Skip to main content
Log in

Stubborn emotions, stubborn beliefs

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recalcitrant emotions, such as fear of flying, are emotions that persist even though they are in tension with the emoter’s considered belief. A widely accepted argument against cognitivist theories of emotion holds that recalcitrant emotions show that emotions are more like sensory states than like thoughts or beliefs. I show that this argument does not succeed: Emotions are usually sensitive to our changing beliefs in a way that is more akin to cognitive states than to sensations. Moreover, empirical evidence strongly suggests that beliefs sometimes behave much like recalcitrant emotions do.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Here, I count as cognitivist views which would reduce emotions to (or identify them with) cognitive states such as judgment or belief (Nussbaum, 2004; Solomon, 1993), as well as views which claim merely that a cognitive state such as belief or judgment is a constituent part of emotion, such as belief-desire accounts (Gordon, 1994; Green, 1992; Reisenzein, 2009). Some of what are termed ‘Neo-Cognitivist’ views (which often position themselves between cognitivist theories and perceptualist theories that seek to align emotions with perceptual states) will fall in this second camp. However, some Neo-Cognitivist views which hold that emotions have propositional content might not be vulnerable to the formulations of the argument from recalcitrance I discuss here. For instance, attitudinal accounts often allow that emotions have propositional content, but whether attitudinal views are vulnerable to these arguments from recalcitrance will depend on the way they specify the nature of the attitude in question (see Helm, forthcoming, for helpful discussion). According to Deonna and Teroni (2012, 2017), the attitude in question is the emoter’s experience of their body as ready for a particular action. This kind of attitude is unlikely to be vulnerable to the argument from recalcitrance (though note that Deonna and Teroni do not spell out the content of emotion propositionally, either). See D’Arms and Jacobson (2003), as well, for a discussion of what they dub ‘quasi-judgmentalist’ theories. See Grzankowski (2020) for helpful discussion and taxonomy of cognitivist, neo-cognitivist, and perceptualist views in the literature.

  2. See, for instance, Deonna and Teroni (2012, pp. 54–55), D’Arms and Jacobson (2003, p. 129), Benbaji (2013), Döring (2014), Naar (2018), Grzankowski (2017), Greenspan (1981), Helm (2015), Prinz (2004), Brady (2009), Tappolet (2012, 2016).

  3. See Grzankowski (2017) and Naar (2018) for helpful overviews.

  4. There is another, slightly different formulation advanced in Grzankowski (2017), which improves on Greenspan’s (1981) formulation. For brevity I will not include a separate discussion of this formulation, since it relies on the same idealized notion of belief, and hence fails for the same reasons as do the two formulations of the argument from recalcitrance that I discuss in Sects. 2 and 5.

  5. See Döring (2014, p. 132), for an example.

  6. See, for example, Döring (2014), as well as Tappolet (2012, 2016), Prinz (2006).

  7. This formulation of the argument has the added bonus of engaging closely with Feldman-Barrett’s (2017) challenge that, contra basic emotions theorists, emotions are not modular. However, whether encapsulation implies modularity is debated and nothing I say here takes a stance on this issue.

  8. Note that even recalcitrant emotions seem in some instances laudatory: Emotions sometimes urge an emoter to act or to adjust their considered beliefs—and in some cases this seems to be a good thing. Recall the oft-cited example of Huck Finn, who hides Jim out of emotion but in spite of Huck’s considered judgment. This case is meant to show that not all recalcitrant emotions should yield to an emoter’s standing, considered beliefs and is discussed, for instance, in Döring (2014), and Benbaji (2013).

  9. It is important to note here that whether and the extent to which encapsulation can divide perception from cognition is not settled. The extent to which perception is encapsulated from cognition is hotly debated, especially in light of cognitive penetration (the top-down influence cognition often has on perception). See e.g. Prinz (2006); Clark (2015). Hence, the role that encapsulation ought to play in drawing the border between perception and cognition is controversial, never mind how well this approach applies to questions about the divisions between emotion and cognition. Some writers in the literature on the perception-cognition border have suggested that encapsulation may come in degrees; perhaps this provides a more promising way to use encapsulation to divide perception from cognition. See Pacherie (2008); Shea (2015); Quilty-Dunn (2017).

  10. See Kunda (1990) and Kuhn and Lao (1996) for an overview.

  11. See, for example, Lord et al. (1979); Nyhan and Reifler (2010); and Nyhan et al. (2013).

  12. Eric Mandelbaum’s work first drew attention to these examples, as well as those discussed later in this section, and to the pressure they put on the view that beliefs update reliably in an ideally rational way. Lord et al. (1979) was first discussed in the philosophical literature on belief by Mandelbaum (2013); Johnson and Seifert (1994) by Mandelbaum and Quilty-Dunn (2015); and Anderson (1983), Anderson et al. (1980), Anderson and Sechler (1986), Batson (1975), Lord et al. (1979), Slusher and Anderson (1989), and Taber and Lodge (2006) by Mandelbaum (2019). See also discussion of many of these studies in Bendaña (2021) and Bendaña and Mandelbaum (2021).

  13. See Taber and Lodge (2006); and Tappin et al. (2021).

  14. As discussed in Bendaña (2021) and Bendaña and Mandelbaum (2021); see for more detailed discussion.

  15. For the purposes of this paper, in (b) ‘awareness’ is meant to be first-personal awareness. I take it that many people will think that we are under less rational pressure to revise incompatible beliefs if we learn of the incompatibility third-personal means (by, for example, taking an implicit association test, contested though they may be) than if we learn of it first-personally.

  16. As discussed in Bendaña (2021).

  17. Though see Mandelbaum (2019) and Williams (2018) for critiques of these models.

  18. One might also worry that recalcitrance reveals that emotions must have non-propositional or non-conceptual content. The idea would be that states with propositional content don’t exhibit resistance to rational revision, so a state that exhibits recalcitrance can’t have propositional content. However, belief arguably has propositional content if any state does. If beliefs are sometimes stubborn, then stubbornness of token mental states does not reveal that the type of mental state to which the token belongs must have non-propositional or non-conceptual content. This is already acknowledged in the literature on the perception-cognition border, since architectural approaches allow that perception and cognition may turn out to use the same kinds of representations; their difference is to be drawn according to the ways the different types of states are structured and interact with one another, rather than according to their representational features. See, e.g., Pylyshyn (2003). For a nice discussion of perceptual pluralism, propositional content, and perceptual views of emotion, see Wringe (2015).

  19. There are other ways a cognitivist might avoid the problems purportedly associated with recalcitrant emotion than this paper considers. Nussbaum, for instance, argues that that in recalcitrant emotions a subject does not have incompatible judgments simultaneously, but rather toggles between them (e.g. Nussbaum, 2009, pp. 383–85). If this paper’s argument goes through, however, no such toggling is required. Since this paper is concerned neither with evaluating nor with advancing a positive view of emotion, a full treatment of Nussbaum’s view as well as of her solution to the problem of recalcitrance is beyond the scope of this paper.

  20. This assumption about the nature of belief is central to yet another formulation of the argument from recalcitrance. See, for instance, Greenspan (1980), Helm (2015), Benbaji (2013), Döring (2014), and Naar (2018).

  21. As nicely noted and discussed in Bendaña (2021).

    Even more permissive views, such as McLaughlin’s (1988), don’t allow for recalcitrant beliefs. Though McLaughlin allows that a subject can have incompatible beliefs, he denies that a subject could be aware of both incompatible beliefs. Instead, he has it that at least one of the beliefs must be “inaccessible” to the subject in cases of incompatibility.

  22. Criterialists bear the additional burden of positing new types of mental states to account for what I’ve been calling stubborn beliefs. Some posit ‘aliefs’ (Gendler, 2008) or merely very vivid imaginings. See Mandelbaum (2013) and Viedge (2018) for detailed treatments of the problems they see plaguing this kind of approach.

  23. c.f. Huddleston’s (2012) argument that ‘naughty’ beliefs are still beliefs.

  24. Some people who take the line that beliefs could never be recalcitrant might still be comfortable admitting that these studies show that beliefs are sometimes evidence-resistant. Perhaps the critic of would insist that nevertheless the intuitions about the coherence of belief must be right, even if beliefs are not always as evidence-responsive as many intuitively take them to be.

    There are thorny issues about the relationship between evidence-responsiveness and coherence. Though a treatment of this issue is beyond the scope of this paper, some argue that coherence is at bottom a matter of evidence-responsiveness. See for instance Kolodny (2007, 2008) and Broome (2013).

  25. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me on this issue.

  26. See Tappin and Gadsby (2019) for review and discussion.

  27. See Jern et al. (2014).

  28. Tappin and Gadsby themselves note that this effect is “extremely robust” (2019, p. 110).

  29. See, for example Lord et al. (1979), Taber and Lodge (2006), Tappin et al. (2021).

  30. Some of this debate also concerns the degree to which belief perseverance might be rational. This is largely beside the point for what I argue here; for brevity, I leave it aside.

  31. See Tappin and Gadsby (2019) and Baron and Jost (2019) for recent reviews in support of their claim that many of cases of purportedly biased or motivated cognition can be accommodated by a Bayesian model, given appropriate right priors and likelihoods.

  32. See Brady (2007, 2009), Helm (2001, pp. 41–46, 2015), Benbaji (2013), Döring (2014), Naar (2018), Grzankowski (2020); for discussion of this formulation of the argument from recalcitrance.

  33. First presented by Makinson (1965).

  34. With the possible exception of phobias, a full consideration of which is beyond the scope of this paper.

  35. And, finally, suppose that this case is not pathological.

  36. Additionally, if a possible outcome is sufficiently bad, perhaps it is in fact most rational to avoid that event if the cost of doing so isn’t too high, even if the emoter believes the likelihood of the dangerous outcome is small. Perhaps for fear of flying, your belief that flying is relatively safe overrides your fear, maybe in part because you estimate that the costs of never flying are too high.

  37. Döring (2014) makes this suggestion, writing that when a person is in the grip of a recalcitrant emotion, “The subject does not contradict himself because he only regards his judgement’s content as true, whilst the content of his emotion merely appears to be true to him.” (p. 134).

References

  • Anderson, C. A. (1983). Abstract and concrete data in the perseverance of social theories: When weak data lead to unshakeable beliefs. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 19(2), 93–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, C. A., Lepper, M. R., & Ross, L. (1980). Perseverance of social theories: The role of explanation in the persistence of discredited information. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 39(6), 1037–1049.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, C. A., & Sechler, E. S. (1986). Effects of explanation and counterexplanation on the development and use of social theories. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 50(1), 24–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, J., & Jost, J. T. (2019). False equivalence: Are liberals and conservatives in the United States equally biased? Perspectives on Psychological Science, 14(2), 292–303. https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691618788876

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. F. (2017). The theory of constructed emotion: An active inference account of interoception and categorization. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 12(1), 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batson, C. D. (1975). Rational processing or rationalization? The effect of disconfirming information on a stated religious belief. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 32(1), 176–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benbaji, H. (2013). How is recalcitrant emotion possible? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(3), 577–599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bendaña, J. (2021). Implicit attitudes are (probably) beliefs. In A. Kinderman & O. C. Borgoni (Eds.), The fragmented mind. Berlin: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bendaña, J., & Mandelbaum, E. (2021). The Fragmentation of belief. In A. Kinderman & O. C. Borgoni (Eds.), The fragmented mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brady, M. S. (2007). Recalcitrant emotions and visual illusions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 44(3), 273–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brady, M. S. (2009). The irrationality of recalcitrant emotions. Philosophical Studies, 145, 413–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2013). Rationality through reasoning. Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2015). Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (2003). The significance of recalcitrant emotion (or, anti-quasijudgmentalism). Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements, 52, 127–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deonna, J., & Teroni, F. (2012). The emotions: A philosophical introduction. Berlin: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Deonna, J., & Teroni, F. (2017). Getting bodily feelings into emotional experience in the right way. Emotion Review, 9(1), 55–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Döring, S. A. (2014). Why recalcitrant emotions are not irrational. In S. Roeser & C. Todd (Eds.), Emotion and value (p. 124). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind: An essay on faculty psychology. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2008). Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 634–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R. M. (1994). The structure of emotions: Investigations in cognitive philosophy (Reprinted). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, O. H. (1992). The emotions: A philosophical theory. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. (1980). A case of mixed feelings: Ambivalence and the logic of emotion. In A. O. Rorty (Ed.), explaining emotions (pp. 223–250). University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. S. (1981). Emotions as evaluations. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 62(2), 158–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grzankowski, A. (2017). The real trouble with recalcitrant emotions. Erkenntnis, 82(3), 641–651.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grzankowski, A. (2020). Navigating recalcitrant emotions. The Journal of Philosophy, 117(9), 501–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helm, B. W. (2001). Emotional reason: Deliberation, motivation, and the nature of value. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Helm, B. W. (2015). Emotions and recalcitrance: Reevaluating the perceptual model. Dialectica, 69(3), 417–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helm, B. W. (forthcoming). Cognitivist theories of emotions. In A. Scarantino (Ed.) The Routledge Handbook of Emotion Theory. Routledge.

  • Huddleston, A. (2012). Naughty beliefs. Philosophical Studies, 160(2), 209–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jern, A., Chang, K. M. K., & Kemp, C. (2014). Belief polarization is not always irrational. Psychological Review, 121(2), 206–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, H. M., & Seifert, C. M. (1994). Sources of the continued influence effect: When misinformation in memory affects later inferences. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 20(6), 1420–1436.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny, N. (2007). How does coherence matter? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 107(1.3), 229–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny, N. (2008). Why be disposed to be coherent? Ethics, 118(3), 437–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, D., & Lao, J. (1996). Effects of evidence on attitudes: Is polarization the norm? Psychological Science, 7(2), 115–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kunda, Z. (1990). The case for motivated reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 108(3), 480–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2015). Neither fish nor fowl: Implicit attitudes as patchy endorsements. Noûs, 49, 800–823.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lord, C. G., Ross, L., & Lepper, M. R. (1979). Biased assimilation and attitude polarization: The effects of prior theories on subsequently considered evidence. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37(11), 2098–2109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D. C. (1965). The paradox of the preface. Analysis, 25(6), 205–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2013). Against alief. Philosophical Studies, 165(1), 197–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2019). Troubles with Bayesianism: An introduction to the psychological immune system. Mind & Language, 34, 141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E., & Quilty-Dunn, J. (2015). Believing without reason: Or: Why liberals shouldn’t watch fox news. The Harvard Review of Philosophy, 22, 42–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B. P. (1988). Exploring the possibility of self-deception in belief. In B. P. McLaughlin & A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Perspectives on Self-Deception (p. 36). University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naar, H. (2018). Sentiments. In H. Naar & F. Teroni (Eds.), The ontology of emotions. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2004). Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MC, Nussbaum. (2009). The stoics on the extirpation of the passions. In the therapy of desire (pp. 359–401). Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nyhan, B., & Reifler, J. (2010). When corrections fail: The persistence of political misperceptions. Political Behavior, 32(2), 303–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nyhan, B., Reifler, J., & Ubel, P. A. (2013). The hazards of correcting myths about health care reform. Medical Care, 51, 127–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2008). The phenomenology of action: A conceptual framework. Cognition, 107(1), 179–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2004). Gut reactions: A perceptual theory of emotion. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2006). Is the mind really modular? In R. J. Stainton (Ed.), Contemporary debates in cognitive science (pp. 22–36). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2003). Seeing and visualizing: It’s not what you think. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quilty-Dunn, J. (2017). Syntax and semantics of perceptual representation. Ph.D. dissertation, The Graduate Center, City University of New York.

  • Reisenzein, R. (2009). Emotional experience in the computational belief–desire theory of emotion. Emotion Review, 1(3), 214–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N. (2015). Distinguishing top-down from bottom-up effects. In D. Stokes, M. Matthen, & S. Biggs (Eds.), Perception and its modalities (pp. 73–91). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slusher, M. P., & Anderson, C. A. (1989). Belief perseverance and self-defeating behavior. In R. C. Curtis (Ed.), Self-defeating behaviors: Experimental research, clinical impressions, and practical implications (pp. 11–40). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. C. (1993). The Passions: Emotions and the Meaning of Life. Berlin: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taber, C. S., & Lodge, M. (2006). Motivated skepticism in the evaluation of political beliefs. American Journal of Political Science, 50, 755–769.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tappin, B. M., & Gadsby, S. (2019). Biased belief in the Bayesian brain: A deeper look at the evidence. Consciousness and Cognition, 68, 107–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tappin, B. M., Pennycook, G., & Rand, D. G. (2021). Rethinking the link between cognitive sophistication and politically motivated reasoning. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 150(6), 1095.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tappolet, C. (2012). Emotions, perceptions, and emotional illusions. In C. Calabi (Ed.), Perceptual Illusions (pp. 205–222). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tappolet, C. (2016). Emotions, Values, and Agency. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Viedge, N. (2018). Defending evidence-resistant beliefs. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99(3), 517–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkes, A. L., & Leatherbarrow, M. (1988). Editing episodic memory following the identification of error. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology a: Human Experimental Psychology, 40A(2), 361–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, D. (2018). Hierarchical Bayesian models of delusion. Consciousness and Cognition, 61, 129–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wringe, B. (2015). The contents of perception and the contents of emotion. Noûs, 49(2), 275–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper is especially indebted to Joseph Bendaña and Eric Mandelbaum. Conversations with Joseph on an earlier version of this paper greatly improved it and helped develop the paper to bring it into closer conversation with the empirical literature. This paper follows Joseph’s own work which discusses that literature in the context of implicit bias and belief. The paper not only benefitted from Eric Mandelbaum’s guidance and feedback, but also depends on Eric’s prior work drawing attention to the body of empirical studies marshalled here as telling against an idealized notion of belief. I also thank Simon Brown, Nemira Gasiunas-Kopp, Matthew Heeney, Eric Bayruns García, Santiago Echeverri, David Rosenthal, Michelle Montague, Jeff Seidman, and participants in the New York Philosophy of Psychology workshop and the Cognitive Science Symposium at the CUNY Graduate Center for their feedback and conversation. Helpful comments from several anonymous reviewers also significantly improved the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kate Pendoley.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pendoley, K. Stubborn emotions, stubborn beliefs. Synthese 201, 165 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04165-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04165-8

Keywords

Navigation