Skip to main content
Log in

Varieties of Metalinguistic Negotiation

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In both co-authored and solo-authored work over the past decade, we have developed the idea of “metalinguistic negotiation”. On our view, metalinguistic negotiation is a type of dispute in which speakers appear to use (rather than explicitly mention) a term in conflicting ways to put forward views about how that very term should be used. In this paper, we explore four possible dimensions of variation among metalinguistic negotiations, and the interactions among those dimensions. These types of variation matter for understanding the nature, and the potential range, of the phenomenon of metalinguistic negotiation. As an illustration of the latter, we argue in our concluding section that understanding the full range of forms that metalinguistic negotiations can take has implications for debates about the “implementation” of conceptual engineering proposals.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. For the relevant co-authored work summarized in this paragraph, see Plunkett and Sundell (2013a, b, 2014, 2021a, b). We both develop and expand on the idea of metalinguistic negotiation in solo-authored work, including in Plunkett (2015, 2016), Sundell (2011a, b, 2016, 2017). We also further develop our views in recent co-authored work with Rachel Sterken (2023).

  2. See Plunkett and Sundell (2013a, b).

  3. For further discussion about the metaethics case, concerning the argument put forward in Horgan and Timmons (1993), see Plunkett and Sundell (2013a), and for further discussion focused on philosophy of law, regarding the argument put forward in Dworkin (1986), see Plunkett and Sundell (2013a).

  4. See Plunkett and Sundell (2021b).

  5. For further discussion, see Plunkett and Sundell (2021b).

  6. Our discussion below draws together ideas presented in the works cited in the first footnote, while closely following the basic line of presentation from Plunkett and Sundell (2013a).

  7. Barker (2002).

  8. Burgess and Plunkett (2013a, b).

  9. On the understanding of “conceptual ethics” we are working with, conceptual ethics is sometimes tied to “conceptual engineering”, which (put roughly) connects conceptual ethics to work on the design and implementation of proposed conceptual changes. For further discussion of this connection, see Burgess and Plunkett (2020) and Cappelen and Plunkett (2020). Later in this paper, we turn to some issues about the implementation aspect of conceptual engineering projects.

  10. For connected discussion, see Burgess and Plunkett (2013a, b), and Cappelen and Plunkett (2020).

  11. See, for example, our work in Plunkett and Sundell (2013a, 2021a, b).

  12. For more discussion of the points in what follows, see Plunkett and Sundell (2013a, b), Sundell (2011a, 2016), and Plunkett (2015).

  13. For connected discussion of this kind of idea, see Burgess and Plunkett (2013b), Plunkett and Sundell (2013a), Sundell (2011b), Plunkett (2015), Haslanger (2000), and Thomasson (2020).

  14. For example, consider the framework that Barker develops in Barker (2013). For further discussion, see Plunkett and Sundell (2021b).

  15. For some different recent takes on this issue (or closely connected ones, about similar kinds of disputes), see Mankowitz (2021), Thomasson (2016), Khoo (2020), Belleri (2017), Kocurek et al. (2020), Bolinger (2022), and Soria-Ruiz (2023). We briefly discuss some of our own ideas on this issue in Plunkett and Sundell (2021b).

  16. For previous work where we emphasize this point, see Plunkett and Sundell (2013a, b, 2021a).

  17. For Ludlow’s original discussion of the case, see Ludlow (2008). For some of our previous discussion of this case, see Plunkett and Sundell (2013a, b).

  18. In this paper, we use small caps (e.g., cat) to name concepts, italics (e.g., cat) to introduce terminology or for rhetorical stress, single quotes (e.g., ‘cat’) to mention linguistic expressions, and double quotes (e.g., “cat”) for quoting other authors, “scare quoting”, simultaneous use and mention, and other informal uses.

  19. See Plunkett and Sundell (2013a).

  20. Versions of this goal, and the previous one, are arguably at the core of a number of cases we have discussed at length in previous work; including metalinguistic disputes about how best to use philosophical or scientific terms. See Plunkett and Sundell (2013a), Plunkett (2015), and Sundell (2011a).

  21. In much of our previous work we have emphasized the importance of differences between these kinds of aims and the aims of engaging in successful inquiry. See, for example, our discussion in Plunkett and Sundell (2013a).

  22. Consider Crocodile Dundee’s statement, insulting a blade-wielding interlocutor who had attempted to appear threatening: “That’s not a knife. This is a knife.” For recent work that emphasizes the kinds of practical issues about domination and power in metalinguistic negotiation (or connected disputes involving conceptual ethics and conceptual engineering), see Shields (2021) and Podosky (2022). These issues are also prominent in Ludlow’s discussion in (Ludlow 2014).

  23. For connected discussion, see Davies (2021). See also related ideas in Eidelson (2023), drawing on Nunberg (2018).

  24. We discuss this more in Plunkett and Sundell (2021a).

  25. This is a point that we have explored in greater detail in previous work. See Plunkett and Sundell (2014, 2021b). We emphasize in that earlier work that it’s consistent with our account not only that speakers engaged in a given metalinguistic negotiation not be aware of it, but indeed that they might vigorously resist such a characterization. As we have argued, there are theoretical resources available not only to accommodate speakers’ lack of awareness, but also to provide a deflationary account of that resistance. See Plunkett and Sundell (2021b). For recent critical discussion of our views here (which it is beyond the scope of this paper to address), see Abreu (2023) and Odrowąż-Sypniewska (2023).

  26. For connected discussion, see Plunkett and Sundell (2021a).

  27. For previous discussion, see Plunkett and Sundell (2013a) and Plunkett (2015).

  28. This point connects to the phenomenon of “code words” (sometimes also discussed as “dog whistles”), and suggests ways in which metalinguistic negotiation might connect to some instances of the use of such words. For some of the recent discussion here on “code words”, and how their use ties into propaganda and other important socially important types of speech, see Khoo (2017), Saul (2018), Stanley (2015), and Quaranto (2022).

  29. We emphasize this point in Plunkett and Sundell (2013a).

  30. For discussion, see Burgess and Plunkett (2013a, b), and Cappelen and Plunkett (2020).

  31. See Plunkett and Sundell (2013a, 2021a), and Plunkett (2015).

  32. See Ludlow (2014).

  33. Thanks to Valerie Friedmann for discussion. This illustration obviously oversimplifies the realities of city planning and development review.

  34. Our points above draw from Plunkett (2015).

  35. Our inclusion of these issues is tied to the broad uses of “normative” and “evaluative” that we favor for characterizing conceptual ethics. For connected discussion, see McPherson and Plunkett (2017).

  36. We note this issue in Plunkett and Sundell (2021a). For a view that analyzes “should” judgments in terms of “what to do” judgments, see Gibbard (2003). For views on which these are importantly distinct kinds of judgment, see Hieronymi (2009) and Southwood (2013).

  37. For connected discussion, see Hansen (2019), Khoo and Knobe (2016), and Kocurek et al. (2020).

  38. Shields (2021).

  39. See Plunkett and Sundell (2013a, b).

  40. This point matters not just for potential critiques of our views, such as Shields’s, but also just for understanding how our framework relates to other discussion of cases of metalinguistic disputes that differ from the cases we have focused on. For example, we think that in light of the discussion in this essay, our framework can incorporate key cases discussed by Podosky (2022) and Davies (2021).

  41. For further discussion of this understanding of conceptual engineering and its connections to conceptual ethics, see Burgess and Plunkett (2020) and Cappelen and Plunkett (2020). Note that there are subtle differences between these accounts. However, those differences won’t matter to us here. For a range of other accounts of what “conceptual engineering” is, see the papers collected in Burgess et al. (2020).

  42. For a view that emphasizes these larger kind of ambitions for key projects in conceptual engineering within philosophy (including his reading of certain paradigmatic examples of such projects), see Cappelen (2018). For arguments that push back against the idea that important conceptual engineering projects (including ones that are often taken to be paradigmatic examples of conceptual engineering within philosophy, such as Haslanger (2000)) really have this ambition, see Pinder (2021) and Riggs (2019).

  43. Koslow (2022) discusses Kevin Scharp’s proposals regarding truth (in Scharp (2013)) as a limiting case with respect to the small size of the linguistic population targeted, despite Scharp’s proposal still being directed at a group. (Namely, logicians, or those facing “liar-shaped predicaments”.) If Scharp’s proposal—directed at a small group, but a group nonetheless—is a limiting case, then changes directed at individual speakers or specific conversations—like the changes advocated in classic cases of metalinguistic negotiation—are unlikely to even register as cases of conceptual engineering.

  44. For further discussion of these (and other) kinds of variation here, see Burgess and Plunkett (2013a, b), and Cappelen and Plunkett (2020).

  45. See Scharp (2013) and Carnap (1947/1956).

  46. Sterken (2020).

  47. Sterken (2020, p. 420, emphasis Sterken’s).

  48. Sterken (2020, p. 420).

  49. Sterken (2020, p. 418).

  50. Jorem (2021, p. 190).

  51. Queloz and Bieber (2021).

  52. Koslow (2022).

  53. This might not be so, however, for Cappelen (2018)’s discussion of metalinguistic negotiation and conceptual engineering. Even there, however, we can take his comments to reflect a broader skepticism about metalinguistic negotiation, and a broader pessimism about intentional semantic revision, rather than being focused on the view that metalinguistic negotiations are too limited in scope to bear on projects in conceptual engineering.

References

  • Abreu P (2023) Metalinguistic negotiation, speaker error, and charity. Topoi. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-023-09910-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker C (2002) The dynamics of vagueness. Linguist Philos 25:1–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker C (2013) Negotiating taste. Inquiry 56(2–3):240–257

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Belleri D (2017) Verbalism and metalinguistic negotiation in ontological disputes. Philos Stud 174(9):2211–2226

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolinger RJ (2022) Metalinguistic negotiations in moral disagreement. Inquiry 65(3):352–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess A, Plunkett D (2013a) Conceptual ethics I. Philos Compass 8(12):1091–1101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess A, Plunkett D (2013b) Conceptual ethics II. Philos Compass 8(12):1102–1110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess A, Plunkett D (2020) On the relation between conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics. Ratio 33(4):281–294

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess A, Cappelen H, Plunkett D (2020) Conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen H (2018) Fixing language: an essay on conceptual engineering. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen H, Plunkett D (2020) A guided tour of conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics. In: Burgess A, Cappelen H, Plunkett D (eds) Conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 1–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R (1947/1956) Meaning and necessity: a study in semantics and modal logic. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Davies A (2021) Identity display: another motive for metalinguistic disagreement. Inquiry 64(8):861–882

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1986) Law’s empire. Belknap Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Eidelson B (2023) The etiquette of equality. Philos Public Aff 51(2):97–139

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard A (2003) Thinking how to live. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen N (2019) Metalinguistic proposals. Inquiry 1–2:1–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger S (2000) Gender and race: (what) are they? (What) do we want them to be? Noûs 34(1):31–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hieronymi P (2009) The will as reason. Philos Perspect 23(1):201–220

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan T, Timmons M (1993) New wave moral realism meets moral twin Earth. In: Heil J (ed) Rationality, morality, and self-interest. Rowan and Littlefield Publishers, Lanham, pp 115–133

    Google Scholar 

  • Jorem S (2021) Conceptual engineering and the implementation problem. Inquiry 64(1–2):186–211

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khoo J (2017) Code words in political discourse. Philos Top 45(2):33–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khoo J (2020) Quasi indexicals. Philos Phenomenol Res 100(1):26–53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khoo J, Knobe J (2016) Moral disagreement and moral semantics. Noûs 50(2):109–143

    Google Scholar 

  • Kocurek AW, Jerzak E, Rudolph RE (2020) Against conventional wisdom. Philos Imprint 20(22):1–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslow A (2022) Meaning change and changing meaning. Synthese 200(2):1–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow P (2008) Cheap contextualism. Philos Issues 18:104–129

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow P (2014) Living words: meaning undetermination and the dynamic lexicon. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mankowitz P (2021) How to have a metalinguistic dispute. Synthese 199(3–4):5603–5622

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McPherson T, Plunkett D (2017) The nature and explanatory ambitions of metaethics. In: McPherson T, Plunkett D (eds) The Routledge handbook of metaethics. Routledge, New York, pp 1–25

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nunberg G (2018) The social life of slurs. In: Fogal D, Harris D, Moss M (eds) New work on speech acts. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Odrowąż-Sypniewska J (2023) Spicy, tall, and metalinguistic negotiations. Topoi. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-023-09930-5

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinder M (2021) Conceptual engineering, metasemantic externalism and speaker-meaning. Mind 130(517):141–163

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plunkett D (2015) Which concepts should we use? Metalinguistic negotiations and the methodology of philosophy. Inquiry 58(7–8):828–874

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plunkett D (2016) Negotiating the meaning of “law”: The metalinguistic dimension of the dispute over legal positivism. Leg Theory 22(3–4):205–275

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plunkett D, Sundell T (2013a) Disagreement and the semantics of normative and evaluative terms. Philosophers’ Imprint 13(23):1–37

    Google Scholar 

  • Plunkett D, Sundell T (2013b) Dworkin’s interpretivism and the pragmatics of legal disputes. Leg Theory 19(3):242–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plunkett D, Sundell T (2014) Antipositivist arguments from legal thought and talk: the metalinguistic response. In: Hubb G, Lind D (eds) Pragmatism, law, and language. Routledge, New York, pp 56–75

    Google Scholar 

  • Plunkett D, Sundell T (2021) Metalinguistic negotiation and speaker error. Inquiry 64(1–2):142–167

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plunkett D, Sundell T (2021) Metalinguistic negotiation and matters of language: a response to cappelen. Inquiry. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2021.1983456

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plunkett D, Sterken RK, Sundell T (2023) Generics and metalinguistic negotiation. Synthese 201(50):1–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Podosky P-M (2022) Agency, power, and injustice in metalinguistic disagreement. Philos Quart 72(2):1–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quaranto A (2022) Dog whistles, covertly coded speech, and the practices that enable them. Synthese 200(4):1–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Queloz M, Bieber F (2021) Conceptual engineering and the politics of implementation. Pac Philos Q 3:670–691

    Google Scholar 

  • Riggs J (2019) Conceptual engineers shouldn’t worry about semantic externalism. Inquiry. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2019.1675534

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul J (2018) Dogwhistles, political manipulation, and philosophy of language. In: Fogal D, Harris DW, Moss M (eds) New work on speech acts. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 360–383

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharp K (2013) Replacing truth. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shields M (2021) Conceptual domination. Synthese 199(5–6):15043–15067

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soria-Ruiz A (2023) Metalinguistic usage is not conversational implicature. Topoi

  • Southwood N (2013) “The thing to do” implies “can”. Noûs 47(3):61–72

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley J (2015) How propaganda works. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sterken RK (2020) Linguistic interventions and transformative communicative disruption. In: Cappelen H (ed) Conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 417–434

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sundell T (2011a) Disagreement, error, and an alternative to reference magnetism. Austral J Philos 90(4):743–759

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sundell T (2011b) Disagreements about taste. Philos Stud 155(2):267–288

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sundell T (2016) The tasty, the bold, and the beautiful. Inquiry 59(6):793–818

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sundell T (2017) Aesthetic negotiation. In: Young J (ed) The semantics of aesthetic judgment. Oxford University Press, New York City, pp 82–105

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson AL (2016) Metaphysical disputes and metalinguistic negotiation. Anal Philos 57(4):1–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson AL (2020) A pragmatic method for normative conceptual work. In: Burgess A, Cappelen H, Plunkett D (eds) Conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 435–458

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Pedro Abreu, Chris Barker, Alexis Burgess, Elisabeth Camp, Herman Cappelen, Andy Egan, Jesse Ferraioli, Valerie Friedmann, Sean Kim, Devontae Lacasse, Zachary Lang, Peter Ludlow, Tristram McPherson, Mark Richard, Adrian Russian, Rachel Sterken, Giulia Terzian, Zoe Thierfelder, Amie Thomasson, Fangzhou Yu, anonymous referees, and audiences at the Nova University of Lisbon and the University of Warsaw for helpful discussion about ideas in this paper or for feedback on previous drafts of this paper.

Funding

Funding information is not applicable/No funding was received.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Plunkett.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflicts of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Plunkett, D., Sundell, T. Varieties of Metalinguistic Negotiation. Topoi 42, 983–999 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-023-09941-2

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-023-09941-2

Keywords

Navigation