Skip to main content
Log in

Realization Relations in Metaphysics

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

“Realization” is a technical term that is used by metaphysicians, philosophers of mind, and philosophers of science to denote some dependence relation that is thought to obtain between higher-level properties and lower-level properties. It is said that mental properties are realized by physical properties; functional and computational properties are realized by first-order properties that occupy certain causal/functional roles; dispositional properties are realized by categorical properties; so on and so forth. Given this wide usage of the term “realization”, it would be right to think that there might be different dependence relations that this term denotes in different cases. Any relation that is aptly picked out by this term can be taken to be a realization relation. The aim of this state-of-the-field article is to introduce the central questions about the concept of realization, and provide formulations of a number of realization relations. In doing so, I identify some theoretical roles realization relations should play, and discuss some theories of realization in relation to these theoretical roles.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. e.g. Chalmers (1994).

  2. e.g. Gillett (2013).

  3. There are a few sources currently in the literature some parts of which might serve the purposes of a survey on the concept of realization. Polger (2004: Ch 4) provides a critical survey of varieties of functional realization. Endicott (2005) has an encyclopaedia entry on multiple realization, which starts with a brief section on realization. Craver and Wilson (2006) explain different usages of the concept of realization in both cognitive science and metaphysics. Morris (2010) discuss a number of realization relations and makes some methodological points about theorizing about realization. Walter (2010) discusses several accounts of realization in relation to the issue of mental causation. Bennett (2011) proposes a theory of building relations some of which are the realization relations that I shall discuss in section “Some Formulations” below.

  4. More accurately, Yablo (1992) and Wilson (2009) argue that mental properties are determinable properties whose realizers are their determinates.

  5. Strictly speaking, Gillett (2002) is sceptical of the notion of a “structural property”, but argues that if there were any, they would be realized by non-structural properties and relations in the same way a higher-level property is realized by physical properties and relations.

  6. Polger (2004, 2007) makes a similar comment about the notion of functional realization. He argues that since there are many different concepts of function (i.e. causal, teleological, etc.), there should also be many different relations by which functions are realized.

  7. Two notable exceptions to this are John Heil’s and Thomas Polger’s discussions of realization. Heil (1999, 2003) analyses realization in terms of a relationship between predicates and properties: the predicate “is in pain” truly applies to different organisms which have different physical properties. If one wants to see this reference relation as a realization relation, predicates can be included in this list too. Polger takes the relation of functional realization to relate objects (bearers) to functions (functional properties): realizing a function is having a function (2004: 125).

  8. The inclusion thesis is deliberately circular: it gives us a tool to translate the property-realization talk into instance-realization talk and vice versa.

  9. I thank an anonymous referee for this observation.

  10. Yablo (1992: 253), Funkhouser (2006: 550), Shoemaker (2007: 27), and Wilson (2009: 152).

  11. In metaphysics, there is a growing literature on the notion of grounding, and arguably, the notion of dependence that is used in this paper is the same notion as grounding. In one sense, grounding is a form of metaphysical explanation. It is thought that explanation relations are different than necessitation relations in the following sense. Let us assume that my throwing the rock necessitates the breaking of the window. If this is true, then so is the following: my throwing the rock and a dog’s barking in another continent necessitate the breaking of the window. However, although the breaking of the window can be explained by my throwing the rock, it cannot be said that my throwing the rock and a dog’s barking in another continent explain the breaking of the window. The dog’s barking is explanatorily irrelevant to the breaking of the window.

  12. Shoemaker’s (1981, 2007) intended use of the term total realizer indicates a metaphysically sufficient condition.

  13. Note that this also has the following result: pace Horgan (1993), the obtaining of a supervenience relation between mental properties and physical properties, insofar as the supervenient properties are metaphysically necessitated by the subvening properties, ensures that mental properties are nothing over and above their physical supervenience bases. I thank an anonymous referee for suggesting that this should be highlighted.

  14. See Walter (2010) for a sceptical proposal about this issue. Walter argues that none of the existing theories of realization can solve the exclusion problem.

  15. See Polger (2004: Ch 5) for these and some “hybrid” concepts of function, and the associated functionalisms.

  16. See Block (1980) and Melynk (2003) for formulations of realization along these lines. Cummins (1983) also appeals to a similar account of realization when he explains how a component of a system contributes to the function of a whole system. Because of its mereological nature, I shall remark on this account in my discussion of mereological realization in 3.4 below.

  17. See Bennett (2003) for an explanation of how causal exclusion worries about mental properties and their realizers can be remedied. Bennett’s account applies to determinables and their determinates too.

  18. Jessica Wilson (2009) responds to Funkhouser’s objection, and argues that a property that is maximally determinate according to one science (e.g. psychology) can be seen as a determinable property according to another science (e.g. physics). If she is right, then Funkhouser’s maximally determinate mental properties can still be determined by physical properties.

  19. Clapp (2001: 133), Shoemaker (2007: 11) and Wilson (1999: 47–48) advertise their views as solutions to the exclusion problem.

  20. See Craver (2001) for further discussion.

  21. Similarly, Endicott (2011) reports on the dispute between the dimensioned view and the flat views of realization and argues that the debate can be solved by acknowledging that different scientific programs can appeal to different types of realization relation.

References

  • Audi, P. (2011). Properties, powers, and the subset account of realization. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84, 654–674.

  • Bennett, K. (2003). Why the exclusion problem seems intractable, and how, just maybe, to tract it. Noûs, 37, 471–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. (2011). Construction area (no hard hat required). Philosophical Studies, 154, 79–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1980). Readings in the philosophy of psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1980). Materialism without reductionism: What physicalism does not entail. In Block, 1980, 268–305.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1994). On implementing a computation. Minds and Machines, 4, 391–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clapp, L. (2001). Disjunctive properties. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 111–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2001). Role functions, mechanisms, and hierarchy. Philosophy of Science, 68, 53–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Wilson, R. (2006). Realization. In P. Thagard (Ed.), Handbook of the philosophy of psychology and cognitive science (pp. 81–104). Dordrecht: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1983). Analysis and subsumption in the behaviorism of hull. Philosophy of Science, 50, 96–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ehring, D. (1996). Mental causation, determinables and property instances. Noûs, 30, 461–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Endicott, R. (2005). Multiple realizability. In D. M. Borchert (Ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy. Farmington Hills: Macmillan Reference, Thomson Gale.

    Google Scholar 

  • Endicott, R. (2010). Realization, reductios, and category inclusion. Journal of Philosophy, 107, 213–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Endicott, R. (2011). Flat versus dimensioned: The what and the how of functional realization. Journal of Philosophical Research, 36, 191–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1974). Special sciences. Synthese, 28, 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Funkhouser, E. (2006). The determinable-determinate relation. Noûs, 40, 548–569.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, C. (2002). The dimensions of realization: A critique of the standard view. Analysis, 62, 316–323.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, C. (2003). The metaphysics of realization, multiple realizability and the special sciences. Journal of Philosophy, 100, 591–603.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, C. (2010). Moving beyond the subset model of realization: The problem of qualitative distinctness in the metaphysics of science. Synthese, 177, 165–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, C. (2013). Constitution, and multiple constitution, in the sciences: Using the neuron to construct a starting framework. Minds and Machines, 23, 309–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (1999). Multiple realizability. American Philosophical Quarterly, 36, 189–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2003). Multiply realized properties. In S. Walter & H. Heckmann (Eds.), Physicalism and mental causation (pp. 11–30). Exeter: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. (1993). From supervenience to superdupervenience: Meeting the demands of a material world. Mind, 102, 555–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1989). The myth of nonreductive physicalism. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 63, 31–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1998). Mind in a physical world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2005). Physicalism, or something near enough. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2010). Thoughts on Sydney shoemaker’s physical realization. Philosophical Studies, 148, 101–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LePore, E., & Loewer, B. (1989). More on making mind matter. Philosophical Topics, 17, 175–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (2001). Purple haze: The puzzle of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1991). Parts of classes. Oxford: Blackwell.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2009). Ramseyan humility. In D. Braddon-Mitchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism (pp. 203–222). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melnyk, A. (1996). Formulating physicalism: Two suggestions. Synthese, 105, 381–407.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Melnyk, A. (2003). A physicalist manifesto: Thoroughly modern materialism. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Melnyk, A. (2006). Realization and the formulation of physicalism. Philosophical Studies, 131, 127–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, K. (2010). Guidelines for theorizing about realization. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 48, 393–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2002). Robust nonreductive materialism. Journal of Philosophy, 99, 499–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polger, T. (2004). Natural minds. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polger, T. (2007). Realization and the metaphysics of mind. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85, 233–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polger, T., & Shapiro, L. (2008). Understanding the dimensions of realization. Journal of Philosophy, 105, 213–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, E., Pargetter, R., & Jackson, F. (1982). Three theses about dispositions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 19, 251–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967). Psychological predicates. In W. H. Capitan & D. D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind and religion (pp. 37–48). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2004). The mind incarnate. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1980). Causality and properties. In P. van Inwagen (Ed.), Time and cause: Essays presented to Richard Taylor (pp. 109–135). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1981). Some varieties of functionalism. Philosophical Topics, 12, 93–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2001). Realization and mental causation. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp. 74–98). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2007). Physical realization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2013). Physical realization without preemption. In S. C. Gibb, E. J. Lowe, & R. D. Ingthorsson (Eds.), Mental causation and ontology (pp. 35–57). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Walter, S. (2010). Taking realization seriously: No cure for epiphobia. Philosophical Studies, 15, 207–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (1999). How superduper does a physicalist supervenience need to be? The Philosophical Quarterly, 49, 33–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2009). Determination, realization, and mental causation. Philosophical Studies, 145, 149–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2011). Non-reductive realization and the powers-based subset strategy. The Monist, 94, 121–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. (2001). Two views of realization. Philosophical Studies, 104, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1992). Mental causation. Philosophical Review, 101, 245–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank two anonymous referees of Minds and Machines for their comments. The work for this article was carried out thanks to a grant provided by The Durham Emergence Project funded by the John Templeton Foundation (grant number: 40485).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Umut Baysan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Baysan, U. Realization Relations in Metaphysics. Minds & Machines 25, 247–260 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-015-9366-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-015-9366-x

Keywords

Navigation