Skip to main content
Log in

Attending Together in Digital Environments

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Discussions of joint attention often focus on examples that involve multiple interacting thinkers who align their attention by triangulating upon an object (e.g., by pointing, gaze following, orienting, etc.). However, not all forms of attending together seem to involve this kind of interpersonal coordination. When an audience attends to a talk, they do not do so by engaging in the perspective-driven alignment of attention that is characteristic of joint attention. Nor do students learning in a digital environment (e.g., on Zoom) triangulate a perspective in the manner typical of joint attention. One might conclude that accounts of joint attention must be broader than have typically been proposed and cannot require coordinated interactions which draw upon the participant’s perspective. I argue that this argument fails because there are multiple forms of attending together, and the processes that enable collective attention in conference talks and Zoom classrooms are different from those that enable the more familiar interaction-based forms of joint attention. By distinguishing joint attention and collective attention, this essay seeks to better understand both the ways in which the digital environments demand a broader concept of joint attention, as well as the place of attending together in digital environments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Additional causes of Zoom fatigue include excessive amounts of close-up eye gaze, cognitive load, increased self-evaluation, and constraints on physical mobility. See Bailenson (2021) for discussion.

  2. Peacocke (2020) offers this apt summary.

  3. Standard anthologies on joint attention include Moore and Dunham (1995), Eilan et al. (2005), Seemann (2011) and Metcalfe and Terrace (2013). Mundy (2014) and Seemann (2019) provide monograph-length discussions.

  4. The literature on each of these topics is substantial. For example: Clark (1996) and Sabbagh and Baldwin (2005) discuss the importance of joint attention in language development, while Mundy (2014) discusses autism and joint attention, and Milward and Carpenter (2018) discuss joint attention and joint action. Tomasello (2019) develops an account of distinctively human language use and social cognition in which joint attention features prominently.

  5. See Tomasello (1995) and Peacocke (2005) for variations on this approach.

  6. See Campbell (2005) and Seeman (2019) for variants of this approach.

  7. Eilan et al. (2005) and Seemann (2011) each include multiple essays that take up these issues.

  8. Of course, relaxing these assumptions raises the question of how broadly we should conceptualize joint attention. See Sect. 3 for further discussion.

  9. See Peacocke (2005) and Campbell (2005) for an informative discussion of openness, as well as Wilby (2010), Campbell (2011) and Seemann (2019) for further thoughts on the matter.

  10. The phrases used in my discussion of (b), like ‘the result of’ and ‘due to’, could be read as either making a causal or a constitutive claim. Drawing this distinction unambiguously can be challenging in discussions of joint attention because some of the processes involved, like attention monitoring, might play a role in both bringing about and maintaining joint attention. That said, my use of these phrases should not be read as merely making claims about the causes of joint attention.

  11. The full role that eye-contact, gaze following, and gaze alternation play in face-to-face interaction is complex. See Kleinke (1986), Flom et al. (2007) and Hessels (2020) for informative overviews.

  12. Bailenson (2021) and Troje (2023) discuss the bearing of eye contact and visual gaze on videoconferencing technology.

  13. At least not to the extent that is typically taken to be required for joint attention.

  14. Battich et al. (2020) develop a multi-sensory account of joint attention. Section 5 discusses the potential impact of multi-sensory accounts in more detail.

  15. See Siposova and Carpenter (2019) for a thorough characterization of the disagreements found in the scientific literature, why it matters, and an attempt to resolve it.

  16. Gallagher (2011) and (2020) for an enactivist account; Campbell (2005, 2011) for the primitivist account, and Tomasello (1995) and Peacocke (2005) for variations on the cognitivist account. It seems worth noting the refreshingly thin boundary between scientific and philosophical work on joint attention.

  17. A non-exhaustive list of the relevant sciences includes psycholinguistics, cognitive and developmental psychology, comparative psychology, and the social neurosciences.

  18. Though Seemann would, presumably, identify each as a variety of joint attention, as opposed to distinguishing joint attention from collective attention. A more thorough comparison between Seemann’s account and the one developed here outstrips the focus on this essay.

  19. Again, see Bailenson (2021) and Troje (2023) for more detailed proposals.

  20. Of course, there are other factors that might contribute to the ways in which digital environments seem to challenge our ability to jointly attend. But the proponent of expanding joint attention seems forced to claim that although joint attention itself is not really challenged, other related things are. This debunking explanation seems less satisfying than capturing the real challenge that digital environments pose to joint attention.

  21. To be clear: The worry about psychological heterogeneity is not merely about whether joint attention is multiply realized but about whether the psychological processes that realize these varieties of attending together exhibit functional differences that substantial enough to fracture them into multiple psychological kinds.

  22. Akhtar and Gernsbacher (2008) develop this criticism. They add that non-Western cultures might rely less heavily on visual cues in establishing joint attention, thus the visual bias might result in a somewhat Western-centric understanding of joint attention.

  23. To be clear, Battich et al. (2020) don’t develop this criticism directly. It is raised here as a plausible extension of what they do say.

  24. Fortney (2019) and (2020) catalog some accounts of intellectual attention and defend a preferred account.

  25. See Chun et al. (2011) for further elaboration of the distinction.

References

  • Akhtar N, Gernsbacher MA (2008) On privileging the role of Gaze in Infant Social Cognition. Child Dev Perspect 2(2):59–65

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Bailenson JN (2021) Nonverbal overload: a theoretical argument for the causes of Zoom fatigue. Technol Mind Behav 2(1). https://doi.org/10.1037/tmb0000030

  • Battich L, Fairhurst M, Deroy O (2020) Coordinating attention requires coordinated senses. Psychon Bull Rev 27:1126–1138

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Botero M (2016) Tactless scientists: ignoring touch in the study of joint attention. Philosophical Psychol 29(8):1200–1214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell J (2005) Joint attention and common knowledge. In: Eilan N, Hoerl C, McCormack T, Roessler J (eds) Joint attention: communication and other minds: issues in philosophy and psychology. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 287–297

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell J (2011) An object-dependent perspective on joint attention. In: Seemann A (ed) Joint attention: New Developments in psychology, philosophy of mind, and Social Neuroscience. MIT Press, pp 415–430

  • Chun M, Golumb J, Turk-Browne N (2011) A taxonomy of external and internal attention. Ann Rev Psychol 62:73–101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark H (1996) Using Language. Cambridge University Press

  • Cockayne J, Salger G (2021) Can the Presence of God be an object of joint attention? Theological Puzzles (Issue 2). https://www.theo-puzzles.ac.uk/2021/06/05/cockayne-salter/

  • Eilan N (2005) Joint attention, communication and Mind. In: Eilan N, Hoerl C, McCormack T, Roessler J (eds) Joint attention: communication and other minds: issues in philosophy and psychology. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 1–33

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Eilan N, Hoerl C, McCormack T, Roessler J (eds) (2005) Joint attention: communication and other minds: issues in philosophy and psychology. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Flom R, Lee K, Muir D (eds) (2007) Gaze-Following: its development and significance. Psychology Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fortney M (2019) Conceptualizing intellectual attention. Theory & Psychology 29(6):775–788

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fortney M (2020) Unity in the scientific study of intellectual attention. Can J Philos 50(4):444–459

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2011) Interactive coordination in joint attention. In: Seemann A (ed) Joint attention: New Developments in psychology, philosophy of mind, and Social Neuroscience. MIT Press, pp 293–306

  • Gallagher S (2020) Action and Interaction. Oxford University Press

  • Hessels RS (2020) How does gaze to faces support face-to-face interaction? A review and perspective. Psychonomic Bull Rev 27:856–881

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kleinke CL (1986) Gaze and Eye Contact: A Research Review. Psychol Bull 100(1):78–100

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Metcalfe J, Terrace HS (eds) (2013) Agency and Joint attention. Oxford University Press

  • Milward SJ, Carpenter M (2018) Joint action and joint attention: drawing parallels between the literatures. Soc Pers Psychol Compass 12:e12377

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mundy P (2014) Autism and joint attention. Guildford Press

  • Nguyen CT (2022) The Word on Wordle. The LA Times, 21 January 2022

  • Peacocke C (2005) Joint attention: its Nature, Reflexivity, and relation to common knowledge. In: Eilan N, Hoerl C, McCormack T, Roessler J (eds) Joint attention: communication and other minds: issues in philosophy and psychology. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 298–324

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke A (2020) Another reason zoom is so draining. PhilosophyTalk org, 18 August 2020.

  • Sabbaugh M, Baldwin D (2005) Understanding the Roel of communicative intentions in Word Learning. In: Eilan N, Hoerl C, McCormack T, Roessler J (eds) Joint attention: communication and other minds: issues in philosophy and psychology. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 165–184

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Seemann A (ed) (2011) Joint attention: New Developments in psychology, philosophy of mind, and Social Neuroscience. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Seemann A (2019) The Shared World: Perceptual Common Knowledge, demonstrative communication, and Social Space. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Siposova B, Carpenter M (2019) A new look at joint attention and common knowledge. Cognition 189:260–274

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (1995) Joint attention as Social Cognition. In: Moore C, Dunham PJ (eds) Joint attention: its origins and Role in Development. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, pp 103–130

  • Tomasello M (2019) Becoming human. Oxford University Press

  • Troje NF (2023) Zoom disrupts eye contact behavior: problems and solutions. TRENDS in Cognitive Science 27(5):417–419

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilby M (2010) The simplicity of mutual knowledge. Philosophical Explorations 13(2):83–100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilby M (2023) The form and function of joint attention within joint action. Philosophical Psychol 36(1):134–161

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bryan Chambliss.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no conflict of interest to declare.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Chambliss, B. Attending Together in Digital Environments. Topoi (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-024-10012-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-024-10012-3

Keywords

Navigation