Skip to main content
Log in

Explanations and candidate explanations in physics

  • Paper in Philosophy of the Natural Sciences
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There has been a growing trend to include non-causal models in accounts of scientific explanation. A worry addressed in this paper is that without a higher threshold for explanation there are no tools for distinguishing between models that provide genuine explanations and those that provide merely potential explanations. To remedy this, a condition is introduced that extends a veridicality requirement to models that are empirically underdetermined, highly-idealised, or otherwise non-causal. This condition is applied to models of electroweak symmetry breaking beyond the Standard Model.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This paper is primarily aimed at scientific explanations in physics. I will make no claims about explanation in biology or other disciplines. However, I believe a similar exposition to a variety of case studies in different scientific disciplines could be fruitful for assessing the condition I introduce, but it is simply outside the scope of this paper.

  2. I have here restricted the explanandum to this problem, but similar stories could be told about the role of the SM Higgs in generating masses of other particles.

  3. There are many physicists who contributed to the development of the Higgs mechanism and I once again refer the reader to Borrelli (2015) for a more careful historical treatment.

  4. Higgs avoided the problem of the massless boson by showing that the transversely polarized vector fields and the longitudinally polarized Goldstone field combine to become the components of a massive vector field. This was also shown with different emphases by Englert and Brout (1964) and Guralnik et al. (1964) who are often also credited as the co-discovers of the mass-generation mechanism.

  5. The boson couples to different SM particles with different strengths, resulting in their different masses. All other particles couple universally, i.e. with the same strength.

  6. These categories are not exclusive or exhaustive, but capture a wide range of popular models. Similar breakdowns are presented in Borrelli and Stöltzner (2013), Chall et al. (2019), and Stöltzner (2017).

  7. For more on these groups of EWSB models see Borrelli (2012) and Chall et al. (2019)

  8. This is precisely where I see the confirmation condition stepping in as an analogue for a veridicality condition as it allows us to make distinctions in such cases.

  9. For a more detailed history of subsequent development of the model, see Borrelli (2015).

  10. While I think it is more accurate to compare the EW theories, the same conclusion should follow comparing the SM and some SM’.

References

  • ATLAS and CMS Collaborations. (2015). Combined measurement of the Higgs boson mass in pp collisions at \(\sqrt s = 7\) and 8 TeV with the ATLAS and CMS experiments. Physical Review Letters, 114(19), 191803.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R.W. (2002). The devil in the details. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. W., & Rice, C.C. (2014). Minimal model explanations. Philosophy of Science, 81(3), 349–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtle, P., & et al. (2016). Killing the cMSSM softly. The European Physical Journal, C76(2), 96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2008). Reexamining the quantum-classical relation: beyond reductionsm and pluralism. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2011). How scientific models can explain. Synthese, 180(1), 13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2012). Distinguishing explanatory from nonexplanatory fictions. Philosophy of Science, 79(5), 725–737.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borrelli, A. (2012). The case of the composite Higgs: the model as a “rosetta stone” in contemporary high-energy physics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 43(3), 195–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borrelli, A. (2015). The story of the Higgs boson: the origin of mass in early particle physics. The European Physical Journal H, 40(1), 1–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borrelli, A., & Stöltzner, M. (2013). Model landscapes in the Higgs sector. In Karakostas, V., & Dieks, D. (Eds.) Epsa11 perspectives and foundational problems in philosophy of science (pp. 241–252): Springer.

  • Carnap, R. (1939). Foundations of logic and mathematics. Journal of Philosophy, 36(23), 636–637.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chall, C., King, M., Mättig, P., Stöltzner, M. (2019). From a boson to the standard model Higgs: a case study in confirmation and model dynamics. Synthese, 1–29.

  • Ellis, J. (2017). Topics in Higgs physics. In 3rd Asia-Europe-Pacific school of high-energy physics (AEPSHEP 2016) Beijing, China, October 12-25, 2016.

  • Englert, F., & Brout, R. (1964). Broken symmetry and the mass of gauge vector mesons. Physical Review Letters, 13(9), 321–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, D., & Koberinski, A. (2016). The Higgs mechanism and superconductivity: a case study of formal analogies. Studies in history and philosophy of modern physics.

  • Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philosophy, 71(5).

    Google Scholar 

  • Galison, P. (1988). How experiments end. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 39(3), 411–414.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R.N. (1988). Explaining science: a cognitive approach. Philosophical Review, 100(4), 653–656.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glashow, S. (1961). Partial symmetries of weak interactions. Nuclear Physics, 22(4), 579–588.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2017). The new mechanical philosophy. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstone, J. (1961). Field theories with ‘superconductor’ solutions. Il Nuovo Cimento (1955-1965), 19(1), 154–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guralnik, G., Hagen, C.R., Kibble, T.W. (1964). Global conservation laws and massless particles. Physical Review Letters, 13(20), 585–587.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Prentice-Hall foundations of philosophy series. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15(2), 40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higgs, P. (1964a). Broken symmetries and the masses of gauge bosons. Physical Review Letters, 13(16), 508.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higgs, P.W. (1964b). Broken symmetries, massless particles and gauge fields. Physics Letters, 12(2), 132–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karaca, K. (2013). The construction of the Higgs mechanism and the emergence of the electroweak theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, (44):1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K., Doble, G., Millson, J. (2018). Counterfactuals and explanatory pluralism. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 26.

  • Kitcher, P. (1981). Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science, 48(4), 507–531.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In Kitcher, P., & Salmon, W. (Eds.) Scientific explanation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Lange, M. (2011). Conservation laws in scientific explanations: Constraints or coincidences?*. Philosophy of Science, 78(3), 333–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2016). Because without cause: non-causal explanations in science and mathematics. USA: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1).

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: models, reasoning and inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peskin, M., & Schroeder, D. (1995). An introduction to quantum field theory. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reutlinger, A. (2012). Getting rid of interventions. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biol & Biomed Sci, 43(4), 787–795.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reutlinger, A. (2016). Is there a monist theory of causal and noncausal explanations? the counterfactual theory of scientific explanation. Philosophy of Science, 83(4), 733–745.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J., & Pexton, M. (2013). Reassessing woodward’s account of explanation: regularities, counterfactuals, and non-causal explanations. Philosophy of Science, 80 (5), 613–624.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W.C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W.C. (1989). Four decades of scientific explanation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sneed, J.D. (1973). The logical structure of mathematical physics. Philosophy of Science, 40(1), 130–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spirtes, P., Glymour, C.N., Scheines, R. (1993). Causation, prediction, and search. Adaptive computation and machine learning, 2nd edn. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stöltzner, M. (2017). The variety of explanations in the Higgs sector. Synthese, 194(2), 433–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: an account of scientific explanation. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1960). A comparison of the meaning and uses of models in mathematics and the empirical sciences. Synthese, 12(2/3), 287–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • ’t Hooft, G. (1971). Renormalizable lagrangians for massive yang-mills fields. Nuclear Physics Section B, 35, 167–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B.C. (1980). The scientific image. Clarendon library of logic and philosophy. New York: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wayne, A. (2017). Explanatory integration. European Journal of Philosophy of Science, 1–19.

  • Weinberg, S. (1967). A model of leptons. Physical Review Letters, 19, 1264–1266.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: a theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work was supported by the DFG as part of the “Epistemology of the LHC” collaboration (grant FOR 2063). I would like to thank Andrew Wayne as well as Cristin Chall, Peter Mättig, and Michael Stöltzner for valuable discussions and comments on many drafts. I would also like to acknowledge all the members of the “Epistemology of the LHC” research unit for their input.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Martin King.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

King, M. Explanations and candidate explanations in physics. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 10, 7 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-019-0273-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-019-0273-5

Keywords

Navigation