Skip to main content
Log in

Stage One of the Aristotelian Proof: A Critical Appraisal

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What explains change? Edward Feser argues in his ‘Aristotelian proof’ that the only adequate answer to these questions is ultimately in terms of an unchangeable, purely actual being. In this paper, I target the cogency of Feser’s reasoning to such an answer. In particular, I present novel paths of criticism—both undercutting and rebutting—against one of Feser’s central premises. I then argue that Feser’s inference that the unactualized actualizer lacks any potentialities contains a number of non-sequiturs.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Chains of causes/changes ordered per se are ones wherein the relevant causal power or property is wholly (concurrently) derivative in all secondary (non-first, non-fundamental) members of the chain. Such secondary members have the relevant causal power or property only derivatively and instrumentally; they do not possess it of themselves but merely transmit the causal power or property bestowed to them. To remove the primary member, then, is to simply collapse the causality of the chain.

  2. Note that the relevant sense of justification here attaches to the one who doesn’t already accept the argument/premise/assumption in question. The question is whether the argument—or, more accurately, its premises or what is said on their behalf—gives those who don’t already accept the argument (i.e., who don’t accept its premises or assumptions) sufficient reason or justification to change their mind and accept it.

  3. Note that in saying that something causes a reduction of potency to act, I am intending to refer to efficient causal actualization of the potential for the existence of the whole substance here, since that is precisely the kind of reduction of potency to act that concerns Feser in his Aristotelian proof.

  4. What’s more, we will see later that, plausibly, we need not even appeal to past states to explain present ones. I will provide (what I take to be) a plausible metaphysical account of per se chains on which the absence of a tendency to expire or annihilate, combined with a few other conditions, explains the present existence of the substance.

  5. Feser (2019).

  6. All it tells us is that (i) x is actual, and (ii) x has the potential to be otherwise. But the conjunction of (i) and (ii) neither means nor entails that x’s actuality consists in a present reduction of potentially existent to actually existent.

  7. Or, at least, an account of one necessary condition for such chains.

  8. An intrinsic causal factor or force would be something like a natural tendency, inclination, or disposition inherent to a thing; an extrinsic one would be something like the effect of gravity, friction, etc.

  9. I don’t mean net force in an expressly mechanistic or physical way (although such forces are sub-categories of what I mean). Instead, I just mean a causal factor or group of causal factors whose overall causal contribution is like a vector quantity insofar as it contributes toward a definite end state or outcome and is not counterbalanced by some other causal factor(s).

  10. The same seems, plausibly, to apply to the other examples of per se chains. For instance, the stone has net causal factors operating on it so as to keep it stationary (friction, gravitational and normal forces, and so on). A concurrent sustaining cause of the stone’s motion plausibly seems required precisely because such a cause contravenes the causal activity of the friction, gravity, etc. toward the definite outcome of stationary spatial position.

  11. C would therefore be like a vector quantity that counterbalances in the opposite ‘direction’ of what would otherwise be a net causal factor/force.

  12. This follows provided that we accept a kind of epistemic modus tollens (i.e., a kind of closure principle)—if we know that p entails q, and we know that we are inadequately justified in accepting q, then we know or are at least in a position to know that we are inadequately justified in accepting p.

  13. A ‘tendency’ does not only mean a probabilistic disposition—it could also mean an immediate reversion to another condition (or no condition at all, in the case of non-existence).

  14. Thanks to an anonymous referee for this objection.

  15. The underlying problem seems to be that we only have a single event here: photons’ presently bouncing off the moon. We don’t have two distinct events (which is dissimilar to per se chains of causation, wherein there are distinct events (or, perhaps, objects) subordinated to one another as causes and effects).

  16. Thus, if Feser wishes to locate existence within a per se chain, he must—in a principled, non-question-begging manner—point to some intrinsic or extrinsic fact about act-potency composites in virtue of which they require a counteracting vector in terms of per se causal sustenance. And this is something that—as I argued in the previous section—he has not (yet) done.

  17. Assuming, of course, that m is the present moment. This is in keeping with how Feser presents his argument.

  18. For articulations of the different models of God, especially what I’ve called ‘neo-classical theism’, see Timpe (2013), Mullins (2016), and Mullins (2020).

  19. More precisely, this is one prong of the three-pronged criticism of Feser’s inference.

References

  • Cohoe, C. (2013). There must be a first: Why Thomas Aquinas rejects infinite, essentially ordered, causal series. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 21(5), 838–856.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feser, E. (2013). Motion in Aristotle, Newton, and Einstein. In E. Feser (Ed.), Aristotle on Method and Metaphysics. Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Feser, E. (2014). Scholastic metaphysics: A contemporary introduction. Editiones Scholasticae.

  • Feser, E. (2017). Five proofs of the existence of God. Ignatius Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feser, E. (2019). Vallicella on existence-entailing relations and presentism. Blogspot. http://edwardfeser.blogspot.com/2019/04/vallicella-on-existence-entailing.html. Accessed 21 Feb 2020.

  • Mullins, R. T. (2016). The difficulty of demarcating panentheism. Sophia, 55, 325–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mullins, R. T. (2020). God and emotion. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schmid, J. C. (2021). Existential inertia and the Aristotelian proof. International Journal for Philosophy of Religionhttps://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-020-09773-9.

  • Timpe, K. (2013). Introduction to neo-classical theism. In J. Diller & A. Kasher (Eds.), Models of God and Alternative Ultimate Realities (pp. 197–206). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am thankful to two anonymous referees for helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joseph C. Schmid.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schmid, J.C. Stage One of the Aristotelian Proof: A Critical Appraisal. SOPHIA 60, 781–796 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-021-00835-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-021-00835-7

Keywords

Navigation