Skip to main content
Log in

Practice for Wisdom: On the Neglected Role of Case-Based Critical Reflection

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Despite increased philosophical and psychological work on practical wisdom, contemporary interdisciplinary wisdom research provides few specifics about how to develop wisdom (Kristjánsson 2022). This lack of practically useful guidance is due in part to the difficulty of determining how to combine the tools of philosophy and psychology to develop a plausible account of wisdom as a prescriptive ideal. Modeling wisdom on more ordinary forms of expertise is promising, but skill models of wisdom (Annas 2011; De Caro et al. 2018; Swartwood 2013b; Tsai 2023) have been challenged on the grounds that there are important differences between wisdom and expert skills (Hacker-Wright 2015, p. 986; Kristjánsson 2015, pp. 98, 101; Stichter 2015, 2016, 2018). I’ll argue that we can both vindicate the promise of skill models of wisdom and begin to specify practically useful strategies for wisdom development by attending to a reflective process that I call Case-Based Critical Reflection. I begin by demonstrating the process as it arose in a notable example from everyday life, illustrating how the process can be usefully applied to a case study of interest to wisdom scientists, and explaining its philosophical pedigree. After isolating the key features that make it relevant to wisdom development, I argue that attending to the importance of Critical Reflection can defuse prominent objections to skill models of wisdom.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The kind of reflection Gandhi is recommending thus aims at developing and testing one’s own existing moral beliefs and judgments by taking seriously alternative views in order to yield guidance about the concrete circumstances of one’s own life. So far, then, the process resembles what psychologist Igor Grossmann and colleagues call Perspectival Metacognition (Grossmann et al. 2020, p. 109). Perspectival Metacognition (PMC) refers to “aspects of metacognition” that “afford greater understanding of and balance between potentially divergent interests on the issue at hand,” including epistemic humility, consideration of diverse perspectives, and balance of viewpoints (ibid). Nevertheless, this process is not sufficient to provide specific and plausible guidance for concrete situations (Kristjánsson et al. 2021; Swartwood 2020), such as the nuisance monkeys. Metacognitive processes such as epistemic humility and consideration of diverse perspectives are parts of good decision-making about what one ought to do precisely because they are necessary for most intellectual or decision-making challenges humans face. Doctors wouldn’t succeed at diagnosing illnesses if they didn’t attend to the limits of their knowledge or identify and examine competing explanations of clinical data. Yet medical schools surely need to supplement these laudable intellectual habits with discipline-specific reasoning skills if they’re going to produce accomplished diagnosticians.

  2. Cp. Grossmann et al. (2020, p. 109): “On their own, moral aspirations such as fairness, justice, loyalty, or purity are abstract concepts, void of pragmatic nuances necessary to implement moral concerns in a person’s life.”

  3. See, for example, Baehr (2022), Kotzee et al (2021), Siegel (2018).

  4. Critical Reflection thus falls into what Stichter (2021, p. 105) calls the “goal setting” and “reflecting after acting” phases of action, which he argues are the domain of wisdom.

  5. For example, the process requires the addition of strategies for identifying plausible descriptive beliefs about how the world is and works, strategies for obtaining self-knowledge, strategies for reflecting on what is conducive to one’s own well-being (Tiberius 2023), strategies for understanding one’s own and others’ behavior and mental states (Hursthouse 2006), and so on.

  6. Compare what Kristjánsson et al (2021, pp. 246–47) call the “integrative function” and the “blueprint function” of phronesis.

  7. See also Wright et al (2020, 24), who endorse Russell’s point that “practical wisdom employs the same global understanding of the human good that is relevant to every virtue,”; Kamtekar (2004, p. 460): practical wisdom organizes a person’s “desires, beliefs about the world, and ultimate goals and values” and does so in such a way that a person’s “motivations are organized so that they do not conflict, but support one another”; and Stichter (2018, 378): “The role of practical wisdom is to make value judgments regarding what it is to live well, what constitutive ends make up living well, and what other ends we could pursue consistent with that overall conception of living well.” Stichter argues elsewhere that “wisdom … requires reflection on our values, goals, and practices, not on how to balance existing goals in particular situations (which is going to be the work of other virtuous skills)” (2021, p. 105). This suggests that Stichter sees only what I have called the critical function as essential to wisdom, while the integrative and specificatory functions are the domain of the character virtues. I find other ways of conceptualizing the relationship between wisdom and the virtues more compelling (De Caro et al. 2018), but that is not essential for my argument here.

  8. Importantly, the process of Critical Reflection can be given more principled or more particularist interpretations, depending on which of the two case-based reasoning strategies are emphasized. If we emphasized the strategy of testing analogies, Critical Reflection could be a process that focuses heavily on the context and details of specific situations. If we emphasized the strategy of developing principles, Critical Reflection could be a process that focuses heavily on general principles that apply across a range of situations. For my purposes here, I will assume only that Critical Reflection needs to include some mix of the two strategies.

  9. Compare what Tsai (2023, Chap. 1.1) calls the Species Thesis (“wisdom is a species of skill”) and The Analogy Thesis (“wisdom is analogous to skill”). Tsai argues that “[t]he Analogy Thesis is too modest because it does not provide or imply any ontological status for wisdom” (ibid). Depending on what the analogy is supposed to show, however, Tsai may be underselling the power of the Analogy Thesis to tell us important things about wisdom.

  10. For similar accounts of the logical structure of analogical reasoning in philosophy of religion and philosophy of science, see Ratzsch and Koperski (2023), and Waters (1986).

  11. Tsai offers a different reply, arguing that the presence of expertise in low-validity environments casts doubt on the strict necessity of feedback for expertise (2023, Chap. 5.3), and the fact that the goal of living well can be analyzed into a hierarchy of sub-goals shows that it is possible to get adequate feedback on wisdom (2023, Chap. 5.3–5.5). My goal is to show that this reply is more compelling if it is illustrated using a specific reflective process, like Critical Reflection, that can provide specificatory, integrative, and critical feedback on our judgments about how to live well.

  12. De Caro et al (2018) make a similar point about wisdom and the character virtues.

  13. An earlier version of this argument was presented in an invited webinar hosted by the Aretai Center on Virtues on 14 April 2023. I thank Maria Silvia Vaccarezza for the invitation and Prof. Vaccarezza and the other participants for their thoughtful and generous feedback on my argument. Thanks go to Ian Stoner for characteristically incisive feedback on an earlier draft of the paper and to Avani Shah f or helpful discussion of additional cases where applying the general value of ahimsa can be challenging. I also benefitted from the feedback of two anonymous reviewers.

References

  • Annas J (2011) Intelligent virtue. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arras JD (1991) Getting down to cases: the revival of casuistry in bioethics. J Med Philos 16(1):29–51

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Baehr J (2022) Deep in thought: a practical guide to teaching for intellectual virtues. Harvard Education Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • De Caro M, Vaccarezza MS, Niccoli A (2018) Phronesis as ethical expertise: naturalism of second nature and the unity of virtue. J Value Inq 52:287–305

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels N (1979) Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics. J Philos 76(5):256–282

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels N (2016) Reflective equilibrium. In: Zalta EN (ed) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Winter, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gandhi MK (2019) The power of nonviolent resistance: selected writings. Penguin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Gomberg P (1990) Patriotism is like racism. Ethics 101(1):144–150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grossmann I, Weststrate NM, Ardelt M, Brienza JP, Dong M, Ferrari M, Fournier MA, Hu CS, Nusbaum HC, Vervaeke J (2020) The Science of wisdom in a polarized world: knowns and unknowns. Psychol Inq 31(2):103–133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker-Wright J (2015) Skill, Practical wisdom, and ethical naturalism. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 18(5):983–993

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse R (2006) Practical wisdom: a mundane account. Proc Aristot Soc 106(1):285–309

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson D (2005) Seeing by feeling: virtues, skills, and moral perception. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 8(4):387–409

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Jonsen AR, Stephen T, Stephen ET (1988) The abuse of casuistry: a history of moral reasoning. Univ of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamtekar R (2004) Situationism and virtue ethics on the content of our character. Ethics 114(3):458–491

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kotzee B, Adam Carter J, Siegel H (2021) Educating for intellectual virtue: a critique from action guidance. Episteme 18(2):177–199

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson K (2015) Aristotelian character education. Routledge, Milton Park

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson K (2022) Teaching phronesis to aspiring police officers: some preliminary philosophical, developmental and pedagogical reflections. Int J Ethics Educ 7(2):289–305

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson K, Fowers B, Darnell C, Pollard D (2021) Phronesis (practical wisdom) as a type of contextual integrative thinking. Rev Gen Psychol 25(3):239–257

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nathanson S (1989) In defense of" moderate patriotism". Ethics 99(3):535–552

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Navarini C, Indraccolo A, Brunetti R (2021) Practical wisdom and generalization: a theoretical and empirical investigation on the effects of limited information. In: Caro MD, Vaccarezza MS (eds) Practical wisdom. Routledge, Milton Park, pp 114–137

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratzsch D, Koperski J (2023) Teleological arguments for god’s existence. In: Zalta EN, Nodelman U (eds) The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel H (2018) Justice and justification. Theory Res Educ 16(3):308–329. https://doi.org/10.1177/1477878518801753

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stichter M (2015) Practical skills and practical wisdom in virtue. Australas J Philos 94(3):435–448

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stichter M (2016) The role of motivation and wisdom in virtues as skills. In: Annas J, Narvaez D, Snow NE (eds) Developing the virtues: integrating perspectives. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Stichter M (2018) The skillfulness of virtue: improving our moral And epistemic lives. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stichter M (2021) Differentiating the skills of practical wisdom. In: Miller CB (ed) Practical wisdom. Routledge, Milton Park, pp 96–113

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoner I, Swartwood J (2021) Doing practical ethics. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Swartwood J (2013a) Cultivating practical wisdom. PhD Dissertation, University of Minnesota, Minneapolis. http://conservancy.umn.edu/bitstream/154543/1/Swartwood_umn_0130E_13707.pdf

  • Swartwood J (2013b) Wisdom as an expert skill. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 16(3):511–528. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-012-9367-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swartwood J (2020) Can we measure practical wisdom? J Moral Educ 49(1):71–97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swartwood J, Tiberius V (2019) Philosophical foundations of wisdom. In: Sternberg RJ, Glück J (eds) The Cambridge handbook of wisdom. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 10–39

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tiberius V (2023) What do you want out of life? In: What do you want out of life? Princeton University Press

  • Tsai C-H (2020) Phronesis and techne: the skill model of wisdom defended. Australas J Philos 98(2):234–247

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsai C-H (2023) Wisdom: a skill theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waters CK (1986) Taking analogical inference seriously: darwin’s argument from artificial selection. Proc Bienn Meet Philos Sci Assoc 1986:502–513

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright JC, Warren MT, Snow NE (2020) Understanding virtue: theory and measurement. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Young T (2001) Overconsumption and procreation: are they morally equivalent? J Appl Philos 18:183–192

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

No funding was received to assist with the preparation of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jason D. Swartwood.

Ethics declarations

Competing Interests

The author has no competing interests to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Swartwood, J.D. Practice for Wisdom: On the Neglected Role of Case-Based Critical Reflection. Topoi (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-023-10000-z

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-023-10000-z

Keywords

Navigation