Skip to main content
Log in

Feeling is believing: recalcitrant emotion & Spinozan belief formation

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I defend the judgementalist theory of emotion against the argument from recalcitrant emotions. Judgementalism holds that a necessary condition for being in an emotional state is that an evaluative belief is formed. Recalcitrant emotions are emotions that contradict endorsed beliefs and judgements. The argument from recalcitrant emotions states that a judgementalist explanation of recalcitrant emotions results in the absurd conclusion that one would hold two contradictory beliefs. I argue that emotion involves a so-called Spinozan belief-forming process: a process which automatically generates beliefs, without taking all available information into account. The generated beliefs might contradict something one already believes, as the so-called Fragmentation of Belief Hypothesis predicts. Thus the judgementalist explanation of recalcitrant emotions does not lead to an absurd conclusion and therefore the argument from recalcitrant emotions is refuted.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Greenspan cites the following works as exemplary of the view she wishes to attack: (Bedford, 1957; Green, 1972; Neu, 1977; Solomon, 1978). She takes (Lyons, 1980) to be a borderline case. A more recent example of judgementalism is (Nussbaum, 2001).

  2. Grzankowski himself argues that judgementalism is not refuted by the argument from recalcitrant emotions. (See also Grzankowski, 2020).

  3. One could make a further distinction between “ballistic” and automatic (Mandelbaum, 2015). For an analysis of “automaticity”, see (Moors & De Houwer, 2006).

  4. Note that “emotion” is not necessarily synonymous with “emotional experience”. One can for instance argue that emotions might occur unconsciously. An emotional experience will then only occur when the emotion is conscious. Or one might argue that an emotional experience is only one element of an emotional process, with many other components. Therefore, one can distinguish between “constitutive of emotion” and “constitutive of emotional experience”. I will mainly focus on “emotion”. In Sect. 6, I will discuss emotional experience and emotional phenomenology.

  5. This idea resembles “appraisal theory”. Appraisal theory is a theory that originated in the psychology of emotion (Lazarus, 1991; Moors, 2013; Robinson, 2005; Scherer, 1984, 2009). It could be seen as the “psychologist’s version” of judgementalism. Appraisal theorists claim that emotion has several components. An evaluative judgement (appraisal) is an essential component of the emotion, and it also gives rise to the other components of the emotion. The emotional experience emerges out of these different components. Most appraisal theorists, however, focus more on the cognitive process underlying the emotion than on emotional experience. I will not discuss appraisal theory in detail.

  6. For clarification of what makes the judgements “evaluative”, see (Nussbaum, 2001, 19–32).

  7. Also called “Fragmentation of the Mind”.

  8. Also called “belief fixation”.

  9. The names of these BFPs obviously refer to ideas of Descartes (1641/1988; 1644/1988) and Spinoza (1677/1991). I believe it is better to state that Descartes and Spinoza inspired Gilbert (1991) to distinguish between these two types of BFPs, rather than stating that these ideas are literally formulated by Descartes and Spinoza. Huebner (2009) describes in greater detail how the original ideas of Descartes and Spinoza relate to Gilbert’s distinction.

  10. Persisting contradictory beliefs are not necessarily a sign of mental illness. Mandelbaum and Quilty-Dunn (2015) refer to a series of studies by Johnson and Seifert (Johnson & Seifert, 1994; Seifert, 2002) which aim to show that people can have persistent contradictory beliefs. The participants of one of these studies read a text about a fire. It first states that the fire was caused by cans of oil paint. In the next sentence, this information is corrected: there were no cans of oil paint. After reading the text, the participants have to answer some questions. There was a tendency amongst the participants to report both that the cans caused the fire and that the text mentioned that there were no cans. This indicates that the participants are capable of having persistent contradictory beliefs.

  11. For interesting accounts of delusions that make use of the idea of Spinozan BFP, see (Bongiorno, forthcoming; Flores 2021).

  12. One of the most important books of Cognitive Behavioral Therapy is (Beck, 1975). For a discussion of the philosophical roots of Cognitive Behavioral Therapy, see (Robertson, 2019). Stoicism is named as its main philosophical inspiration, which is, in fact, judgementalism avant la lettre (Nussbaum, 2001).

  13. For the following paragraphs, I depend heavily on Clark’s (1999) overview article.

  14. This is Gilbert’s and Quilty-Dunn’s (2019) interpretation of Reid. For a more recent defense of the so-called doxastic theory of perception, see (Glüer, 2009).

  15. However, see (Quilty-Dunn, 2020), for an excellent defense of this view.

References

  • Beck, A. T. (1975). Cognitive therapy and the emotional disorders. International Universities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedford, E. (1957). Emotions, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 57, 281–304.

  • Bongiorno, F., forthcoming, Spinozan Doxasticism About Delusions, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly.

  • Broad, C. D. (1954). Emotion and sentiment. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 13(2), 203–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burns, D. (1980). Feeling good. Signet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (2010). Judging, believing and thinking. Philosophical Issues, 20(1), 80–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, D. M. (1999). Anxiety disorders: why they persist and how to treat them. Behaviour research and therapy, 37(1), S5–S27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2001). Elements of mind: an introduction to the philosophy of mind. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1641/1984). Fourth meditation, in J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, & D. Murdoch (Eds. and Trans.), The philosophical writings of Descartes (Vol. 2) Cambridge University Press, 37–43.

  • Descartes, R. (1644/1984). Principles of philosophy, in J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, & D. Murdoch (Eds. and Trans.), The philosophical writings of Descartes (Vol. 1) Cambridge University Press, 193–291.

  • Egan, A. (2008). Seeing and believing: perception, belief formation and the divided mind. Philosophical Studies, 140(1), 47–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, A. (2011). Comments on Gendler’s ‘The epistemic costs of implicit bias’. Philosophical Studies, 156(1), 65–79.

  • Flores, C. (2021). Delusional evidence-responsiveness, Synthese 199(3–4), 6299–6330.

  • Folkman, S., & Lazarus, R. S. (1984). Stress, appraisal, and coping. Springer Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, D. (1991). How mental systems believe. American Psychologist, 46(2), 107–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, D., Tafarodi, R., & Malone, P. (1993). You can’t not believe everything you read. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65(2), 221–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glüer, K. (2009). In defence of a doxastic account of experience. Mind & Language, 24(3), 297–327.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, O. H. (1972). Emotions and Belief. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in the philosophy of mind, American Philosophical Quarterly. Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. S. (1988). Emotions and reasons: an Enquiry Into Emotional Justification. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grzankowski, A. (2017). The real trouble with recalcitrant emotions. Erkenntnis, 82(3), 641–651.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grzankowski, A. (2020). Navigating recalcitrant emotions. Journal of Philosophy, 117(9), 501–519.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hackmann, A., Clark, D. M., & McManus, F. (2000). Recurrent images and early memories in social phobia. Behaviour research and therapy, 38(6), 601–610.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofmann, S. G., Asnaani, A., Vonk, I. J., Sawyer, A. T., & Fang, A. (2012). The efficacy of cognitive behavioral therapy: a review of meta-analyses. Cognitive therapy and research, 36(5), 427–440.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huebner, B. (2009). Trouble with stereotypes for Spinozan minds. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 39(1), 63–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koss, M. P., Figueredo, A. J., Bell, I., Tharan, M., & Tromp, S. (1996). Traumatic memory characteristics: a crossvalidated mediational mode of response to rape among employed women. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 105(3), 421–432.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, H. M., & Seifert, C. M. (1994). Sources of the continued influence effect: when misinformation in memory affects later inferences. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning Memory and Cognition, 20(6), 1420.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lazarus, R. S. (1991). Emotion and adaptation. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2016). Have I turned the stove off? Explaining everyday anxiety. Philosopher’s Imprint, 16(2), 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1982). Logic for equivocators. Nous, 16(3), 431–441.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, W. (1980). Emotion. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majeed, R. (2020). What Not to Make of Recalcitrant Emotions, Erkenntnis, 1–19.

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2013). Against alief. Philosophical Studies, 165(1), 197–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2014). Thinking is believing. Inquiry : A Journal Of Medical Care Organization, Provision And Financing, 57(1), 55–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2015). The Automatic and the ballistic: modularity beyond perceptual processes. Philosophical Psychology, 28(8), 1147–1156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2016). Attitude, Association, and inference: on the Propositional structure of Implicit Bias. Noûs, 50(3), 629–658.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E., & Bendana, J., & Forthcoming, The Fragmentation of Belief D. Kinderman, A. Onofri, & C. Borgoni (Eds.), The Fragmented Mind, Oxford University Press.

  • Mandelbaum, E., & Quilty-Dunn, J. (2015). Believing without reason: or: why liberals shouldn’t watch Fox News. The Harvard Review of Philosophy, 22, 42–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mansell, W., & Clark, D. M. (1999). How do I appear to others? Social anxiety and biased processing of the observable self. Behaviour Research and Therapy, 37(5), 419–434.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moors, A. (2013). On the Causal Role of Appraisal in emotion. Emotion Review, 5(2), 132–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moors, A., & De Houwer, J. (2006). Automaticity: a theoretical and conceptual analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 132(2), 297–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neu, J. (1977). Emotion, Thought and Therapy. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neu, J. (2000). A tear is an intellectual thing: the meanings of emotion. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2001). Upheavals of thought: the intelligence of emotions. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plass, J. L., & Kalyuga, S. (2019). Four Ways of considering emotion in cognitive load theory. Educ Psychol Rev, 31(2), 339–359.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porot, N., & Mandelbaum, E. (2020). The science of belief: A progress report. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science,e1539. (First published online).

  • Quilty-Dunn, J. (2019). Reid’s Doxastic Theory of Perception, Philosophers’ Imprint, 19.

  • Quilty-Dunn, J. (2020). Perceptual Pluralism, _Noûs_ 54(4), 807–838.

  • Quine, W. V. O., & Ullian, J. (1978). The web of belief. Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachman, S. J. (1976). The passing of the two-stage theory of fear and avoidance: fresh possibilities. Behaviour Research and Therapy, 14(2), 125–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid, T. (1764/1997). In D. R. Brookes (Ed.), An Inquiry into the human mind on the principles of common sense. Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid, T. (1785/2002). Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man. Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, D. (2019). The philosophy of cognitive-behavioural therapy (CBT): stoic philosophy as rational and cognitive psychotherapy. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, J. (2005). Deeper than reason: emotion and its role in literature, music and art. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seifert, C. M. (2002). The continued influence of misinformation in memory: what makes a correction effective?. In B. H. Ross (Ed.), Psychology of learning and motivation (41 vol., pp. 265–292). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, K. R. (1984). On the nature and function of emotion: a component process Approach. In K. R. Scherer, & P. Ekman (Eds.), Approaches to emotion (pp. 397–410). Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, K. R. (2009). The Dynamic Architecture of emotion: evidence for the component process model. Cognition and Emotion, 23(7), 1307–1351.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. C. (1973). Emotions and choice. The Review of Metaphysics, 27(1), 20–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. C. (1976). The passions. Doubleday Anchor.

  • Spinoza, B., 1677/1991, Ethics. Hackett.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the following people for their valuable feedback: Andrea Blomkvist, Claudia Gâlgău, Gerardo Viera, Stacie Friend, Alex Grzankowski, Nicolas Porot, Bence Nanay, Eric Mandelbaum, an anonymous referee and audiences at several conferences and seminars. This work was supported by the Research Foundation – Flanders (FWO) Junior Postdoctoral Fellowship (1217120 N).

Funding

Research Foundation – Flanders (FWO) Junior Postdoctoral Fellowship 1217120N. This research was funded by Research Foundation – Flanders (FWO) Junior Postdoctoral Fellowship 1217120N.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kris Goffin.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

I declare that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Goffin, K. Feeling is believing: recalcitrant emotion & Spinozan belief formation. Synthese 200, 520 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03980-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03980-9

Keywords

Navigation