. (1983). Optimal advertising with stochastic demand. Management Science, 29, 106–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moriarity, S., & Allen, C. P. (1984). Cost accounting. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, F. H., Toman, M. A., & Weiss, H. J. (1989). A dynamic Nash game model of oil market disruptions and strategic stockpiling. Operational Research, 37, 958–971.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, R. (1987). Personal communication. Stony Brook, NY.

  • Samuelson, P. A. (1937). A note on measurement of utility. Review of Economic Studies, 4, 155–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sethi, S. P. (1998). Optimal consumption-investment decisions allowing for bankruptcy: A survey. In W. T. Ziemba & J. M. Mulvey (Eds.), Worldwide asset and liability modeling. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapley, L. S. (1953). Stochastic games. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 39, 1095–1100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sharpe, W. F. (1985). Investments (3rd ed.). Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shefrin, H. (1998). Changing utility functions. In S. Babera, P. J. Hammond, & C. Seidl (Eds.), Handbook of utility theory: Vol. 1. Principles (pp. 569–626). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shubik, M. (1970). Game theory, behavior and the paradox of the prisoner’s dilemma: Three solutions. The Journal of Conflict Resolution, 14, 181–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shubik, M., & Sobel, M. J. (1992). On matching book: A problem in banking and corporate finance. Management Science, 8, 827–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, M. J. (1975). Ordinal dynamic programming. Management Science, 21, 967–975.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, M. J. (1980). Ordinal sequential games. Economies Et Sociétés, XIV, 1571–1582.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, M. J. (2010). Time, risk, and Trojan horse preferences. In J. J. Hasenbein (Ed.), Risk and optimization in an uncertain world: tutorials in operations research, 2010 (pp. 99–115). Hanover: Institute for Operations Research and the Management Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Ploeg, F. (2010). Voracious transformations of a common natural resource into productive capital. International Economic Review, 51, 365–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1944). Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (2nd ed. 1947).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. P. (1993). Additive representations on rank-ordered sets II. The topological approach. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 22, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weibull, J. W. (1985). Discounted-value representations of temporal preferences. Mathematics of Operations Research, 10, 244–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, D. J. (1988). Mean, variance, and probabilistic criteria in finite Markov decision processes: A review. Journal of Optimization Theory and Applications, 56, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittle, P. C. (1990). Risk-sensitive optimal control. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, A. C., & Nassar, J. I. (1966). Financial measurement of capital investments. Management Science, 12, 851–864.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yeh, W. W.-G. (1985). Reservoir management and operations models: A state-of-the-art review. Water Resources Research, 21, 1797–1818.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I was fortunate to have been a student at Columbia University. In Columbia College my advisor was George E. Kimball, an operations research pioneer for whom the Kimball Medal of INFORMS is named, and a prominent theoretical chemist. The mathematics teachers who influenced me were Samuel Eilenberg, Bernard O. Koopman (after whom the Koopman Prize of the Military Applications section of INFORMS is named), and Serge Lange. Cyrus Derman was my icon of an academician then and he remained one for more than fifty years.

Even to a twenty-year old student it was obvious that Professor Derman’s papers would have enduring importance. His interests were broad, he was intense but fair-minded, he had a passion for chamber music (he could have attended Curtis Institute as a violinist), and he was an enthusiastic tennis player and skier. In his courses I first encountered linear programming, stochastic processes, and his student and graduate assistant, Arthur F. Veinott, Jr., who was a major influence on me a few years later at Stanford University. Professor Derman encouraged my fascination with Markov decision processes, he supervised my master’s essay, and more than fifty years later I still benefit from his tutelage.

I valued Professor Robert Rosenthal’s friendship highly, and his penetrating questions (Rosenthal 1987) led to Sect. 5. He died in 2002.

I am grateful to Professor James C. Alexander for comments and the argument on which the proof of Lemma 3(a) is based, to Professors Eugene Feinberg and Charu Sinha for comments, and to an anonymous commentator on a precursor of this paper who noted that confining Y to 0 in (A3) permitted a counterexample.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew J. Sobel.

Additional information

In memory of Professors Cyrus Derman and Robert Rosenthal.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Sobel, M.J. Discounting axioms imply risk neutrality. Ann Oper Res 208, 417–432 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10479-012-1066-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10479-012-1066-9

Keywords

Navigation