Skip to main content
Log in

The emerging structure of the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis: where does Evo-Devo fit in?

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Theory in Biosciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Extended Evolutionary Synthesis (EES) debate is gaining ground in contemporary evolutionary biology. In parallel, a number of philosophical standpoints have emerged in an attempt to clarify what exactly is represented by the EES. For Massimo Pigliucci, we are in the wake of the newest instantiation of a persisting Kuhnian paradigm; in contrast, Telmo Pievani has contended that the transition to an EES could be best represented as a progressive reformation of a prior Lakatosian scientific research program, with the extension of its Neo-Darwinian core and the addition of a brand-new protective belt of assumptions and auxiliary hypotheses. Here, we argue that those philosophical vantage points are not the only ways to interpret what current proposals to ‘extend’ the Modern Synthesis-derived ‘standard evolutionary theory’ (SET) entail in terms of theoretical change in evolutionary biology. We specifically propose the image of the emergent EES as a vast network of models and interweaved representations that, instantiated in diverse practices, are connected and related in multiple ways. Under that assumption, the EES could be articulated around a paraconsistent network of evolutionary theories (including some elements of the SET), as well as models, practices and representation systems of contemporary evolutionary biology, with edges and nodes that change their position and centrality as a consequence of the co-construction and stabilization of facts and historical discussions revolving around the epistemic goals of this area of the life sciences. We then critically examine the purported structure of the EES—published by Laland and collaborators in 2015—in light of our own network-based proposal. Finally, we consider which epistemic units of Evo-Devo are present or still missing from the EES, in preparation for further analyses of the topic of explanatory integration in this conceptual framework.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Image conceived by Fátima Sofía Ávila-Cascajares and Alejandro Fábregas-Tejeda; image design by Casandra Lizbeth Méndez-Martínez, Diana Martínez Almaguer and Julio César Montero Rojas (color figure online)

Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Before moving forward, we point out that our discussion will be centered mainly around the ideas and concepts espoused in the book edited by Pigliucci and Müller (2010a, b) and in Laland et al. (2015), which constitute the mainstream usage of the framework dubbed ‘Extended Evolutionary Synthesis,’ but we recognize that many other authors in recent years have proposed diverse views as to how to ‘extend’ (or ‘expand’) the current evolutionary synthesis (e.g. Gould 2002; Kutschera and Niklas 2004; Brooks 2011 and citations therein; Tëmkin and Eldredge 2015 for an updated version of the ‘Hierarchy Theory of Evolution’ (HTE) that incorporates network analysis; see also Pievani 2016a; Eldredge et al. 2016). In the literature focused on the integration of non-genetic heritable variation into wider evolutionary frameworks, somewhat interchangeable terms to refer to some of the themes and motifs of the EES are being used, e.g. ‘Inclusive Evolutionary Synthesis’ (Danchin 2013) or ‘Pluralistic Model of Inheritance’ (Bonduriansky 2012). Differences are more explicit in Bonduriansky and Day (2018).

  2. The visual tradition for depicting the EES as a nested set of ellipses (a Venn diagram), initiated by Pigliucci (2009), has been influential for many evolutionary biologists and philosophers. For example, taking Pigliucci´s diagram as a starting point, the British physiologist Denis Noble recently published his take on the contours of the EES (Noble 2015), for him dubbed ‘Integrative Synthesis’ as it would be based on the integration of a variety of interacting mechanisms of evolutionary change; he sees it as “a nuanced multi mechanism theory of evolution” (Noble 2015; p. 7). The differences between the two diagrams are conspicuous: at variance with Pigliucci, Noble does not portray the ‘new synthesis’ as a perfectly continuous extension of the MS: several elements of its gene-centric stance will be left out, being replaced by wider views of inheritance, multilevel selection and a different view of genomic evolution. Instead of using a nested set of enlarging ellipses, Noble depicts the EES as a set of partially overlapping ellipses (with elements of the MS not in contact with the elements of the purported EES).

  3. It should be mentioned that Pigliucci’s stance on the current juncture and the future of evolutionary thought has become more nuanced in recent years (see Pigliucci and Finkelman 2014; Pigliucci 2018).

  4. In the traditional narratives, it was not until a few decades later that what we properly call ‘philosophy of biology’ was born (Palma 2015). Philosophy of biology integrated aspects, reformulations and critiques to the blind spots and flaws of twentieth-century philosophy of science—e.g. the rejection to strict determinism, ‘universal laws’ and physicalist epistemologies, accepting, instead, probabilistic predictions and historical explanations (see Mayr 2004)—as well as the unique theoretical and empirical developments of a mature biology (Palma 2015). For a different and robust historiography on the origins of philosophy of biology, see Nicholson and Gawne (2015).

  5. Other possibilities would include conceptualizing the EES, just as the MS was conceived in past decades, as a multi-field theory (sensu Darden 1986) or, following Wassermann (1981), as a hypertheory that subsumes subordinate theories that deal with different but complementary evolutionary mechanisms; for additional discussions, see Love (2013, 2017).

  6. This idea emerged in the context of an academic collaboration with Mexican philosopher of science Mario Casanueva López (UAM-Cuajimalpa, Mexico).

  7. A possibility that may be worth exploring further is that, for a given moment in time, there could be more than one topological configuration of the EES existing simultaneously. For Love (2013; p. 332), in evolutionary biology we can see a “(…) multiplicity of theory structures constructed from the heterogeneity of methodological and epistemological goals” (italics added); in the future, if the EES reaches far-ranging acceptance, we could have many EES structures in the cases where distinct situated communities of evolutionary biologists follow different epistemic goals.

  8. Theories can also be epistemic units for wider conceptual frameworks (e.g. hypertheories, see Wassermann 1981) that embrace several complementary theories or models.

  9. A quote from Love (2013; p. 328) is insightful in that regard: “(…) new findings and conceptual developments may involve the reorganization or rearrangement of theory components, even if they do not ‘overthrow’ existing foundations. Part of the call for an EES could be a complaint about how evolutionary theory organizes biological knowledge and guides inquiry, not simply about whether it contains all of the relevant parts”.

  10. We think the notion of ‘evolutionary theories’ in that context is adequate. Niche construction theory is the prominent example of one (see Odling-Smee et al. 2003; Laland et al. 2016). Eva Jablonka and Marion Lamb have also described the general picture of their book Evolution in Four Dimensions as a “sort of Darwinian theory (…) that sees DNA as a crucial heritable developmental resource, but recognizes that DNA is not the only resource that contributes to heredity” (Jablonka and Lamb 2007; p. 356; see Jablonka and Lamb 2014 for a revised edition of the book).

  11. Although one could interpret Fig. 2 as something akin to a construction chain.

  12. For three different accounts of the tensions that exist between Evo-Devo and the Modern Synthesis, consult Minelli (2010), Laubichler (2010), Craig (2015). They address, respectively, the viable possibility of integration, the insurmountable obstacles for doing so, and the possible pluralist co-existence of both as individual conceptual frameworks in evolutionary biology. Amundson (2005) is a good historical complement to these debates.

  13. Fusco (2015) places the blame on the flawed and insufficient theoretical work being conducted; other scientific or sociohistorical reasons will not be addressed here.

  14. We have selected, for the consideration of the reader, three additional fragments of Laland et al. (2015) where the prominence of developmental processes and developmental frameworks is patent: “Parent–offspring similarity occurs not only because of transmission of DNA, but because parents transfer a variety of developmental resources that enable reconstruction of developmental niches”(p. 4); “Niche construction also influences ontogeny and constitutes an important way in which environmental factors are incorporated into normal development, sometimes to become as dependable as genomic factors” (p. 4); “Too much causal significance is afforded to genes and selection, and not enough to the developmental processes that create novel variants, contribute to heredity, generate adaptive fit, and thereby direct the course of evolution” (p. 6).

  15. Laland and collaborators consider that Evo-Devo is in no position to subsume or engulf the study of developmental plasticity (see Laland et al. 2015).

  16. Eva Jablonka and Marion Lamb (pers. comm, July 2017) raised the concern that, by focusing on “just one paper”, we may be acting uncharitable or unfairly to gauge the contributions of Evo-Devo (or of any other research field) to the EES; that to settle the matter of the relative contributions of different fields of research to the structure of the EES, we should wait for a full-length exposition, similar to Huxley’s 1942 book, to appear. Although we agree with them (and encourage them to take up to task to write such book) in the sense that our philosophical analysis about the structure of the EES is preliminary and somewhat sketchy, we need to stress that it is just a response to one of the objectives laid out explicitly in Laland et al. (2015: p. 3): “Our objective here is to add substance to these debates by providing a clear statement of the structure, assumptions and predictions of the EES that is useful to both enthusiasts and skeptics, allowing its status as an alternative conceptual framework to be evaluated”. We shall add that theory presentations (see Griesemer 1984) are not philosophically innocuous as they reflect how scientists use their frameworks in practice and further demonstrate “how different structures are adopted to achieve specific methodological and epistemological goals in evolutionary theory” (Love 2017; p. 161) by means of idealizing some features while ignoring or concealing to the background other properties or variables of the systems under scrutiny (see also Love 2013).

References

  • Abouheif E, Sears K (2015) It’s time to get together: announcing the new society for evolutionary developmental biology in the Americas. Evol Dev 17:1. https://doi.org/10.1111/ede.12114

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson R (2005) The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Arthur W (1997) The origin of animal body plans. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Arthur W (2002) The emerging conceptual framework of evolutionary developmental biology. Nature 415:757–764

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Arthur W (2011) Evolution: a developmental approach. Wiley, Hoboken

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson P, Gluckman P (2011) Plasticity, robustness, development and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonduriansky R (2012) Rethinking heredity, again. Trends Ecol Evol 27:330–336

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bonduriansky R, Day T (2018) Extended Heredity. A New Understanding of Inheritance and Evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton and Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonner JT (ed) (1982) Evolution and development. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I (2010) Beyond reduction and pluralism: toward an epistemology of explanatory integration in biology. Erkenntnis 73:295–311

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I, Love AC (2010) Evolutionary novelty and the Evo-Devo synthesis: field notes. Evol Biol 37:93–99

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I, Love AC (2012) Conceptualizing evolutionary novelty: moving beyond definitional debates. J Exp Zool B Mol Dev Evol 318:417–427

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks DR (2011) The extended synthesis: something old, something new. Evol Edu Outreach 4:3–7. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12052-010-0304-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burian RM (1988) Challenges to the evolutionary synthesis. In: Hecht MK, Wallace B (eds) Evolutionary biology, vol 23. Springer, New York, pp 247–269

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W (2010) The dialectics of dis/unity in the evolutionary synthesis and its extensions. In: Pigliucci M, Müller GB (eds) Evolution: the extended synthesis. MIT Press, Boston, pp 443–481

    Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut W, Rasskin-Gutman D (eds) (2005) Modularity: understanding the development and evolution of natural complex systems. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Caponi G (2012) Réquiem por el centauro. Aproximación epistemológica a la biología evolucionaria del desarrollo. Centro de Estudios Filosóficos, Políticos y Sociales Vicente Lombardo Toledano, México

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll SB (2008) Evo-Devo and an expanding evolutionary synthesis: a genetic theory of morphological evolution. Cell 134:25–36

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll SB, Grenier JK, Weatherbee SD (2001) From DNA to diversity: molecular genetics and the evolution of animal design. Blackwell Science, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Casanueva M (2016) Redes y paisajes conceptuales en la Evo-Devo. Metatheoria 5:83–97

    Google Scholar 

  • Casanueva M, Martínez M (2014) Marcos causales y síntesis teóricas. Acta Scientiae 16:330–344

    Google Scholar 

  • Charlesworth D, Barton NH, Charlesworth B (2017) The sources of adaptive variation. Proc Biol Sci 284:20162864. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2016.2864

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Craig L (2010) The so-called extended synthesis and population genetics. Biol Theory 5:117–123

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig LR (2015) Neo-Darwinism and Evo-Devo: an argument for theoretical pluralism in evolutionary biology. Perspect Sci 23:243–279

    Google Scholar 

  • Danchin E (2013) Avatars of information: towards an inclusive evolutionary synthesis. Trends Ecol Evol 28:351–358

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Darden L (1986) Relations among fields in the evolutionary synthesis. In: Bechtel W (ed) Integrating scientific disciplines. Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht, pp 113–123

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson EH (2006) The regulatory genome: gene regulatory networks in development and evolution. Academic Press, San Diego

    Google Scholar 

  • Delisle RG (2009) Les philosophies du néodarwinisme: Conceptions divergentes sur l’homme et le sens de l’évolution. Presses Universitaires de France, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Delisle RG (2018) From Charles Darwin to the evolutionary synthesis: weak and diffused connections only. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context. Research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 133–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Depew DJ, Weber BH (2011) The fate of Darwinism: evolution after the modern synthesis. Biol Theory 6:89–102

    Google Scholar 

  • Depew DJ, Weber BH (2013) Challenging Darwinism: expanding, extending, replacing. In: Ruse M (ed) The Cambridge encyclopedia of Darwin and evolutionary thought. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 405–411

    Google Scholar 

  • Dieckmann U, Doebeli M (2005) Pluralism in evolutionary theory. J Evol Biol 18:1209–1213

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Diogo R (2016) Where is the Evo in Evo-Devo (evolutionary developmental biology)? J Exp Zool B Mol Dev Evol 326:9–18

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Duboule D (2010) The Evo-Devo comet. EMBO Rep 11:489

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge N (1985) Unfinished synthesis: biological hierarchies and modern evolutionary thought. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge N (2008) Hierarchies and the sloshing bucket: toward the unification of evolutionary biology. Evol Edu Outreach 1:10–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge N, Pievani T, Serrelli E, Tëmkin I (eds) (2016) Evolutionary theory: a hierarchical perspective. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Endler JA, McLellan T (1988) The processes of evolution: toward a newer synthesis. Annu Rev Ecol Evol 19:395–421

    Google Scholar 

  • Fábregas-Tejeda A, Vergara-Silva F (2018) Hierarchy theory of evolution and the extended evolutionary synthesis: some epistemic bridges, some conceptual rifts. Evol Biol 45:127–139

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend P (1975) Against method. New Left Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuentes A (2016) The extended evolutionary synthesis, ethnography, and the human niche: toward an integrated anthropology. Current Anthropology 57(S13):S13–S26

    Google Scholar 

  • Fusco G (2015) For a new dialogue between theoretical and empirical studies in evo-devo. Front Ecol Evolut. https://doi.org/10.3389/fevo.2015.00097

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma DJ (2015) Can modern evolutionary theory explain macroevolution? In: Serrelli E, Gontier N (eds) Macroevolution. Explanation, interpretation and evidence. Springer, Cham, pp 29–85

    Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma DJ (2017) Evolutionary biology today and the call for an extended synthesis. Interface Focus 7(5):20160145. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsfs.2016.0145

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Gaddis JL (2002) The landscape of history. How historians map the past. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert SF, Bosch TCG, Ledón-Rettig C (2015) Eco-Evo-Devo: developmental symbiosis and developmental plasticity as evolutionary agents. Nat Rev Genet 16:611–622

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb G (1992) Individual development and evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1980) Is a new and general theory of evolution emerging? Paleobiology 6:119–130

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (2002) The structure of evolutionary theory. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Grant B (2010) Should evolutionary theory evolve? Sci 24:24–31

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (1984) Presentations and the status of theories. In: Asquit PD, Kitcher P (eds) Proceedings of the 1984 Biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association, vol 1. Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, pp 102–114

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (1979) Imre Lakatos’s philosophy of science. Brit J Philos Sci 30:381–402

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall BK (1992) Evolutionary developmental biology. Chapman & Hall, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Handschuh S, Mitteroecker P (2012) Evolution—the extended synthesis. A research proposal persuasive enough for the majority of evolutionary biologists? Hum Ethol Bull 27:18–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Held LI (2017) Deep homology? Uncanny similarities of humans and flies uncovered by Evo-Devo. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendrikse JL, Parsons TE, Hallgrímsson B (2007) Evolvability as the proper focus of evolutionary developmental biology. Evol Dev 9:393–401

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hoekstra HE, Coyne JA (2007) The locus of evolution: Evo Devo and the genetics of adaptation. Evolution 61:995–1016

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Irie N, Kuratani S (2014) The developmental hourglass model: a predictor of the basic body plan? Development 141:4649–4655

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Ingold T (2018) Anthropology: Why It Matters. Polity Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (2007) Précis of evolution in four dimensions. Behav Brain Sci 30:353–389

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (2014) Evolution in four dimensions. Genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in the history of life (revised edition). MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger J, Laubichler M, Callebaut W (2015) The comet cometh: evolving developmental systems. Biol Theory 10:36–49

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Kellert SH, Longino HE, Waters CK (2006) Introduction: the pluralist stance. In: Kellert SH, Longino HE, Waters CK (eds) Scientific pluralism. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp vii–xxviii

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiger PJ (2016) Is it time for our understating of evolution to evolve? HowStuffWorks website. http://science.howstuffworks.com/life/evolution/extended-evolutionary-synthesis-theory.htm. Accessed 1 July 2017

  • Kirschner MW, Gerhart JC (2005) The plausibility of life: resolving Darwin’s dilemma. Yale University Press, Yale

    Google Scholar 

  • Kutschera U, Niklas KJ (2004) The modern theory of biological evolution: an expanded synthesis. Naturwissenschaften 91:255–276

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1978) The methodology of scientific research programmes. Philosophical papers, vol 1. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN, O’Brien M (2012) Cultural niche construction: an introduction. Biol Theory 6:191–202

    Google Scholar 

  • Laland K, Uller T, Feldman MW, Sterelny K, Müller GB, Moczek A, Jablonka E, Odling-Smee J, Wray GA, Hoekstra HE, Futuyma DJ, Lenski RE, Mackay TF, Schulter D, Strassmann JE (2014) Does evolutionary theory need a rethink? Nature 514:161–164

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Laland K, Uller T, Feldman MW, Sterelny K, Müller GB, Moczek A, Jablonka E, Odling-Smee J (2015) The extended evolutionary synthesis: its structure, assumptions and predictions. Proc R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 282:20151019. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2015.1019

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland K, Matthews B, Feldman MW (2016) An introduction to niche construction theory. Evol Ecol 30:191–202

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler MD (2010) Evolutionary developmental biology offers a significant challenge to the neo-Darwinian paradigm. In: Ayala FJ, Malden RA (eds) Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology. Wiley, Massachusetts, pp 199–212

    Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler MD, Renn J (2015) Extended evolution: a conceptual framework for integrating regulatory networks and niche construction. J Exp Zool B Mol Dev Evol 324:565–577

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler MD, Prohaska SJ, Stadler PF (2018) Toward a mechanistic explanation of phenotypic evolution: the need for a theory of theory integration. J Exp Zool (Mol Dev Evol) 330:5–14

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewens T (2016) The meaning of science. An introduction to the philosophy of science. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Love AC (2008) Explaining evolutionary innovation and novelty: criteria of adequacy and multidisciplinary prerequisites. Philos Sci 75:874–886

    Google Scholar 

  • Love AC (2010) Rethinking the structure of evolutionary theory for an extended synthesis. In: Pigliucci M, Müller GB (eds) Evolution: the extended synthesis. MIT Press, Boston, pp 403–441

    Google Scholar 

  • Love AC (2013) Theory is as theory does: scientific practice and theory structure in biology. Biol Theory 7:325–337

    Google Scholar 

  • Love AC (2017) Evo-Devo and the structure(s) of evolutionary theory: a different kind of challenge. In: Huneman P, Walsh DM (eds) Challenging the modern synthesis. Adaptation, development, and inheritance. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 159–187

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch M (2007) The origins of genome architecture. Sinauer Associates, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Martínez M (2009) Los constreñimientos del desarrollo y la integración EvoDevo: precisiones y distinciones en torno al tema. Acta Biol Colomb 14S:151–168

    Google Scholar 

  • Martínez M, Esposito M (2014) Multilevel causation and the extended synthesis. Biol Theory 9:209–222

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1963) Animal species and evolution. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (2004) What makes biology unique? Considerations on the autonomy of a scientific discipline. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • McKinney ML, McNamara KJ (eds) (1991) Heterochrony: the evolution of ontogeny. Plenum Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Minelli A (2010) Evolutionary developmental biology does not offer a significant challenge to the neo-Darwinian paradigm. In: Ayala FJ, Malden RA (eds) Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology. Wiley, Massachusetts, pp 213–226

    Google Scholar 

  • Minelli A, Pradeu T (eds) (2014) Towards a theory of development. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Moczek AP (2012) The nature of nurture and the future of evodevo: toward a theory of developmental evolution. Integr Comp Biol 52:108–119

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB (2007a) Six memos for Evo-Devo. In: Laubichler MD, Maienschein J (eds) From embryology to Evo-Devo: a history of developmental evolution. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 499–524

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB (2007b) Evo-devo: extending the evolutionary synthesis. Nat Rev Genet 8:943–949

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB (2014) EvoDevo shapes the extended synthesis. Biol Theory 9:119–121

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB (2017) Why an extended evolutionary synthesis is necessary. Interface Focus 7(5):20170015. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsfs.2017.0015

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB, Newman SA (2005) The innovation triad: an EvoDevo agenda. J Exp Zool Mol Dev Evol 304:487–503

    Google Scholar 

  • Nei M (2013) Mutation-driven evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman SA (2003) From physics to development: the evolution of morphogenetic mechanisms. In: Müller GB, Newman SA (eds) Origination of organismal form. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 221–239

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman SA, Bhat R (2009) Dynamical patterning modules: a “pattern language” for development and evolution of multicellular form. Int J Dev Biol 53:693–705

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson DJ, Gawne R (2015) Neither logical empiricism nor vitalism, but organicism: what the philosophy of biology was. Hist Philos Life Sci 37:281–345

    Google Scholar 

  • Noble D (2015) Evolution beyond neo-Darwinism: a new conceptual framework. J Exp Biol 218:7–13

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Noble D, Jablonka E, Joyners MJ, Müller GB, Omholt SW (2014) Evolution evolves: physiology returns to centre stage. J Physiol 592:2237–2244

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Nuño de la Rosa L (2014) On the possible, the conceivable, and the actual in evolutionary theory. Biol Theory 9:221–228

    Google Scholar 

  • Nuño de la Rosa L (2017) Computing the extended synthesis: mapping the dynamics and conceptual structure of evolvability research front. J Exp Zool B Mol Dev Evol 328:395–411

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee FJ, Laland KN, Feldman MW (2003) Niche construction: the neglected process in evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S (1986) The ontogeny of information. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S, Griffiths PE, Gray RD (eds) (2001) Cycles of contingency: developmental systems and evolution. MIT Press, Massachusetts

    Google Scholar 

  • Palma H (2015) Origen, actualidad y prospectiva de la filosofía de la biología. CTS 28:123–140

    Google Scholar 

  • Pavličev M, Wagner GP (2012) A model of developmental evolution: selection, pleiotropy and compensation. Trends Ecol Evol 27:316–322

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Pavličev M, Wagner GP (2015) Evolutionary systems biology: shifting focus to the context-dependency of genetic effects. In: Martin LB, Ghalambor GK, Woods HA (eds) Integrative organismal biology. Wiley, Hoboken, pp 91–108

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi E (2008) Modernizing the modern synthesis. Science 321:196–197

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi E (2016) Templeton grant funds evolution rethink. Science 352:394–395

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson EL (2016) The life organic: the theoretical biology club and the roots of epigenetics. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Pievani T (2012) An evolving research programme: the structure of evolutionary theory from a lakatosian perspective. In: Fasolo A (ed) The theory of evolution and its impact. Springer, Italia, pp 211–228

    Google Scholar 

  • Pievani T (2016a) How to rethink evolutionary theory: a plurality of evolutionary patterns. Evol Biol 43:446–455. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11692-015-9338-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pievani T (2016b) Hierarchy theory and the extended synthesis debate. In: Eldredge N, Pievani T, Serrelli EM, Tëmkin I (eds) Evolutionary theory: a hierarchical perspective. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 351–364

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2007) Do we need an extended evolutionary synthesis? Evolution 61:2743–2749

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2009) An extended synthesis for evolutionary biology. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1168:218–228

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2018) Darwinism after the modern synthesis. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context. Research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 98–103

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M, Finkelman L (2014) The extended (evolutionary) synthesis debate: where science meets philosophy. Bioscience 64:511–516

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M, Müller GB (eds) (2010a) Evolution: the extended synthesis. MIT Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M, Müller GB (2010b) Elements of an extended evolutionary synthesis. In: Pigliucci M, Müller GB (eds) Evolution: the extended synthesis. MIT Press, Boston, pp 3–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Pradeu T, Laplane L, Prévot K, Hoguet T, Reynaud V, Fusco G, Minelli A, Orgogozo V, Vervoort M (2016) Defining “development”. Curr Top Dev Biol 117:171–183

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Raff RA, Wray GA (1989) Heterochrony: developmental mechanisms and evolutionary results. J Evol Biol 2:409–434

    Google Scholar 

  • Raj K (2013) Beyond postcolonialism…and postpositivism: circulation and the global history of science. Isis 104:337–347

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Rebeiz M, Patel NH, Hinman VF (2015) Unraveling the tangled skein: the evolution of transcriptional regulatory networks in development. Annu Rev Genomics Hum Genet 16:103–131. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-genom-091212-153423

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Reiss JO (2012) Footnotes to the synthesis? Metascience 21:163–166

    Google Scholar 

  • Shubin N, Tabin C, Carroll S (2009) Deep homology and the origins of evolutionary novelty. Nature 457:818–823

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sidlauskas B, Ganapathy G, Hazkani-Covo E, Jenkins KP, Lapp H, McCall LW, Price S, Scherle R, Spaeth PA, Kidd DM (2010) Linking big: the continuing promise of evolutionary synthesis. Evolution 64:871–880

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Smocovitis VB (1996) Unifying biology: the evolutionary synthesis and evolutionary biology. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Sommer RJ (2009) The future of Evo-Devo: model systems and evolutionary theory. Nat Rev Genet 10:416–422. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrg2567

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley SM (1981) The new evolutionary timetable. Fossils, genes, and the origin of species. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoltzfus A (2017) Why we don’t want another “synthesis”. Biol Direct 12:23. https://doi.org/10.1186/s13062-017-0194-1

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Suman F (2016) An updated evolutionary research programme for the evolution of language. Topoi. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9419-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Svensson EI (2018) On reciprocal causation in the evolutionary process. Evol Biol 45(1):1–14

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Tëmkin I, Eldredge N (2015) Networks and hierarchies: approaching complexity in evolutionary theory. In: Serrelli E, Gontier N (eds) Macroevolution: explanation, interpretation, evidence. Springer, Cham, pp 183–226

    Google Scholar 

  • True JR, Haag ES (2001) Developmental system drift and flexibility in evolutionary trajectories. Evol Dev 3:109–119

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • von Dassow G, Munro E (1999) Modularity in animal development and evolution: elements of a conceptual framework for EvoDevo. J Exp Zool 285:307–325

    Google Scholar 

  • Waddington CH (1969) Paradigm for an evolutionary process. In: Waddington CH (ed) Towards a theoretical biology, vol 2. International Union of Biological Sciences & Edinburgh University Press, Paris, pp 106–123

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (2000) What is the promise of developmental evolution? Part I: Why is developmental biology necessary to explain evolutionary innovations? J Exp Zool B Mol Dev Evol 288:95–98

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (2007) The developmental genetics of homology. Nat Rev Genet 8:473–479

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner A (2011) The origins of evolutionary innovations. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (2014) Homology, genes and evolutionary innovation. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (2015) Reinventing the organism: evolvability and homology in post-Dahlem evolutionary biology. In: Love AC (ed) Conceptual change in biology. Scientific and philosophical perspectives on evolution and development. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 327–342

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (2016) What is “homology thinking” and what is it for? J Exp Zool B Mol Dev Evol 326:3–8

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Wassermann GD (1981) On the nature of the theory of evolution. Philos Sci 48:416–437

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber BH (2011) Extending and expanding the Darwinian synthesis: the role of complex systems dynamics. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 42:75–81

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Welch JJ (2017) What’s wrong with evolutionary biology? Biol Philos 32:263–279

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitfield J (2008) Biological theory: postmodern evolution? Nature 455:281–284

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Wicken JS (1987) Evolution, thermodynamics and information: extending the Darwinian program. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins A (2014) “The genetic tool-kit”: the life-history of an important metaphor. In: Steelman JT (ed) Advances in evolutionary developmental biology. Wiley, Singapore, pp 1–14

    Google Scholar 

  • Willmore KE (2012) The body plan concept and its centrality in Evo-Devo. Evol Edu Outreach 5:219–230

    Google Scholar 

  • Winther RG (2015a) The structure of scientific theories. In: Zalta EN (ed) The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/structure-scientific-theories/. Accessed 12 July 2016

  • Winther RG (2015b) Evo-Devo as a trading zone. In: Love AC (ed) Conceptual change in biology: scientific and philosophical perspectives on evolution and development, boston studies in the philosophy of science, vol 307. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 459–482

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmer C (2016) Scientists seek to update evolution. Quanta magazine. https://www.quantamagazine.org/scientists-seek-to-update-evolution-20161122. Accessed 1 July 2017

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors acknowledge the advice and assistance of Fátima Sofía Ávila-Cascajares during the conception of Fig. 1, and thank Casandra Lizbeth Méndez-Martínez for her aid in the design of Fig. 1. Diana Martínez Almaguer and Julio César Montero Rojas (Graphic Design Unit, Instituto de Biología, UNAM) assisted in the design of all figures of the article. We also thank Mario Casanueva for discussions and his critical remarks about the structure of the EES. The comments and feedback received from Alan Love and Kevin Laland during the presentation of this work at the 2017 Meeting of the International Society for History, Philosophy and Social Studies of Biology (ISHPSSB) in São Paulo, Brazil, were valuable for the preparation of revised versions of this work; at the same meeting, we also benefited from conversations with Eva Jablonka, Marion Lamb and Jan Baedke about the sociological, epistemological and political dimensions involved in the EES debate. AFT is indebted to participants in the poster session of the Sixth Meeting of the European Society for Evolutionary Developmental Biology (Uppsala, July 2016), especially to Mark Jonas. AFT also thanks Francesco Suman for comments on an earlier version of this manuscript and discussions on the structure of the EES and the pluralist landscape of contemporary evolutionism (Washington D.C., September 2016). FVS acknowledges facilities provided by libraries at the Instituto de Biología, UNAM and other academic institutions in Mexico City, Uppsala and London during his long-term research projects on the historiography, epistemology and sociology of biology. Finally, we thank an anonymous reviewer for critical comments which substantially improved the original manuscript. The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest, and that they did not receive any specific funding during the research and writing of this work.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding authors

Correspondence to Alejandro Fábregas-Tejeda or Francisco Vergara-Silva.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fábregas-Tejeda, A., Vergara-Silva, F. The emerging structure of the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis: where does Evo-Devo fit in?. Theory Biosci. 137, 169–184 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12064-018-0269-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12064-018-0269-2

Keywords

Navigation