Skip to main content
Log in

Thomas S. Kuhn: key to a better understanding of the extended evolutionary synthesis

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Theory in Biosciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In recent years, some scholars have explicitly questioned the desirability or utility of applying the classical and “old-fashioned” theories of scientific change by the likes of Karl Popper and Thomas S. Kuhn to the question of the precise nature and significance of the extended evolutionary synthesis (EES). Supposedly, these twentieth-century philosophers are completely irrelevant for a better understanding of this new theoretical framework for the study of evolution. Here, it will be argued that the EES can be fruitfully interpreted in terms of, as yet, insufficiently considered or even overlooked elements from Kuhn’s theory. First, in his original, historical philosophy of science, Kuhn not only distinguished between small and big scientific revolutions, he also pointed out that paradigms can be extended and reformulated. In contrast with what its name suggests, the mainstream EES can be interpreted as a Kuhnian reformulation of modern evolutionary theory. Second, it has, as yet, also been overlooked that the EES can be interpreted in terms of Kuhn’s later, tentative evolutionary philosophy of science. With the EES, an old dichotomy in evolutionary biology is maybe being formalized and institutionalized.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Availability of data and material

N/a.

Code availability

N/a.

Notes

  1. These conferences formed part of a series of convocations and events and concluded with a ceremony which included a convocation address by president Harry Truman. See: https://findingaids.princeton.edu/catalog/AC1-48.

  2. Stoltzfus (2017) adds that we don’t need a new one either (i.e., the EES). See, on the futility of the dream of a single, coherent and unified theory of evolution in the “postmodern era” or the post-“unity of science” era, also Koonin (2011), Doolittle Ford (2007) and Novick and Doolittle (2019).

  3. The MS was, first and foremost, the result of a constriction, not of a synthesis (see below).

  4. Intriguingly, Shapere wrote something similar about the MS: “All this is to say that the usual ways of thinking about scientific change and innovation do not quite capture the entirety of achievement of the synthetic theory of evolution, which in turn suggests that there is something special to be learned about the nature of scientific change and the scientific enterprise from this case that cannot be learned from most other cases” (Shapere, cited in Smocovitis 1996, p. 33).

  5. See also Gayon (1998). As a young scholar, he discovered that “the ‘synthetic theory’ (…) was less the offspring of Julian Huxley (who had coined the term ‘modern synthesis’ in 1942) than that of the determined work of a group of American biologists. During the Second World War they had decided to make their disciplines coexist and their doctrines congruent, dividing up the work in a typically American way (…)” (p. xiv). The MS seemed more and more to be “an episode of sociology” (ibid.) rather than a genuine theory. The philosopher in him was disappointed, especially when Richard Lewontin confirmed his hypothesis: “‘There is no synthetic theory. It’s a question that needs to be dealt with by the social history of science’” (ibid.). Clearly, the young Gayon referred here to the institutional MS.

  6. For a more comprehensive summary of the original MS, see, e.g., Futuyma (2010, p. 3).

  7. For a full list of the predictions, see Table 3 in Laland et al. (2015, p. 10). For a list of the accompanying research projects that are designed to test them, see https://extendedevolutionarysynthesis.com/theproject/research-projects/.

  8. Kuhn mentioned Fleck’s Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache (1935) in Structure. He also wrote the Foreword (Kuhn 1979) to its English translation (Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact). He acknowledged that Fleck anticipated many of his ideas but felt uncomfortable with the idea of a monolithic “thought collective.” In his account of scientific change, the heterogeneity of research communities plays a crucial role. Without it, revolutionary change is impossible, in the same way that variability within biological populations is essential to evolution through natural selection (see Wray 2021, pp. 21–23 and Fábregas-Tejeda 2019). Thus, he made, in a way, a synthesis between Fleck’s idea and a central feature of another book that very much influenced him: Michael Polanyi’s Personal Knowledge (1962). To wit, with Kuhn’s research communities, composed of individual scientists, Polanyi’s focus on individual scientists was combined with Fleck’s monolithic collectives.

  9. She made this suggestion during a talk at the meeting of the International Society for the History, Philosophy and Social Studies of Biology in São Paulo, Brazil (July 2017).

  10. After Godfrey-Smith (2007) queried Jablonka’s and Lamb’s (2005) claim that evolutionary biology is undergoing a revolution, the latter (Jablonka and Lamb 2007, p. 453) stated that “evolutionary theory is not undergoing a Kuhnian revolution” even though “the incorporation of new data and ideas about hereditary variation, and about the role of development in generating it, is leading to a version of Darwinism that is very different from the gene-centered one that dominated evolutionary thinking in the second half of the twentieth century” (ibid.).

  11. See, e.g., also the presentation of the EES on its official website: http://extendedevolutionarysynthesis.com.

  12. Rudolf Carnap, one of the main editors of the Encyclopedia, described it “as a book in the history of science, not philosophy of science (…)” (Carnap, cited in Wray 2012, p. 4). In 1961, Kuhn asked The University of Chicago Press for it to be simultaneously published in book format.

  13. At the time, Kuhn was professor of history of science at Berkeley, although he taught in both the philosophy and the history department. Of the 150 footnotes in the first edition of Structure, only 13 include references to philosophers, most other references concern historians (Bird 2000, p. x). To be precise, sixty percent of the sources (76/127), and ninety percent of the most cited sources, are works in the history of science (Wray 2015). Most of Kuhn’s own publications before 1962 were in the history of science. In 1968, six years after the publication of Structure, Kuhn still called himself “a practicing historian of science (…) I am a member of the American Historical, not the American Philosophical Association” (Kuhn, cited in Hacking 2012, p. x).

  14. As a graduate student in physics at Harvard University, Kuhn had discovered such a rupture himself, while preparing a course in the history of physics. He couldn’t understand Aristotle’s physics until he realized that Aristotle attached different meanings to his basic concepts than Newtonian physicists did. It is this “Aristotle-experience” that awakened his interest in the history of science and set him on a course to write Structure. Steven Weinberg (2001, p. 204) even believes that his discovery of the revolutionary shift from Aristotelian to Newtonian physics “set a pattern into which he [Kuhn] tried to shoehorn every other scientific revolution.”

  15. In 1991, he pointed out in his “Robert and Maurine Rothschild Distinguished Lecture” (“The Trouble with the Historical Philosophy of Science”) that “the problem with the historiographic revolution was that it was unable to provide a philosophy of science to replace the one it demolished and to account for the growth of scientific knowledge” (Kuhn, cited in Marcum 2015, p. 25). Some scholars claim that he did not refer to logical or empirical positivism, in this respect (see Wray 2021, Ch. 4). However, that positivist philosophy was, at the time, also being questioned, independently from the historiographic revolution: by the 1960s, many philosophers found it objectionable and, like Kuhn, believed that the history of science might be an interesting resource for developing a new philosophy of science (“the historical turn in the philosophy of science”). In any case, “Kuhn was giving us an account of science very different from the positivists’ account” (Wray 2014, p. 1).

  16. Kuhn was “reticent to assume a unified science” (Wray 2021, p. 38). However, it is no coincidence that Structure was initially published as a volume (about the history of science) in the Encyclopedia of Unified Science, a series that originated with the Vienna Circle (positivism): with its interest in a single scheme for the historical development of almost all sciences and all scientific revolutions, it clearly bears the mark of the unity of science movement. A more proximal source of inspiration was the Harvard “General Education course in the history of science” to which Kuhn contributed (see Wray 2021, pp. 33–42). With this course, the President of Harvard, James B. Conant, wanted to give Harvard graduates a sense of what science was, in abstracto, and how it worked. At the same time, he believed that the abstract, philosophical approach to understanding science could be misleading and that “the historical approach” was the key to appreciating the “dynamic quality of science” (Conant 1947, p. 24). He also claimed that, at its core, science involved the “development of conceptual schemes” (ibid.).

  17. Kuhn did indeed not conceive it as a scheme that is strictly followed in the historical development of every single science. First, as he pointed out in 1962, the early history of some sciences, like astronomy, mathematics and biochemistry, differed from the early history of his archetypal science that he described in the second chapter of Structure. In fields like mathematics and astronomy, the first firm paradigms date from prehistory, whereas biochemistry arose by division and recombination of specialties already matured. Second, Kuhn also clearly pointed out that his developmental scheme was meant as a heuristic tool and a means to practice a historiocentric kind of historiography and that sciences did not follow it in every detail of their historical development: “I’ve always said, assimilate this point of view and this way of doing it, and then see what it does for you when you try to write a history, but don’t go out looking at history to see whether this is true or false, to test the ideas. (…) But it’s not going to be ‘Can you always locate the paradigm, can you always tell the difference between a revolution and a normal development?’ It’s not meant to be applied that way” (Kuhn, cited in Sigurdsson 2016, p. 27).

  18. This criticism is not new. For example, Bird (2000, p. 60) points out that the revolutionary discovery of the structure of DNA “does not fit Kuhn’s description of development (…).” It was not normal science, nor a Kuhnian revolution. In his later evolutionary philosophy, Kuhn did recognize such “theory-creating changes” (see Wray 2014, p. 32 and Ch. 7). The fact remains, though, that they do not form part of his historical philosophy. Also, the start of evolutionary biology (i.e., of the pre-paradigmatic phase in the history of this science), through the publication of On the Origin, cannot be put in the same historical category as the (revolutionary) discovery of DNA or x-rays since Darwin did not discover evolution (also, the discovery of DNA was not followed by a pre-paradigmatic phase).

  19. The modern science of cosmology also started out in this way. It can be traced back to Einstein and his 1917 general theory of relativity. However, cosmology as a serious scientific discipline only started in the 1960s, with the victory of the Big Bang model over the steady state model. Consequently, Einstein’s theory merely marked the start of the pre-paradigmatic phase in the historical development of modern cosmology. Evidently, this science also has a long prehistory.

  20. Not everybody agrees with the traditional timing of this period, though. Brooks (2011), for example, situates the beginning of the end of the eclipse of Darwinism in the 1980s. He believes that it currently hangs in the balance. An EES must extend back in time to recover important aspects of Darwinism that were lost with the MS and also move forward beyond SET.

  21. Examples of empirical research are the testing of the models of mathematical population genetics in the field and in the laboratory (e.g., Lewontin et al. 1981) and the study of swift changes, through natural selection, of body and beak size in Galápagos finches in response to changes in their food supply (Grant and Grant 2003, 2008).  See also Tanghe et al. (2018).

  22. Of course, the EES is not the only modern alternative theoretical framework in evolutionary biology or the only modern source of criticism of SET (e.g., Walsh and Huneman 2017). Above, I already referred to the EIS (Noble 2016) and to Corning’s (2020) “Inclusive Biological Synthesis.” Other examples are the reconciliation that Danchin and colleagues (2019) propose between neo-Darwinism and neo-Lamarckism under the banner of the inclusive evolutionary synthesis (IES) and the twenty-first-century model of evolution, based on a full explanation of how genotypes generate phenotypes, envisaged by Bard (2011).

  23. This organism-centered focus should be distinguished from the organicist philosophy that opposes mechanistic explanations and therefore, natural selection as it is understood and portrayed within the SET framework. Instead, it promotes “a directed drive from within the organism as the main force for change” (Ruse 2022, p. 109).

  24. The end of World War 2, a caesura and seminal event in Germany, was another ultimate cause of the demise of this OCB.

  25. They refer to two categories of biologists: geneticists who study genetic evolutionary processes with selected organisms in the laboratory and naturalists (taxonomists and paleontologists) who draw conclusions, based on studies of populations of organisms in the field.

  26. Kuhn focused on specialization through branching but new scientific specializations can originate “either through branching from a parent discipline or through emerging from an overlap between two separate disciplines” (Marcum 2015, p. 144). This corresponds to cladogenesis and hybridization speciation in nature.

  27. As Wray (2014, p. 7) points out, the notion of a paradigm remained relevant in Kuhn’s evolutionary philosophy.

References

  • Amundson R (2005) The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary biology: structure and synthesis. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Antonovics J (1987) The evolutionary dys-synthesis: which bottles for which wine? Am Nat 129(3):321–331

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baedke J (2019) O organism, where art thou? Old and new challenges for organism-centered biology. J Hist Biol 52:293–324

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Baedke J (2021) What’s wrong with evolutionary causation? Acta Biotheor 69:79–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baedke J, Fábregas-Tejeda A (2023) The organism in evolutionary explanation: from early twentieth century to the extended evolutionary synthesis. In: Dickins TE, Dickins BJA (eds) Evolutionary biology: contemporary and historical reflections upon core theory. Springer International Publishing, Cham, pp 121–150

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bard JB (2011) The next evolutionary synthesis: from Lamarck and Darwin to genomic variation and systems biology. Cell Commun Signal. https://doi.org/10.1186/1478-811X-9-30

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Bird A (2000) Thomas Kuhn. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blum A, Gavroglu K, Joas C, Renn J (2016) Introduction. In: Blum A, Gavroglu K, Joas C, Renn J (eds) Shifting paradigms: Thomas S. Kuhn and the history of science. Edition Open Access, Berlin, pp 1–2

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumenthal G (2011) Kuhn and the chemical revolution: a reassessment. Found Chem 15(1):93–101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowler P (1983) The eclipse of Darwinism: anti-Darwinian evolution theories in the decades around 1900. John Hopkins University, Baltimore

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks DR (2011) The extended synthesis: something old, something new. Evo Edu Outreach 4:3–7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown JD (1948) The Princeton bicentennial conferences: a retrospect. J Higher Educ 19(2):55–59

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burian RM (1988) Challenges to the evolutionary synthesis. In: Hecht MK, Wallace B (eds) Evolutionary biology 23. Springer, New York, pp 247–269

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cain J (2009) Rethinking the synthesis period in evolutionary studies. J Hist Biol 42:621–648

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2010) The dialectics of dis/unity in the evolutionary synthesis and its extensions. In: Pigliucci M, Müller GB (eds) Evolution: the extended synthesis. The Mit Press, Cambridge, pp 443–481

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll SB (2000) Towards a new evolutionary synthesis. Trends Ecol Evol 15(1):27–32

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen IB (1985) Revolution in science. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Conant JB (1947) On understanding science: an historical approach. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Corning P (2020) Beyond the modern synthesis: a framework for a more inclusive biological synthesis. Prog Biophys Mol Biol 153:5–12

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Craig LR (2010) The so-called extended synthesis and population genetics. Biol Theory 5:117–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig LR (2015) Neo-Darwinism and evo-devo: an argument for theoretical pluralism in evolutionary biology. Perspect Sci 23(3):243–279

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Danchin E, Pocheville A, Huneman P (2019) Early in life effects and heredity: reconciling neo-Darwinism with neo-Lamarckism under the banner of the inclusive evolutionary synthesis. Phil Trans R Soc B 374:20180113

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1859) On the origin of species, or, the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life. John Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1989) The selfish gene, 2nd ed. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Dawkins R (2006) The selfish gene, 3rd ed. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Delisle RG (2011) What was really synthesized during the evolutionary synthesis? A historiographical proposal. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 42:50–59

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Dickins TE, Rahman Q (2012) The extended evolutionary synthesis and the role of soft inheritance in evolution. Proc R Soc B Biol Sci 279:2913–2921

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doolittle Ford W (2007) Review of Rose and Oakley (2007). https://biologydirect.biomedcentral.com/articles/10.1186/1745-6150-2-30

  • Eldredge N (1985) Unfinished synthesis: biological hierarchies and modern evolutionary thought. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fábregas-Tejeda A (2019) New perspectives on theory change in evolutionary biology. Workshop ‘The extended evolutionary synthesis: philosophical and historical dimensions’, Ruhr University Bochum, Germany, March 21–22, 2019. J Gen Philos Sci 50:573–581

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fábregas-Tejeda A, Vergara-Silva F (2018) The emerging structure of the extended evolutionary synthesis: where does evo-devo fit in? Theor Biosci 137:169–184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleck L (1935) Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache. Schwabe Verlag, Basel

    Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma DJ (2011) Expand or revise? The evolutionary synthesis today. Q Rev Biol 86(3):203–208

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma DJ (2010) Evolutionary biology: 150 years of progress. In: Bell MA, Futuyma DJ, Eanes WF, Levinton JS (eds) Evolution since Darwin: the first 150 years. Sinauer Associates Inc., Sunderland, pp 3–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma DJ (2015) Can modern evolutionary theory explain macroevolution? In: Serrelli E, Gontier N (eds) Macroevolution: explanation, interpretation and evidence. Springer International Publishing, Cham, pp 29–85

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma DJ (2017) Evolutionary biology today and the call for an extended synthesis. Interface Focus 7(5):20160145

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Gayon J (1998) Darwinism’s struggle for survival: heredity and the hypothesis of natural selection, translated from French by Matthew Cobb. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon J, Huneman P (2019) The modern synthesis: theoretical or institutional event? J Hist Biol 52(4):519–535

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Gerhart J, Kirschner M (2007) The theory of facilitated variation. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 104:8582–8589

    Article  ADS  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert SF (2006) Developmental biology. Sinauer, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2007) Is it a revolution? Biol Philos 22:429–437

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grant BR (2008) How and why species multiply: the radiation of Darwin’s finches. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Grant BR, Grant PR (2003) What Darwin’s finches can teach us about the evolutionary origin and regulation of biodiversity. Bioscience 53(10):965–975

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gupta M, Prasad NG, Dey S, Joshi A, Vidya TNC (2017) Niche construction in evolutionary theory: the construction of an academic niche? J Genet 96(3):491–504

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (2012) Introductory essay. In: Kuhn TS (ed) The structure of scientific revolutions: 50th anniversary. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp vii–xxxvii

    Google Scholar 

  • Ho M-W, Saunders PT (1984) Beyond neo-Darwinism: an introduction to the new evolutionary paradigm. Academic Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan J (1995) The return of the maverick. Sci Amer 272(3):46–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene P (2008) Thomas Kuhn and the chemical revolution. Found Chem 10:101–115

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman P (2010) Assessing the prospects for a return of organisms in evolutionary biology. Hist Phil Life Sci 32:341–372

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley JS (1942) Evolution: the modern synthesis. George Allen and Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (2005) Evolution in four dimensions: genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in the history of life. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (2007) The expanded evolutionary synthesis—a response to Godfrey-Smith, Haig, and West-Eberhard. Biol Phil 22:453–472

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (2020) Inheritance systems and the extended evolutionary synthesis (Elements in the philosophy of biology). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Raz G (2009) Transgenerational epigenetic inheritance: prevalence, mechanisms, and implications for the study of heredity and evolution. Q Rev Biol 84:131–176

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Jepsen GL, Mayr E, Simpson GG (eds) (1949) Genetics, paleontology, and evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

  • Kirschner M (2005) The plausibility of life: resolving Darwin’s dilemma. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner M, Gerhart J (1998) Evolvability. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 95:8420–8427

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Koonin EV (2011) The logic of chance: the nature and origin of biological evolution. FT Press, Upper Saddle River, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1962) The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions, enlarged, 2nd edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1979) Foreword. In: Fleck, L Genesis and development of a scientific fact. Trenn TJ, Merton RK (eds), translated by F Bradley and TJ Trenn, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp vii–xi

  • Kuhn TS (1993) Foreword. In: Hoyningen-Huene P (ed) Reconstructing scientific revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn’s philosophy of science, translated by A. T. Levine. Chicago University Press, Chicago, pp ix–xiii

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (2000) The road since structure. In: Conant J, Haugeland J (eds) The road since Structure: philosophical essays, 1970–1993, with an autobiographical interview. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 90–104

    Google Scholar 

  • Kutschera U (2013) Evolution. In: Maloy S, Hughes K (eds) Brenner’s encyclopedia of genetics, 2nd ed. Academic Press, Cambridge, pp 541–544

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kutschera U, Niklas KJ (2004) The modern theory of biological evolution: an expanded synthesis. Naturwissenschaften 91:255–276

    Article  ADS  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1978) The methodology of scientific research programmes. Philosophical papers. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN et al (2014) Does evolutionary theory need a rethink? Nature 514:161–164

    Article  ADS  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN et al (2015) The extended evolutionary synthesis: its structure, assumptions and predictions. Proc R Soc B Biol Sci 282:20151019

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler MD (2009) Evolutionary developmental biology offers a significant challenge to the Neo-Darwinian paradigm. In: Ayala J, Arp R (eds) Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology. Wiley, New Jersey, pp 199–212

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewens T (2019) The extended evolutionary synthesis: what is the debate about, and what might success for the extenders look like? Biol J Linn Soc 127(4):707–721

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1974) The genetic basis of evolutionary change. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC, Moore JA, Provine WB, Wallace B (eds) (1981) Dobzhansky’s genetics of natural populations. Columbia University Press, New York, pp i–xliii

    Google Scholar 

  • Lind MI, Spagopoulou F (2018) Evolutionary consequences of epigenetic inheritance. Heredity 121:205–209

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Love AC (2010) Rethinking the structure of evolutionary theory for an extended sythesis. In: Pigliucci M, Müller GB (eds) Evolution: the extended synthesis. The Mit Press, Cambridge, pp 403–442

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch M (2007) The frailty of adaptive hypotheses for the origins of organismal complexity. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 104(Suppl 1):8597–8604

    Article  ADS  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Marcum JA (2015) Thomas Kuhn’s revolutions: a historical and an evolutionary philosophy of science? Bloomsbury Publishing, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Martins dos Reis CR, Luvison Araújo LA (2020) Extended evolutionary synthesis: neither synthesis nor extension. Biol Theory 15:57–60

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1985) Do we need a new evolutionary paradigm? New Sci 1447:38–39

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1963) Animal species and evolution. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1982) The growth of biological thought: diversity, evolution, and inheritance. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1994) The advance of science and scientific revolutions. J Hist Behav Sci 30:328–334

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB (2007) Evo–devo: extending the evolutionary synthesis. Nat Rev Genet 8:943–949

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB (2017) Why an extended evolutionary synthesis is necessary. Interface Focus 7(5):20170015

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Newman SA, Linde-Medina M (2013) Physical determinants in the emergence and inheritance of multicellular form. Biol Theory 8(3):274–285

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noble D (2013) Physiology is rocking the foundations of evolutionary biology. Exp Physiol 98:1235–1243

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Noble D (2015) Evolution beyond neo-Darwinism: a new conceptual framework. J Exp Biol 218:7–13

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Noble D (2016) Dance to the tune of life: biological relativity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Noble D (2021) The illusions of the modern synthesis. Biosemiotics 14:5–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Novick A, Doolittle WF (2019) How microbes ‘jeopardize’ the modern synthesis. PLoS Genet 15(5):e1008166

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Nuño de la Rosa L, Müller GB (eds) (2021) Evolutionary developmental biology. Springer, Cham

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi E (2008) Modernizing the modern synthesis. Science 321(5886):196–197

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Pievani T (2012) An evolving research programme: the structure of evolutionary theory from a Lakatosian perspective. In: Fasolo A (ed) The theory of evolution and its impact. Springer, Milan, pp 211–228

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pievani T (2016) How to rethink evolutionary theory: a plurality of evolutionary patterns. Evol Biol 43:446–455

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2003) The new evolutionary synthesis: Around the corner, or impossible chimaera? Rev Biol 78(4):449–453

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2007) Do we need an extended evolutionary synthesis? Evolution 61:2743–2749

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2009) An extended synthesis for evolutionary biology. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1168:218–228

    Article  ADS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2012) Biology’s last paradigm shift. The transition from natural theology to Darwinism. Paradigmi 3:45–58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2016) The origin of the extended evolutionary synthesis: an interview with Massimo Pigliucci. This view of life. https://thisviewoflife.com/the-origin-of-the-extended-evolutionary-synthesis-an-interview-with-massimo-pigliucci/

  • Pigliucci M, Finkelman L (2014) The extended (evolutionary) synthesis debate: where science meets philosophy. Bioscience 64:511–516

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M, Müller G (eds) (2010) Evolution: the extended synthesis. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M (1962) Personal knowledge: towards a post-critical philosophy. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Provine WB (1971) The origins of theoretical population genetics. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Provine WB (1989) Progress in evolution and meaning in life. In: Nitecki MH (ed) Evolutionary progress. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 49–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Reingold N (1980) Through paradigm-land to a normal history of science. Soc Stud Sci 10:475–496

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse M (1978) What kind of revolution occurred in geology? PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1978:240–273

  • Ruse M (1989) Is the theory of punctuated equilibria a new paradigm? J Soc Biol Struct 12:195–212

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse M (1999) The Darwinian revolution: science red in tooth and claw, 2nd edn. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse M (2022) Understanding natural selection. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar S (2015) The Genomic challenge to adaptationism. British J Philos Sci 66:505–536

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Schlichting CD, Pigliucci M (1998) Phenotypic evolution: a reaction norm perspective. Sinauer, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Sepkoski D (2018) The unfinished synthesis? Paleontology and evolutionary biology in the twentieth Century. J Hist Biol 52:687–703

    Article  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Shanks N (2004) God, the devil, and Darwin: a critique of intelligent design theory. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sigurdsson S (2016) The nature of scientific knowledge: an interview with Thomas S. Kuhn. In: Blum A, Gavroglu K, Joas C, Renn J (eds) Shifting paradigms: Thomas S Kuhn and the history of science. Edition Open Access, Berlin, pp 17–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner M (2016) Unified theory of evolution. Aeon. https://aeon.co/essays/on-epigenetics-we-need-both-darwin-s-and-lamarck-s-theories

  • Smocovitis VB (1996) Unifying biology: the evolutionary synthesis and evolutionary biology. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Stidd BM (1980) The neotenous origin of the pollen organ of the gymnosperm Cycadeoidea and implications for the origin of higher taxa. Paleobiology 6:161–167

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoltzfus A (2017) Why we don’t want another “Synthesis.” Biol Direct 12:23

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Tanghe KB, De Tiège A, Pauwels L et al (2018) What’s wrong with the modern evolutionary synthesis? A critical reply to Welch. Biol Philos 33:23. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9633-3

  • Tanghe KB, Pauwels L, De Tiège A, Braeckman J (2021) Interpreting the history of evolutionary biology through a Kuhnian prism: sense or nonsense? Perspect Sci 29(1):1–35

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uller T, Laland K (eds) (2019) Evolutionary causation: biological and philosophical perspectives. Vienna series in theoretical biology. The Mitt Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Waddington CH (1953) Genetic assimilation of an acquired character. Evolution 7(2):118–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waddington CH (1957) The strategy of the genes: a discussion of some aspects of theoretical biology. Allen & Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D, Huneman P (2017) Challenging the modern synthesis. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg S (2001) The non-revolution of Thomas Kuhn. In: Weinberg S (ed) Facing up: science and its cultural adversaries. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 187–206

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Welch JJ (2017) What’s wrong with evolutionary biology? Biol Philos 32:263–279

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wray GA et al (2014) Does evolutionary theory need a rethink? No, all is well. Nature 514:161–164

    Article  ADS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Wray KB (2012) Assessing the influence of Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Metascience 21:1–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Wray KB (2015) Kuhn’s social epistemology and the sociology of science. In: Devlin WJ, Bokulich A (eds) Kuhn’s structure of scientific revolutions–50 years on. Springer International Publishing Switzerland, Cham, pp 167–183

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wray KB (2021) Kuhn’s intellectual path: charting The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the reviewer for their constructive and useful comments.

Funding

N/a.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

N/a.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Koen B. Tanghe.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

N/a.

Ethical approval

N/a.

Consent to participate

N/a.

Consent for publication

I agree to be accountable for all aspects of the work in ensuring that questions related to the accuracy or integrity of any part of the work are appropriately investigated and resolved.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Tanghe, K.B. Thomas S. Kuhn: key to a better understanding of the extended evolutionary synthesis. Theory Biosci. 143, 27–44 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12064-023-00409-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12064-023-00409-w

Keywords

Navigation