1 Introduction

The relationship between pathology and social environments has become a key issue within research into psychiatric conditions, including the most recent publication of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of mental disorders (American Psychiatric Association, 2022, xxi; First et al., 2022). This raises the central question of how to integrate psychiatry with our social environments. To this end, enactive approaches to psychiatry have sought to provide a relational understanding of psychiatric disorders as properties, not of individuals but of broadly interactive (dis)relations between individual and environment (Fuchs, 2017; Varga, 2017; 2019; Krueger, 2020; de Haan, 2020a; Toro et al., 2020; Nielsen & Ward, 2020; Maiese, 2021; Gallagher et al., 2022). The overarching message from these enactive approaches is that we cannot take the role of social contexts for granted but must view psychiatric conditions from an irreducibly interactional basis.

One potential issue for enactive bids for integrating the sociocultural dimension is that the appeal to individual adaptive self-maintenance does not provide a means of adjudicating between conflicting norms at the social level (Russell, 2023). In this regard recent commentaries on enactive approaches have considered whether highlighting aspects such as individual autonomy, flourishing, and authenticity provide sufficient bases for the evaluation of different social norms (Maiese & Hanna, 2019; Gallagher, 2022b; Krueger, 2022; Slaby, 2022). The disconnection between dyadic interactions and social norms thus pushes the question of social integration beyond the purview of questions of individual embodiment towards more systematically socially embedded approaches to cognition (Di Paolo et al., 2018; Di Paolo & De Jaegher, 2022; Brancazio, 2023) and to psychiatry (de Haan 2020a; Maiese, 2022b; Nielsen, 2023).

In support of this recent turn in the enactive literature, I will highlight two aspects of the contributing role of social environments to psychiatric conditions that fall outside relational interactions between individuals and their environment. First, social environments themselves may constrain the focus of analysis to individual (including dyadic) relations by defining certain individuals as atypical. Consequently, the designation of an individual as atypical, even when disorders are seen as irreducibly relational, may in some instances act to obfuscate or exculpate potential systemic dysfunction. Second, most social environments tend to prescribe parameters of appropriate interaction, including interactional breakdowns, independently of direct interaction with inhabiting individuals – especially developmentally formative environments like health and educational institutions. As such both the identification of individual interactants and the terms of interaction are commonly dictated by social structures prior to any interactions with individuals. Insofar as these aspects may in some cases be part of a socially integrated naturalistic psychiatry, their influence cannot be captured by interactions between individual and environment but must be understood and evaluated as part of the autonomous normative structure of social systems.

In light of this, integration of the social dimension of psychiatry in accordance with enactive approaches to psychiatry calls for a means of evaluating social normative systems independently of their relations with specific individuals. Accordingly, I will argue that an enactive psychiatry, in addition to considerations of the world-embedded individual – disruptions of nonlinear causality (Fuchs, 2017), impairments of authentic autonomous agency (Maiese, 2022b), biases in existential sense-making (de Haan, 2021) – stands to benefit from the addition of means of evaluating, on its own terms, the influence of social systems in psychiatry.

The latter part of this paper aims to provide enactive approaches to psychiatry with one possible means of integrating influences of normative social systems through a systems-theoretic reading of Canguilhem’s analysis of health and disease in terms of forms of normative structure. According to Canguilhem’s analysis, health and disease may be differentiated by means of adaptively open or restrictive normative structure. This provides a formal means of assessing normative social systems in their own right, beyond individual interactions: namely by the extent to which the social system can encompass and incorporate different variations of input in the form of populational diversity into its own normative structure. This, I will argue, provides a strongly complementary means for enactive approaches to identify and adjudicate systemic aspects of social integration.

The structure of the paper is as follows. Section 1 outlines the enactive model of psychiatry and its relationship with socially embedded and relationally constituted individuals as bases for a socially integrative psychiatry. Section 2 offers some points of consideration for the interactive conceptualization of psychiatric conditions under enactive approaches, highlighting the active role of social environments in defining individuals as well as in dictating the terms of interactions and what counts as interactive breakdown. Section 3 offers a means for enactive approaches to address influences from social environments on their own terms, based on Canguilhem’s account of pathology by means of normative systems.

2 Enactive approaches to psychiatry: individual and dyadic interaction

The recent turn towards a social paradigm for psychiatry signifies an unprecedented change in the understanding and assessment of mental conditions. Instead of the previous exclusive focus on individual neurocognitive functionality, normative societal contingencies are increasingly acknowledged as playing a decisive role in both the etiology and attribution of psychiatric conditions (Priebe, 2016; Ventriglio et al., 2016; APA, 2022; p. 17).Footnote 1 This raises the pressing question of how research might provide a naturalistic understanding of the effective causal role of social contexts in psychiatric conditions.

One way of approaching this question is through the subsumption of social aspects as linearly cascading effects of neurofunctional deficits (see for example Barkley, 2015). According to this explanation social and personal impacts follow from impairments within individual neurofunctional substrate. Effectively, however, such an approach fails to present an integration of social factors, instead presenting social factors as downstream products of individualized deficits (Rosqvist et al., 2020; Dengsø, 2022). Accordingly, the linear model does little to address the causal contribution of the social contexts. The task of providing a systematic and naturalistic understanding of the causal role of social contexts for psychiatry thus remains inadequately addressed by these linear accounts.

Several different ways of approaching the task of providing a naturalistic integration of social factors in psychiatric conditions have recently been launched from the group of theoretical frameworks called enactive. Enactive approaches most commonly concern means of addressing the nature of experience, perception, and cognition (Thompson, 2007; Hutto & Myin, 2012; Di Paolo & Thompson, 2014; Varela et al., 2017; Di Paolo, 2018). In broad terms, enactive approaches advocate for conceptualizing mental phenomena as properties of interactive relations between brain, body, and environment, as opposed to brains alone (Gallagher et al., 2013; Di Paolo, 2009). Recently, various enactive accounts have applied this relational view of mental phenomena to understanding psychiatric conditions and pathology (De Jaegher, 2013; Fuchs, 2017; Varga, 2019; de Haan, 2020a; Glas, 2020; Toro et al., 2020; Jurgens, 2020; Krueger, 2020, 2021; Gallagher, 2022a; Dengsø, 2022). This section will outline several enactive approaches to mental conditions and their appeal to nonlinear forms of causality as a means of accounting mental conditions as irreducibly relational phenomena. I will focus on the approaches outlined in the work of Fuchs and de Haan’s enactive approaches to psychiatry (Fuchs, 2017; de Haan, 2020a), the enhanced meshed architecture (Gallagher et al., 2022), and the norm-based approaches of Nielsen and Maiese (Nielsen & Ward, 2020; Maiese, 2021).

2.1 Enactive models of psychiatry

For Fuchs, as well as for many other phenomenological and enactive approaches to psychiatry, problems of standard approaches are intimately related to the detachment of the individual subject from its social and experiential environments, or its lifeworld (Fuchs, 2017).Footnote 2 According to Fuchs, the relational character of mental life is simply beyond the standard linear and brain-based explanations employed by neurofunctional accounts. As he puts it, “with the linear causality of nineteenth-century physics – brain state A causes disorder B – it is impossible to grasp the complex causal connections involved in mental disorders, even less so without the patient’s subjective experience” (Fuchs, 2017, p. 261). Instead of simply tracing a linear path from neural substrates, psychiatry must take into account the socially embedded relations of patients lived experience. As Fuchs argues, we cannot hope to progress our understanding of mental phenomena (pathological or otherwise) while neglecting their inherently relational character (Fuchs, 2017, p. 284).

Fuchs unpacks this relational constitution of minds in terms of two forms of nonlinear, or circular, causality: vertical and horizontal. Vertical circular causality describes reciprocal top-down and bottom-up causal interactions between different structural levels of the individual organism: organs, cells, molecules. Horizontal circular causality, in turn, describes how the individual organism and its surrounding world mutually implicate one another at each structural level (see also Baggs & Chemero, 2019; Kirchhoff & Kiverstein, 2020).Footnote 3

On this account, psychiatric conditions may be understood in terms of disruptions of complex nonlinear relations involving, but not exclusive to, brains. Instead of identifying psychiatric phenomena with neural processes, “we should consider psychiatry as a relational medicine in an encompassing sense: as a science and practice of biological, psychological, and social relations and their disorders” (Fuchs, 2017, p. 276, italics in original). Fuchs’ account of psychiatric conditions is thus centred around disruptions or imbalances within interactions on the vertical circular causality or in the interaction of a given level of organization with the environment.

De Haan’s Enactive Psychiatry (de Haan, 2020a; see also de Haan, 2020b) builds from Fuchs’ account, likewise emphasizing the importance of experience and its fundamental relationality.Footnote 4 De Haan uses the term organizational causality between individual and environments as an instance of transformational fusion emergence (henceforth TFE), as developed by Humphreys (1997; 2016; de Haan, 2020a, pp. 117-9). TFE may be exemplified by how grains of sand, when fused into glass, become transformed in a way such that the individual grains of sand can no longer be said to exist as individual entities (Humphreys, 2016, p. 72, 81). In TFE, instead of maintaining a ‘vertical’ axis of interaction between components and wholes, components and whole fuse together. Using the intuitive analogy of cake-baking – where each of the component ingredients fuse into a single batter – de Haan proposes that basic sense-making capacities such as experience emerge from the fusion of organism and environment. In it is in these relations fusing the biological organism and their environment into a broader whole that psyches and psychiatric phenomena play out.Footnote 5

On de Haan’s account, psychiatric conditions arise from disturbances of a special type of sense-making which she terms existential. Existential capacities for self-reflection, de Haan argues, constitutes a qualitative shift in forms of sense-making, creating a new level of social and existential meaning for the agent.Footnote 6 This existential dimension of sense-making is central to psychiatric conditions (de Haan, 2020a, pp. 130, 212). De Haan’s enactive psychiatry thus portrays mental disorders in terms of harmful forms of existential sense-making characterized by inflexibility, inappropriateness, and suffering.

Building from similar considerations of the relationship between psychiatric disorder and the socially embedded self, Maiese emphasizes how disorders may be understood as involving various disruptions of self-governance (Maiese, 2022a, b). Maiese’s account focuses especially on the authenticity and (relational) autonomous agency of individuals constituted across various socially embedded identities. Congruent with de Haan’s enactive psychiatry, Maiese thus develops a naturalistic view of psychiatric disorders accounting for their social dimensions by way of how psychiatric disturbances manifest as disruptions of the authenticity and autonomy of our relationally embedded nature. Human minds are fundamentally relational and partly shaped by sociocultural institutional norms (Maiese & Hanna, 2019, p.8). Whereas de Haan’s enactive psychiatry focuses on the existential dimension of reflective individuals, Maiese’s often brings to the fore the relationship between individuals and their particular sociocultural niches (Maiese, 2022c, d; see also Slaby et al., 2017). Maiese’s work demonstrates in various ways how sociocultural norms become engraved within individual’s normative way of making sense of their worlds. In this sense, some psychiatric conditions may be understood in terms of discrepancies between expectations of neurotypical normative institutions and the normative sense-making of atypical individuals (Krueger & Maiese, 2018; see also Jurgens, 2020). One way of understanding this is through differences in styles or forms of life (Krueger, 2021), with overly restrictive institutional norms potentially hindering atypical individuals from exercising their own authentic norms.

Whereas the work of Maiese may be seen as expanding upon enactive psychiatry – with a special attention to how social embeddedness shapes agents’ sense of autonomy and authentic selfhood (see also Maiese & Hanna, 2019; Nielsen, 2023, p. 88) – Nielsen’s 3E psychopathology (Nielsen, 2020; 2023; Nielsen & Ward, 2020) is partly grounded in the functional norms of sensemaking and the structural aspect of inflexibility in disordered behaviour (see Nielsen, 2021 and de Haan, 2021 for discussion). Although bringing close attention to our sociocultural embeddedness, Nielsen is careful to maintain a solid foundation for his account within the normativity of the individual biological organism. Nielsen thus cautions that the networks of cultural identities in the manner emphasized by more radical interpretations of enactivism are better understood as metaphors (Nielsen, 2023, p. 84). It has been argued that Nielsen’s account, by conceptualizing individuals in terms of functional norms, could be construed as reductive of human-specific existential dimensions (de Haan, 2021). While Nielsen emphasizes compatibility between the two accounts – arguing that existential relations such as those highlighted by de Haan may be seen as an important although non-ubiquitous aspect of psychiatry (Nielsen, 2021) – Maiese has proposed that the mind-shaping thesis might enact a potential synthesis between these two views (Maiese, 2021).

Finally, another distinct enactive framework for understanding psychiatric conditions has recently been developed based on what is known as meshed architecture (Christensen et al., 2016). In line with the above, proponents of this enactive strain called enhanced meshed architecture (Gallagher et al., 2022) offer a similarly relational understanding of psychiatric conditions based on a two-axis model of (horizontal) environmental integration and (vertical) individual organizational integration, with affectivity acting as a binding function between the two axes. It has been applied especially to neurodevelopmental conditions (Gallagher, 2022a; Gallagher et al., 2022).

2.2 Enactive convergences: the relationally constituted individual

Let us take stock of how these enactive proposals account for the social dimension of psychiatry. Each of the above outlined accounts have stressed the inherently relational structure of psychiatric conditions. Centrally, enactive approaches may be distinguished by their conceptualization of psychiatric conditions in terms of various forms of relational integration involving both an individual and their respective physical and sociocultural environment. In this sense, psychiatric conditions are the result of breakdowns or disattunements of relational interactions centring around the experiential and sense-making capacities of an individual. One can represent this in terms of one of the following kinds of nonlinear causal interactions laid out by Fuchs and de Haan.

  1. i.

    Vertical: an interaction between (two or more) different organizational levels of the individual.

  2. ii.

    Horizontal: an interaction between an individual and the environment.

  3. iii.

    Combination/organizational: an interaction between (two or more) different levels of the individual and the environment.

In the account given by Fuchs, disorders from disruptions of the vertical and horizontal circular causalities integrating individuals and environments, resulting in self-relational disturbances or in negative feedback loops at the level of social interactions (Fuchs, 2017, p. 256). In de Haan’s enactive psychiatry disorders result from disattunements in the relational existential sense-making capacities of the individual (de Haan, 2020a, p. 197). 3E psychopathology seeks to ground our understanding of psychiatric conditions within the functional norms of biological organisms (Nielsen, 2020; 2023). Enactive medical models explore how both psychiatric conditions and sociocultural niches may impact on agentive autonomy and authenticity (Maiese, 2021; Krueger, 2021). And finally, enhanced meshed architecture provides its heuristic in terms of various intertwined factors, including social interactions (Gallagher, 2022a, p. 12).

Enactive explanations of psychiatric conditions converge in their attribution of mental disorders to various forms of relational problems between an individual and their social environment, or as arising from the socially embedded nature of individuals.Footnote 7 Psychiatric phenomena are understood in terms of interactive relations in which the individual minimally constitutes a ubiquitous and basic component of a dyadic relation. The relationally constituted individual – its autonomy, authentic form of life,Footnote 8 existential and/or organismic sense-making – thus constitutes the core of enactive approaches to psychiatry (Krueger, 2021; de Haan, 2020a; Nielsen, 2021; Krueger & Maiese, 2018; Maiese & Hanna, 2019).Footnote 9

2.3 The limits of embedded individuals

One potential challenge to enactive approaches is whether focusing on the interactions of a relationally constituted individual can provide a means of systematically distinguishing and adjudicating between dysfunctionality from the perspective of sociocultural environments and from that of the individual. A key point of attention for enactive approaches here is whether appeal to individual autonomy and authenticity provides a systematic means of evaluating the social norms in which the individual organism or person finds themselves (Maiese & Hanna, 2019; Krueger, 2022; Gallagher, 2022b; Slaby, 2022; Jurgens, 2023).

It has been argued that enactive approaches to psychiatry leave too much open for interpretation in cases where different individual or social norms may disagree about what counts as dysfunction (Russell, 2023). Russell argues that appeals to the adaptivity and autonomy of individual embodiment does not provide a systematic means of adjudication between conflicting norms.

Enactivism, as it stands, does not itself give us the resources to adjudicate between competing perspectives of what is or is not functional/dysfunctional. More importantly, enactivism itself doesn’t give us the tools to critically engage with and discuss which perspectives ought to be involved. (Russell, 2023, p. 16)

While enactive approaches understand psychiatric conditions as involving breakdowns between a relational individual and their social context, it is not clear how such approaches propose to weigh one up against the other. At what point should sociocultural institutions, including psychiatrists, be regarded as authorities over patients? When should misrelations be interpreted as a failure on the part of my niche to fit my own authentic self? Indeed, what is my authentic self and form of life, as contrasted with the recommendations of my developmental niche? Several questions relating to social integration remain open despite having a relational account of individuals. It is not clear how enactive approaches can provide a systematic justification for distinguishing between harmful and developmentally conducive pressures from sociocultural norms.Footnote 10 Russell suggests that a pluralistic approach informed by feminist philosophy of science, ethics, and social epistemology may provide enactive approaches with a more systematic assessment of sociocultural norms and practices. She concludes that “if we want to push such accounts, like enactivism, to go further, I suggest supplementing it with a more critical, political and socially engaged framework” (ibid., p. 22).Footnote 11

Despite their openness to pluralistic views of psychiatric conditions (de Haan, 2020a, p 110; Nielsen, 2023, p. 109), enactive approaches to psychiatry also retain specific limits regarding the extent of social influences. The interactive relations leveraged by enactive approaches minimally imply some level of independence between interactants like individual and their social environment: as de Haan puts it, even within an enactive ontology, “relations presuppose their relata” (de Haan, 2020a, p. 66; see also Varga & Gallagher, 2012; Gallagher, 2020, pp. 192-3). Grounding psychiatry within the interactions of a relational individual thereby importantly sets enactive approaches apart from what Nielsen describes as deflationary accounts of psychiatry (Nielsen, 2023, p. 34), comprising social constructivist, post structuralist, and some feminist accounts of psychiatry. Similarly, while researchers like Maiese often champion the importance of systemic issues with social institutions (Maiese & Hanna, 2019; Maiese, 2022c) and mental institutions (Krueger & Maiese, 2018) her enactive medical model specifically centres sociocultural integration in terms of its effect upon individuals’ authenticity and autonomy while specifically rejecting social constructionist models (Maiese, 2021, 2022a). Accordingly, psychiatric conditions are grounded within the dyadic interaction between agent and environment. Considering feminist criticism of the degree to which social contingency dictates existential forms of sense-making, de Haan offers that

[t]he freedom that comes our excentric position is certainly not a free-floating one – yet our capacity for taking a stance does mark a qualitative shift that opens up a new scope of agency and possibilities for change. […] We cannot help but be determined one way or another […], but it is our relating to these determinations and the sociocultural practices in which we enact them that opens the way for emancipation and change. (de Haan, 2020a, p. 125-6, fn1)

De Haan’s recognition of how the existential dimension is at least partly determined by social contingencies raises the question of whether the qualitative shift facilitated by our excentric stance might not equally open up ways for social domination and control as for individual emancipation and change.Footnote 12 While enactive approaches to psychiatric conditions thus seek to promote the well-being of relationally embedded individual agents, it is still crucial to ask how the individual is initially disclosed within a psychiatric context – and to what degree notions of individual’s authenticity and well-being might be differentiated from influences of its sociocultural niche.

In one sense, the rejection of wholesale social constructivist models of psychiatry does credit to enactive approaches in their efforts towards the integration of the social dimension with a naturalistic understanding of psychiatric conditions. But despite the merit in rejecting a wholesale social constructivism, it is not clear that a naturalistic understanding of psychiatry presupposes a wholesale repudiation of all social constructivist aspects from social integration. The following section offers two examples of sociocultural influence within psychiatry which may fall outside the interactions of even a relationally constituted view of individuals. As will be seen, this is in part because of the crucial role that sociocultural factors play in the determination of both individual and interaction. Focusing on breakdowns in healthy individually self-reproductive norms may insufficient partly because both healthy individual and breakdown are defined in advance by sociocultural systems – blurring the lines between psychiatric and systemic causes of relational disruptions. Especially in the case of formative health and educational environments, social environments tend to get the first and final words in construing both their interlocutor and the aims of their interaction. Providing a systematic way of assessing and integrating sociocultural factors may therefore (or so I will argue) require a means of assessing and evaluating the role of sociocultural norms in psychiatry on their own terms.

3 Individual atypicality and interactive breakdown as social phenomena

Enactive approaches to psychiatry broadly reject the attribution of mental disorder as a straight-forward property of an individual taken in isolation. Instead, they argue, we should often view such disorders in terms of a discrepancy or disattunement between a normative social environment and an atypical individual. But how do we differentiate between variation and atypicality – or between conducive and problematic behaviour?

This section offers two points which highlight how interactions of relationally constituted individuals may in some causes be insufficient to capture the full range of social influences relevant to psychiatric phenomena. The first concerns the attribution of individual atypicality, and how it may serve as a way for social systems to designate certain individuals as partly complicit in relational disturbances. Attributions of individual atypicality, even when non-pathologizing, may in this way obfuscate and exculpate systemic causes of disruption. The second point concerns the nature of interactive breakdowns: how the difference between successful and problematic interactions is often defined at several removes from the involved individuals; and the positive or negative value of institutionally determined interactions can often not be assessed solely on the basis of institutions’ prioritization of individual authenticity.

3.1 Individual atypicality, its social manifestation and systemic function

Much of psychiatric research recognizes that psychiatric atypicality is not, strictly speaking, a property of individuals taken in isolation; but rather of individuals in relation to socially determined parameters of normality (APA, 2022, p. 17). This may be decisive in cases where a condition’s symptoms consist of otherwise normal behaviour exhibited at abnormal frequency or intensity – reflected especially in conditions marked by high degrees of heterogeneity and situational context-sensitivity in symptomatic presentations (Roberts et al., 2015; Wåhlstedt et al., 2009; Madsen et al., 2015; Mottron & Bzdok, 2020) or by disproportionate influence from differences in diagnostic criteria (Voort et al., 2014).

The attribution of atypicality to an individual relies on contrasts with sociocultural determinations of normal degrees of behavioural variation. Accordingly, behaviour otherwise designated as within the norm may be interpreted as evidence of pathology or atypicality in others. For example, fidgeting behaviour, common within healthy populations, may be construed as a symptomatic presentation of intrinsic atypicality in others. Indeed, statistical comparison with peer average behaviour and development is often deeply involved in diagnostic practice, as may be gleaned in the disproportionate diagnosis and treatment of ADHD in children born later in the school year (Elder, 2010; Karlstad et al., 2017).Footnote 13

Enactive approaches to psychiatry emphasize the sociocultural contingency of pathology and disorder. Accordingly, these often regard individual atypicality in non-pathologizing ways, as expressive of individuals’ unique style or form of life (Krueger & Maiese, 2018; de Haan, 2020a, b; Krueger, 2021; Gallagher et al., 2022; Nielsen, 2023). In one sense, this provides a more nuanced view of the individual disclosed to psychiatry. However, even a non-pathologizing attribution of atypicality may in some instances contribute to the concealment of systemic responsibility by designating individuals as partly responsible for relational incompatibilities between themselves and their environments. I will unpack this below.

Social contexts and systems exert a significant part of their causal influence on some psychiatric conditions precisely by construing situational disturbances in terms of interactions between a normal environment and an anomalous or atypical individual.Footnote 14 The attribution of individual atypicality is here part of the contribution of social contexts: diagnostic criteria act as a critical threshold which, once reached, brings about a gestalt-shift in the psychiatric significance attributed to an individual’s behaviour, as described above. Here the contribution of the social context is not circumscribed to their interactions with the atypical individual, but to a significant degree precisely in its identification of an individual as atypical.

This shift brings out one of the ways in which social contributions to psychiatric conditions may in some instances go beyond interactions with individuals. Considering, for example, a classroom setting conceptualized as an interconnected system comprised of students, teachers, various explicit and implicit regulations of behaviour, and a set of educational and socially formative goals. When the system encounters a disruption of its functioning – for example, a decline in student concentration and retention – it may try to identify and modify the elements responsible for this breakdown. We may partition the lineup of potential culprits into three broad categories: (a) student behaviour; (b) institutional constraints such as teaching facilities, content, and regulations; (c) relational incompatibilities between student behaviour and institutional constraints. Designating pathological phenomena in terms of relational interactions will tend to favour option c instead of options a and (more importantly) b. I should here stress that b may be more common than is often assumed (Sage, 2022).Footnote 15 With rapidly changing trends in terms of societal pressures and priorities, especially as related to children and adolescents, it is quite possible that institutional constraints and practices may be increasingly incongruous with best learning practices for emerging generations.

The attribution of disruptions to relational interactions may obfuscate systemic culpability insofar as it tends to absolve those individual components not in direct interaction with students, such as institutional constraints determined at administrative or policy levels (more on this in the next subsection). Attribution of responsibility in social system breakdown tends to fall disproportionately on elements with weaker social consolidation and purchase: as a result, students, direct caregivers, and teachers tend to be the most common targets of modification while regulations set down from more distantly ingrained administrative bodies are less frequently brought into question. By having culpability for disruption conferred equally or reduced to incompatibility between the individual and the social system a relational view may inadvertently lead to an underrepresentation of potential systemic causes of disruption.

What is more, emphasizing individual uniqueness can in such cases obfuscate systemic issues by attributing them to more innocuous relational discrepancies. Recognizing the inadequacies of individual pathologization, several enactive accounts have already put forward constructive proposals for how to make formative social institutions more appropriate to diverse forms of life (Krueger & Maiese, 2018; Maiese & Hanna, 2019; Toro et al., 2020; Krueger, 2021; Chapman, 2021; van Es & Bervoets, 2022; de Carvalho & Krueger, 2023). Still, it is important to recognize that even sympathetic and non-pathologizing conceptualizations of individual atypicality could end up excusing systemic dysfunction.

The potential problem lies not in sensitivity to populational diversity, but in potential insensitivity to systemic dysfunctionality. Designating individuals as inherently pathological is thus just one way for social systems to potentially excuse their own dysfunction: designating individuals as atypical can potentially be another. Whereas one exculpates social institutions by directly problematizing individual behaviour, the other may underemphasize institutional culpability by assigning a shared responsibility. In cases of systemic dysfunction, attributions of individual atypicality may thus become indirect sources of harm (for individual and system alike). In this light, the attribution of individual atypicality, even in terms such as uniquely authentic forms of life, can thus become potential stabilizers for systemic dysfunction. Designations of individual atypicality are in such cases a way for the system to relate to itself – or, more precisely, a means for systems to circumvent critical self-reflection and potential systemic (say, administrative-level) modification. The key takeaway here is that appreciating individual atypicality may be insufficient for identifying and evaluating the influences of social environments. I will expand upon this point in the following subsection.Footnote 16

3.2 Interaction, disinteraction, and formative social systems

Before proposing a possible means for enactive approaches to psychiatry to evaluate and integrate these kinds of social environmental self-relations, I will outline one more aspect of social influences that falls outside the purview of interactions with relationally embedded individuals. Social environments often set the terms of healthy interactions independently of individual dyadic interactions. In this regard focusing on interactive breakdowns risks ignoring decisive contributions of social environments in dictating what constitutes appropriate interactions and their breakdowns.

Any social setting, whether educational, vocational, public, etc., contains implicit or explicit parameters of acceptable interactions almost always set up independently of any involvement of the embedded individuals. For example, service sector employees are often bound by various mechanisms that favour management and consumers, such as uniform dress, periodic (management and patron) evaluation, or tipping-dependent wages. These and other mechanisms pressure employees into assuming attitudes of availability and subservience, often with high demands on emotional labour (Totterdell & Holman, 2003; Hochschild, 1983). Social environments are thus active forces in defining and constraining appropriate and available courses of action (Wartenberg, 1988; Slaby et al., 2017). Additionally, these parameters for appropriate forms of interaction are often dictated well beyond the influence of embedded and interacting individuals (Schmidt & Engelen, 2020; Peeters & Schuilenburg, 2017) – and often to the disadvantage of the latter (Schüll, 2012; Slaby, 2016; Timms & Spurrett, 2023).

The distance between embedded individuals and parameters of acceptable interaction is especially consequential in the case of formative social environments associated with health and education. Here, maintaining the independent ‘top-down’ determination of acceptable forms of interaction is often understood as essential to the formative purpose and functioning of the social environment or institution. The active forces shaping the demands and goals of such social environments are rarely controlled by directly embedded individuals such as pupils, pedagogues, and patients, but is generally set out at administrative and managerial levels. The dictation of interactions is in this way removed from the interacting inhabitants, meaning that significant parts of the contribution of social environments central to psychiatry does not involve any real interaction with individuals but consists rather of the prior determination of both individuals and appropriate or available interactions.

Furthermore, insofar as educational and health institutions often aim specifically at developing (and transforming) the behaviour of inhabitants, recognition of individuals’ authentic forms of life will often be insufficient to provide a systematic means of evaluating the influences of such social environments. The formative role of social institutions is often framed by constructivist accounts in predominantly negative terms.Footnote 17 It is, however, important to emphasize that the formative role of institutions is not inherently harmful to inhabiting individuals even when it might be said to resist and restrict the norms of its inhabiting individuals. First, the resistance of social environments to some of its inhabiting individuals’ norms is central to the socialization and integration of individuals into new sociocultural niches. Second, such socialization into developmental niches aimed towards the permanent transformation of individuals is itself indispensable to individual flourishing. For these reasons, the fact that social institutions entrain, constrain, and problematize individually autonomous or authentic behaviour does not itself provide a means of their evaluation – and perhaps especially so for institutions associated with health and education. Because constraining individual’s norms is often specifically part of the functional purpose of social institutions, the constraining and transformative effects of interactions with individuals are here not sufficient to gauge the merit or demerits of social influences.

In this section I have sought to show how aspects of the social dimension of psychiatric conditions may go beyond relational interactions with individuals. The issue is not just that environments are permeated by normative structures set out well before the interacting individuals come on the scene, but that individuals emerge onto the scene partly as products of the normative structures, purposes, and designations laid out by the social environment. Additionally, the fact that social institutions – and especially formative health and educational institutions – often resist and constrain their inhabitants does not itself provide a basis for their evaluation.

4 A canguilhemian account of systemic health

As previously mentioned, enactive approaches to psychiatry are often explicitly open to implementations of theoretical pluralism (Fuchs, 2017; Nielsen, 2023; Russell, 2023). In the previous section I have outlined some further motivations for why implementing aspects beyond the purview of the interactions of a relationally constituted individual may be necessary for an adequately socially integrative psychiatry. In this section, I will offer one potential means of complementing enactive approaches to psychiatry with a means of integrating and evaluating social norms on their own terms. To this end, I will begin developing the foundations for an ecological-level account based on the analysis of pathology offered by Georges Canguilhem.

4.1 Canguilhem’s norm-based approach to pathology

In The Normal and the Pathological, the physiologist and philosopher Georges Canguilhem pursued a means of systematically distinguishing between disease and health (Canguilhem, 2012). Criticizing notions of health as approximations towards an ideal statistical average or ‘normal’ state, partly due to sociocultural variations in normality, Canguilhem argued that diversity and variation is inherent to the dynamic richness of healthy existence. Accordingly, statistical deviation cannot suffice for pathology just as normality cannot determine what is healthy: “diversity is not disease; the anomalous is not the pathological (ibid., p. 137, italics in original). Instead, Canguilhem proposed to conceptualize health and disease by way of life’s normative structure.

A norm is here understood not as a prescriptive rule, but as a feature of the organizational structure of living systems in accordance with their vital needs. In this minimal sense, normativity is a fundamental feature of living systems: “[t]he simplest biological nutritive system of assimilation and excretion expresses a polarity” (ibid., pp. 128-9). The polarity in question here refers to the organizational orientation of the system: the system expresses a polar orientation towards some normative state and away from other states. Canguilhem’s use of norms might thus be distinguished from the commonplace use of norms as explicit and static rules: first, the meaning of a norm is here minimal in the sense that it pertains to a systems’ implicit structure, and not to any explicit rules as such; second, norms are in this biological sense not to be understood as static ideals but as “a dynamic and polemical concept” in that it seeks to transform and adapt inputs in correspondence with itself (ibid., p. 239). Finally – and importantly for Canguilhem’s account of health and disease – the norms of living systems can themselves be more or less open to change.

For Canguilhem, the way to identify the difference between health and disease lies in their expression of distinct forms of normative organization. As defined by Canguilhem, “[h]ealth is a margin of tolerance for the inconstancies of the environment.” (ibid., p. 197). Being healthy is not about being in a state of perfect fitness or even of well-being per se. Rather, it is precisely being able to weather the predictable unpredictabilities – the unavoidable ups and downs – of life’s inherent dynamicity. In other words, instead of an approximation towards a static ideal of immaculate mediocrity, health denotes the adaptive openness of living systems to the contingencies of everyday existence. Because life must navigate a changing and often surprising environment, “[w]hat characterizes health is the possibility of transcending the norm, which defines the momentarily normal, the possibility of tolerating infractions of the habitual norm and instituting new norms in new situations.” (ibid.). Being healthy is thus neither normality nor the absence of challenges but the ability to meet and adapt to challenges by instantiating new norms. In short, for Canguilhem, health is defined as a norm characterized by openness or adaptivity.Footnote 18

Just as health for Canguilhem is not the approximation to a normal state, neither is pathology the divergence from such an ideal. Instead, pathology and disease may be contrasted with health by the inflexibility of normative structure. As a norm, pathology demands that novelty be minimized, rather than adaptively encountered – for example, by staying in bed or otherwise simplifying and constraining the diversity of interactions one is exposed to. Just as health is characterized by the ability to accommodate novelty, pathology is characterized by intolerance of novelty. As Canguilhem puts it, “[d]isease is still a norm of life but it is an inferior norm in the sense that it tolerates no deviation from the conditions in which it is valid, incapable as it is of changing itself into another norm.” (ibid., p. 183). Disease thus constrains the degree of variation from its own norm wherein a living being can retain viability.

To briefly summarize, Canguilhem defines health and pathology as opposing propensities in the normative structure of living systems: respectively a healthy, adaptive or progressive norm and a diseased, restrictive or reactionary norm.Footnote 19 Alternatively, Canguilhem’s account may be conceptualized in contemporary terms as presenting health and disease as distinguished in terms of respectively open or static affordance landscapes, or in terms of changes in systemic state-space: health is a normative structure characterized by adaptivity of the available state-space whereas pathology is a normative structure characterized by the need to restrict and minimize the state-space.

With this norm-based notion of health and pathology, it should finally (and crucially for my own purposes) be noted that Canguilhem’s account not only applies to individual organisms, but essentially to any normative system. In other words, this provides a potential means of evaluating the normative structure of any kind of system by way of its adaptive openness. A Canguilhemian understanding of health and pathology may thus provide an ecological-level assessment of social systems by way of their normative structure.Footnote 20 Canguilhem himself remarks, albeit briefly, upon the autonomous normative structure of social systems

“[T]he normalization of the technical means of education, health […] expresses collective demands which, taken as a whole, even in the absence of an act of awareness [prise de conscience] on the part of individuals, in a given historical society, defines its way of referring its structure, or perhaps its structures, to what it considers its own good. (Canguilhem, 2012, p. 238)

Although Canguilhem is here considering the normative structure of whole societies, the same principle of the essentially self-referential normative structure of collective demands nonetheless applies to those aspects highlighted in the previous section. As the next subsection will argue, this provides a way for enactive approaches to account for those aspects of psychiatry manifested by social systems in a way that does not excuse or mitigate systemic responsibility.Footnote 21

4.2 Enactive individuals in Canguilhemian social systems

Having outlined the Canguilhemian approach to health, I will now show how this may be used in the evaluation of social systems for social integration in enactive psychiatry. I will first unpack its complementarity with enactive approaches. Not unlike Canguilhem’s own account, the adaptively open operation of living normative systems is a central aspect of the general characterization of life under enactivism (Di Paolo, 2021). This aspect of adaptive openness also extends to the application of enactive approaches to psychiatry and health through the portrayal of relational individual agents. Enactive accounts have thus made occasional reference to Canguilhem’s account albeit as a means of illustrating the minimal normative organization of living systems outlined above – building from this notion of normative systems by additional notions such as autonomy and autopoiesis or ‘self-production’ (see Di Paolo, 2005;, 2010). In this regard, enactive approaches are specifically equipped to deal with the adaptive well-being of normative systems centred around situated organisms and persons in ways that Canguilhem’s approach arguably is not. As unpacked in previous sections of this paper, this makes enactive approaches specifically appropriate to relationally constituted individuals.

In this regard, pertinent aspects of Canguilhem’s account of pathology as related to social systems, ironically, consist precisely in this relative simplicity and consequent potential limitations in relation to the health of individual organismic systems. One such limitation being, for example, a disregard for the impacts of aging upon adaptivity. On Canguilhem’s account, the health of any system (organismic or social) is given by its degree of adaptive openness to changes in its existing norm. In an epilogue (added twenty years after its initial publication) Canguilhem critiques his earlier youthfully optimistic perspective: “The only pathology ascertained at the time was a pathology of young subjects” (Canguilhem, 2012, p.289). Due to its emphasis on adaptivity, the Canguilhemian definition of health is at risk of conflating the inevitable gradual loss of adaptivity from aging with disease. But while this presents a limitation for the appropriateness of a Canguilhemian assessment of health within systems organized around naturally aging organisms and persons, this same limitation becomes a potential improvement in the assessment of non-aging systems such as social institutions. Because social systems are not subject to necessary diminishments in adaptivity over time the discrepancy between health in naturally aging systems and non-aging systems becomes a point of descriptive advantage for a Canguilhemian evaluation of such systems.

Another crucial difference between Canguilhemian and enactive approaches to health is the latter’s emphasis on systemic autonomy, as noted in Sect. 1. Whereas enactive means of evaluating systemic health crucially and centrally prioritize the autonomy of the system in question, a Canguilhemian approach to health specifically prioritizes adaptivity. Here again, the limitation of Canguilhem’s approach to individuals becomes an advantage in its application to social systems. While notions of autonomy are generally seen as privileged over adaptivity for individual persons or organisms,Footnote 22 the same does not apply to social systems. Unlike individual persons, social systems are not ends in themselves, but are legitimate insofar as they serve their purpose or constituency. Accordingly, the autonomous existence of an unhealthy social system – for example, one whose functioning cannot facilitate the purpose or encompass the diversity of its constituency – is no end in itself.

A Canguilhemian approach to health in this way complements the enactive focus on relationally constituted individuals. The disadvantages of Canguilhem’s approach evaluating the contributions of the relationally constituted individual simultaneously presents its key usefulness for enactive approaches in evaluating the influences of social institutions outlined in Sect. 2. Canguilhem’s formal description of health and disease in terms of the normative structure of a dynamical system provides the foundation for evaluating the contributions of social systems on their own terms – namely by independently assessing the health of social systems by way of their normative structure. I will unpack how this Canguilhemian perspective might be applied to social systems in the remainder of this section.

4.3 Evaluating social systems

In the following I will explore how a systems-theoretical reading of Canguilhem’s notions of health and pathology may extend enactive social integration by providing a means of assessing the normative structure of social systems. One way to understand the normative openness of a social system is by the degree of structural complexity and component diversity which the system is capable of integrating into its functioning. This may be contrasted with degrees of component diversity and complexity which the system has to either ignore, repress, or expel.Footnote 23

For example, an educational social system’s components are constituted by the inhabitants of the system (students and staff) which are organized in accordance with the system’s regulations to be conducive to the system’s norms (the pursuit of goals such as formative learning and socialization). Using Canguilhem’s understanding of normative structure, the inhabitants may be disclosed to the social system by way of their role for the system’s own norms. From the perspective of the social system, properties of inhabitants (including the attribution of healthy diversity and problematic atypicality) are defined by their functional role within the normative structure of the overall system. The health of the social system is determined by its openness to the diversity of its populational input.

Following the Canguilhemian approach to health, social systems may be evaluated by the maintenance their adaptive capability: namely, by their ability to provide a functionally cohesive environment encompassing the greatest degree of sensitivity to new variations of input. As a means of assessing the health of the system, we should therefore consider the degree to which systemic functionality demands that components (such as the inhabiting students) conform to preestablished norms. Systemic capacity for the integration of new forms of input into its cohesive functioning corresponds to its degree of adaptivity and health in its normative operation and organization. Conversely, the ‘sickness’ of a given social system corresponds to the degree of functional insensitivity or hostility of its normative function to the novelty and diversity of its inhabitants.

It should be clear that the Canguilhemian approach put forward here is not intended to replace enactive approaches to psychiatry. Rather, the point is to provide a complementary framework to complement enactive approaches in their efforts towards a socially integrative psychiatry. The account provided here is intended as one suggestion for a potential complement to existing enactive proposals. On the one hand, enactive approaches to psychiatry provide a bedrock understanding of the relationally constituted nature of individuals, and a new avenue for social integration of a naturalistic understanding of psychiatric conditions. A Canguilhemian approach to health and disease complements the enactive accounts by providing a means of assessing and evaluating social systems in their own right. Finally, I will unpack some general and specific implications of a Canguilhemian approach to social integration in psychiatry.

First, recall that Canguilhem’s notion of health provides no more guarantee against everyday challenges in social systems than it does for individual people. Just as for individuals, Canguilhem’s definition of health as applied to a social system is not determined by an absence of challenges, but by the capacity of the system in question to meet with and adapt to them. Canguilhem’s account allows us to evaluate how the social system responds appropriately to the discrepancies which might arise in the course of ordinary existence. In particular, it provides a way to minimize the degree to which the social system responds to problems in ways that would be unsustainable in the long term – such as ignoring changing patterns of input. This is because the health of the social system depends on receptivity to novelty both as a direct measure of its present adaptivity, as well as for the continued maintenance of its functional adaptivity. In this sense, the stability of a healthy social system is defined not by approximation towards more flawless and inflexible parameters, but by the resilience engendered through the dynamic adaptivity of its parameters. Healthy social environments must maintain an appropriate level of flexibility in the protocols that dictate the interactions of its inhabitants. As applied to formative institutions, this means that institutional goals should not be to strive for a perfect programme of education, for instance, but for programmes that may meet with the legitimate present and changing concerns and interests of developing generations.

Note also that the advantage of opting for dynamic resilience over rigid stability not only facilitates the interests of its inhabitants but also that of the social system itself. From a dynamic systems theoretical perspective, the benefits of higher input diversity may be described in terms of feedback fidelity and operational resilience facilitated by diversification and functional redundancy (Meadows, 2008). Openness to multiple different functional norms, either through the diversification of ways of implementing a given function or by diversification of functional goals increases systemic resilience against functional breakdown. Diversification of its components equips the system with a larger and more specialized toolbox in dealing with the challenges that it might run into. Accordingly, the health of the system is intimately intertwined with its facilitation of populational and behavioural diversity. The advantages of component diversity from the perspective of the social system itself complements existing appeals to more inclusive paradigms of individual flourishing (see Rosqvist et al., 2020). Diversity is in this sense not a source of errors for correction but a vital source of functional adaptivity, and indispensable to the maintenance of functional stability in dealing with ever new input and challenges. New and ‘troublesome’ inputs become vital sources of growth for the system in constantly redefining its functioning; with the only constant being maintaining openness to the diversity and its systematic implementation. Indeed, greater input novelty and diversity contribute disproportionately to systemic health by their disproportionate potential for further increasing the systemic capacity for functional adaptivity. In line with research from neurodiversity and neurodivergent flourishing, the Canguilhemian view of health thus emphasizes the systemic benefits of populational diversity (Chapman & Botha, 2023).Footnote 24

Finally, this Canguilhemian dynamical systems theoretical perspective may also help to provide some general recommendations for healthy modes of organization of control in social systems. For example, narrower and more stratified top-down forms of control put a structural limitation on systemic adaptivity and health. This is because having a narrower and more insulated subset of controlling elements will tend to diminish contact between new sources adaptivity and the system’s controlling norms. Strict localization of the operational control of a given system within a smaller subset of the system in this way introduces a higher degree of functional volatility by separating sites of control from crucial sources of novel input. In the example of a school-setting, more streamlined administrative control puts restrictions on the system’s ability to adapt to new input such as students with changing motivations and interests, and especially students that might fall outside of the normative expectations of the system. In other words, consolidated and stratified forms of control may render social systems volatile by diminishing adaptive receptivity in a way that corresponds to Canguilhem’s notion of (systemic) sickness. By contrast, horizontal and distributed forms of control, where inhabitants such as students and their directly involved faculty are more directly involved in the determination of the operation and parameters of interaction, will allow for more resilient, adaptive, and healthy social environments.

In summation, Canguilhem’s understanding of disease in terms of overly restrictive norms allows us to understand how, in some situations and for some conditions, problematic aspects thematized in psychiatry may in fact be properly attributed neither to the relationally constituted individual nor its environmental interactions. It allows for a systematic means of evaluating and integrating the contributing influences of social environments on their own terms. As such this provides a means of determining whether aspects of a socially integrated psychiatry reflect a need for restructuring social environments, for the sake of their own well-being, as well as that of their respective inhabitants.

5 Conclusion

This paper has sought to provide enactive approaches to psychiatry with a means of evaluating the social influences the relationally constituted individual and its interactions. Section 1 outlined key points of divergence and convergence between various enactive proposals for a simultaneously naturalistic and socially integrative psychiatry. It was shown that, while enactive approaches to psychiatry differ in many important respects, they converge on conceptualizing psychiatric conditions in terms of relations enacted by or with a socially embedded individual. Section 2 argued that some social influences may consist not in social environmental interactions with individuals, but in the prior social environmental determination of interactants and interactions. It was argued that enactive approaches accordingly stand to benefit from a means of evaluating the contributions of social systems on their own terms. In following the enactive openness to pluralistic approaches, I have argued that Canguilhem’s definition of health as an adaptively open normative structure, offers a strongly complementary addition to social integration under an enactive approach to psychiatry. This offers one potential means of supplementing the enactive understanding of embedded individual flourishing with a means of evaluating the social systems that often influence and define that same flourishing at the systemic level.