Skip to main content
Log in

Some conceptual issues in the transition from chemistry to biology

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The transition from chemistry to biology is an extremely complex issue because of the huge phenomenological differences between the two domains and because this transition has many different aspects and dimensions. In this paper, I will try to analyze how chemical systems have developed a cohesive, self-maintaining and functionally differentiated system that recruits its organization to stay far from equilibrium. This organization cannot exist but in an individualized form, and yet, it unfolds both a diachronic-historical and a synchronic collective dimension. I will argue that, far from being a problem, these different dimensions of the phenomenon of life, appear as a consequence of the nature of this individualized organization.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I will not discuss here the problem of whether life could or should be defined for developing a useful research program in the Origin of Life domain. First, because in this paper I will only try to explain the emergence of certain (in my view, fundamental) properties of life as we know it in our planet; and second, because I am just focusing only in the earlier steps of the biogenic process, and therefore, I am not endorsing here any claim about which could be the requirements to call something a full-fledged biological system.

  2. This combinatorial process is in turn enhanced by the phenomenon of catalysis (a catalyst is a chemical element that increases the rate of a reaction without being consumed).

  3. A side reaction is a secondary or subsidiary reaction that takes place simultaneously with the reaction of primary interest.

  4. And of course, they should also be able to preserve organizational innovations. But we will discuss this question later.

  5. Though a reflexively catalytic network has not yet been produced in vitro, different theoretical studies suggest that it is likely that systems achieving reflexive catalytic closure could have appeared before a RNA stage (Hordjik et al. 2012; Vasas et al. 2012). These models are based on the pioneer work of Kauffman (1986).

  6. Prebiotic compartments would probably be the result of spontaneous assembling of amphiphilic molecules in water (Deamer 1985; Deamer & Dworkin 2005).

  7. De Duve (2007) uses the term “proto-metabolism” for those chemical networks driven by catalysts that, whatever their nature, cannot have displayed the exquisite specificity of present-day enzymes and must necessarily have produced some sort of “dirty gemisch”.

  8. The origin of far-from-equilibrium maintenance of chemical organizations also raises the problem of the interplay of individuated systems and collective networks, or in other words, of sets of different types of individual systems in conjunction with environmental compounds, interacting together as a long-term self-maintaining collective system. This is an important issue in the field of Origin of Life because the early appearance of a collective proto-ecological network would in turn permit metabolically less complex individual systems. As discussed by Morowitz (1992) and Morange (2008), metabolic simplicity depends on the chemical demands of the environment and, as a consequence, there is not a minimal metabolic network. Thus, a highly stable and chemically rich environment is less demanding than a more changeable and chemically restricted one. However, the trade-off between metabolic and environmental complexities during the early evolutionary stages has yet to be explored. I will discuss later (Sect. 6) the close and complex relationship between the individual and collective dimensions in the origin of life.

  9. A protocell is any experimental or theoretical model that involves a self-assembling compartment linked to chemical processes taking place around or within it (Rasmussen et al. 2008; Ruiz-Mirazo 2011). Here, I use the concept of protocell in a slightly more specific sense, as a far-from-equilibrium, self-maintaining compartmentalized system with some prebiotic properties, such as growth, autocatalytic activities or reproduction.

  10. In the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Wilson and Barker (2016) define organism as a contiguous living system, capable of some degree of response to stimuli (“agency”), reproduction, growth and development, and homeostasis.

  11. Template replication is a typical example. In fact, the basic mechanism of replication by template can be found in relatively simple systems, like the growth of crystals. Modular templates like RNA or DNA are a specific form of this mechanism. The process of copy by template is grounded in the morphological and chemical properties (i.e. a conjunction of form and materiality) possessed by certain polymers, especially nucleic acids. In these molecules, nucleotides polymerize one by one, following the guidelines set by the template string; no instructions are required to explicitly determine the form of the final set, because the reconstruction of the sequential configuration of the original molecule is ensured by the complementarity principle of nucleotide bases.

  12. Evelyn Fox Keller (2009, 2010) has suggested that some form of historical accumulation of complexity preceded evolution by natural selection. What Keller is trying to stress is that what is needed for a primitive form of evolution is the existence of systems with properties that contribute to their persistence, which will be enough to trigger a different (simpler) selection process for stability and persistence. In other words, adaptation mechanisms, which result in the generation of stabilities in a system, are enough for the operation of simpler evolutionary-competitive dynamics that will result in different degrees of maintenance of those stabilities.

  13. As argued in Moreno and Ruiz-Mirazo (2009), there are several experimental cases (e.g. Walde et al. 1994; Segre and Lancet 2000; Chen et al. 2004) which have shown that multiplication, variation and heredity would constitute a necessary but not sufficient set of conditions for what is commonly understood as evolution by natural selection.

References

  • Arnellos, A., & Moreno, A. (2012). How functional differentatiation originated in prebiotic evolution. Ludus Vitalis, 37, 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H. (2000). Autonomy, function, and representation. Communication and Cognition—Artificial Intelligence, 17(3–4), 111–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Briones, C., Fernandez, A., & Bermudez de Castro, J.M. (2015). Origenes. El universe, la vida, los humanos. Barcelona: Critica.

  • Carrara, P., Stano, P., & Luisi, L. (2012). Giant Vesicles “Colonies”: A model for primitive cell communities. ChemoBioChem, 13, 1497–1502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, I. A., Roberts, R. W., & Szostak, J. W. (2004). The emergence of competition between model protocells. Science, 305, 1474–1476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, I. A., & Szostak, J. W. (2004). Membrane growth can generate a transmembrane pH gradient in fatty acid vesicles. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 101(21), 7965–7970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dagg, J. (2003). Ecosystem organization as side-effects of replicator and interactor activities. Biology and Philosophy, 18, 491–492. doi:10.1023/A:1024128115666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Duve, C. (2007). Chemistry and selection. Chemistry & Biodiversity, 4(4), 574–583.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deamer, D. W. (1985). Boundary structures are formed by organic compounds of the Murchison carbonaceous chondrite. Nature, 317, 792–794.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deamer, D. W., & Dworkin, J. (2005). Chemistry and physics of primitive membranes. In P. Walde (Ed.), Prebiotic chemistry (pp. 1–27). Heidelberg: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Eschenmoser, A. (2007). Question 1: Commentary referring to the statement ‘‘the origin of life can be traced back to the origin of kinetic control?’’. Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, 37(4–5), 309–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox Keller, E. (2009). Self-Organization, Self-Assembly, and the Inherent Activity of Matter. In S. H. Otto (Ed.), The Hans Rausing Lecture 2009 (Uppsala University, Disciplinary Domain of Humanities and Social Sciences, Faculty of Arts, Department of History of Science and Ideas).

  • Fox Keller, E. (2010). It is possible to reduce biological explanations to explanations in chemistry and/or physics. In F. J. Ayala & R. Arp (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology (pp. 19–31). Oxford: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer, J. R. (2002). What is “Epi” about epigenetics? In L. Van Speybroeck, G. Van de Vijver, & D. De Waele (Eds.), From epigenesis to epigenetics: The genome in context (pp. 97–110). New York: New York Academy of Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guerrero, R. (1995). Vida arcaica y ecopoyesis. In F. Morán, J. Peretó, & A. Moreno (Eds.), Los Orígenes de la Vida (pp. 225–243). Madrid: Editorial Complutense.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guerrero, R., Piqueras, M., & Berlanga, M. (2002). Microbial mats and the search for minimal ecosystems. Int Microbiol, 5(4), 177–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harold, F. M. (1986). The vital force: A study of bioenergetics. New York: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, C. (2015). Foreword. In A. Moreno & M. Mossio (Eds.), Biological autonomy. A philosophical and theoretical inquiry (pp. i–xiii). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hordijk, W., & Steel, M. (2004). Detecting autocatalytic, self-sustaining sets in chemical reaction systems. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 227(4), 451–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hordjik, W., Steel, M., & Kauffman, S. (2012). The structure of autocatalytic sets: Evolvability, enablement, and emergence. Acta Biotheorica, 60, 379–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. (1986). Autocatalytic sets of proteins. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 119(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. (2000). Investigations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, W., & Russell, M. J. (2003). On the origins of cells: A hypothesis for the evolutionary transitions from abiotic geochemistry to chemoautotrophic prokaryotes, and from prokaryotes to nucleated cells. Philosophical Transactions Biological Sciences, 358, 59–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1987). The tree of knowledge: The biological roots of human understanding. Boston: Shambhala Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mavelli, F., & Ruiz-Mirazo, K. (2013). Theoretical conditions for the stationary reproduction of model protocells. Integrative Biology, 5(2), 324–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, P. (1961). Coupling of phosphorylation to electron and hydrogen transfer by a chemi-osmotic type of mechanism. Nature, 191, 144–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morange, M. (2008). Life explained. New Haven: Yale University Press (original edition (2003): La vie expliquée. 50 ans après la double helice. Paris: Odile Jacob).

  • Moreno, A., & Etxeberria, A. (1992). Self-reproduction and representation. The continuity between biological and cognitive phenomena. Uroboros, 2(1), 131–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, A., & Ruiz-Mirazo, K. (2009). The problem of the emergence of functional diversity in prebiotic evolution. Biology and Philosophy, 24(5), 585–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morowitz, H. J. (1981). Phase separation, charge separation and biogenesis. BioSystems, 14(1), 41–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morowitz, H. J. (1992). Beginnings of cellular life: Metabolism recapitulates biogenesis. New Haven & London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., & Moreno, A. (2010). Organizational closure in biological organisms. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 32(2–3), 269–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., Saborido, C., & Moreno, A. (2009). An organizational account of biological functions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60, 813–841.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbert, E., & Sleep, N. (2001). The habitat and nature of early life. Nature, 409, 1083–1091.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pascal, R., Pross, A., & Sutherland, J. (2013). Towards an evolutionary theory of the origin of life based on kinetics and thermodynamics. Open Biology, 3, 130–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pross, A. (2003). The driving force for life’s emergence: kinetic and thermodynamic considerations. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 220(3), 393–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pross, A. (2009). Seeking the chemical roots of Darwinism: bridging between chemistry and biology. Chemistry—A European Journal, 15, 8374–8381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rasmussen, S., Bedau, M. A., Liaohai, C., Deamer, D., Krakauer, D. C., Packhard, N. H., et al. (Eds.). (2008). Protocells: Bridging nonliving and living matter. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz Mirazo, K., & Moreno, A. (2004). Basic autonomy as a fundamental step in the synthesis of life. Artificial Life, 10(3), 235–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo, K. (2011). Protocell. In M. Gargaud, R. Amils, J. C. Quintanilla, H. J. Cleaves, W. M. Irvine, D. Pinti, & M. Viso (Eds.), Encyclopedia of astrobiology (Vol. 3, pp. 1353–1354). Heidelberg: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo, K., & Mavelli, F. (2008). On the way towards ‘basic autonomous agents’: stochastic simulations of minimal lipid-peptide cells. BioSystems, 91(2), 374–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo, K., Peretó, J., & Moreno, A. (2004). A universal definition of life: Autonomy and open-ended evolution. Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, 34, 323–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segre, D., & Lancet, D. (2000). Composing life. EMBO Reports, 1(3), 217–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shirt-Ediss, B. (2016). Modelling Early Transitions Toward Autonomous Protocells. PhD Dissertation. University of the Basque Country, San Sebastian.

  • Skulachev, V. P. (1992). The laws of cell energetics. European Journal of Biochemistry FEB., 208(2), 203–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stano, P., de Souza, T. P., Carrara, P., Altamura, E., D’Aguanno, E., Caputo, M., et al. (2014). Recent biophysical issues about the preparation of solute-filled lipid vesicles. Mechanics of Advanced Materials and Structures, 22(9), 748–759.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vasas, V., Fernando, C., Santos, M., & Kauffman, S. (2012). Evolution before genes. Biology Direct,. doi:10.1186/1745-6150-7-1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walde, P., Goto, A., Monnard, P. A., Wessicken, M., & Luisi, P. L. (1994). Oparin’s reaction revisited: enzymatic synthesis of poly (adenylic acid) in micelles and self-reproducing vesicles. Journal of the American Chemical Society, 116, 7541–7547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, P., & Brownlee, D. (2004). Rare earth: Why complex life Is uncommon in the universe. New York: Copernicus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R.A., & Barker, M. (2016). The Biological Notion of Individual. In E.N. Zalta (Ed). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition) URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/biology-individual/.

  • Zepik, H., Blöchliger, E., & Luisi, P. L. (2001). A chemical model of homeostasis. Angewandte Chemie Int Ed, 40(1), 199–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alvaro Moreno.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Moreno, A. Some conceptual issues in the transition from chemistry to biology. HPLS 38, 16 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-016-0117-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-016-0117-y

Keywords

Navigation