Skip to main content
Log in

Making sense of the lived body and the lived world: meaning and presence in Husserl, Derrida and Noë

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I argue that Husserl’s transcendental account of the role of the lived body in sense-making is a precursor to Alva Noë’s recent work on the enactive, embodied mind, specifically his notion of “sensorimotor knowledge” as a form of embodied sense-making that avoids representationalism and intellectualism. Derrida’s deconstructive account of meaning—developed largely through a critique of Husserl—relies on the claim that meaning is structured through the complication of the “interiority” of consciousness by an “outside,” and thus might be thought to lend itself to theories of mind such as Noë’s that emphasize the ways in which sense-making occurs outside the head. But while Derrida’s notion of “contamination” rightly points to an indeterminateness of meaning in an outside, extended, concrete lived world, he ultimately reduces meaning to a structure of signification. This casts indeterminateness in terms of absence, ignoring the presence of non-linguistic phenomena of embodied sense-making central to both the contemporary enactivist program and to the later Husserl, who is able to account for the indeterminateness of meaning in lived experience through his distinction between sense (Sinn) and more exact linguistic meaning (Bedeutung). Husserl’s transcendental theory of meaning also allows for a substantive contribution to sense-making from the side of the perceived object—an aspect missing from Noë’s account. Thus, in contrast to Derrida and to Noë, Husserl accounts for sense-making in terms of both the lived body and the lived world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Noë mentions Husserl occasionally in his work, but rarely discusses his ideas directly or at length and does not mention him at all in Varieties of Presence. As shown below, Derrida’s relationship to Husserl is frequently acknowledged and well documented.

  2. See Noë (2015, p. 9).

  3. See Noë (2012, p. 9).

  4. Derrida is included in the list of “existential phenomenologists” in the introduction to Noë’s Varieties of Presence, but is not further discussed in the book (2012, pp. 6–7).

  5. I use “originary,” “co-originary,” and “originarily” throughout in accord with recent English translators of Derrida’s works on Husserl (Hobson and Lawlor), where it generally translates “originaire,” and in place of the terms “primordial” and “equiprimordial” more common in the English-language phenomenological literature and sometimes also used to translate Husserl’s “Ursprung” and “Urquelle.” The term refers to the question at issue between Derrida and Husserl, which concerns the notion of an origin of meaning, and not merely its originality in the everyday sense.

  6. See Husserl (1987, p. 4).

  7. See Husserl (1984, 2001b, Investigation 6, §5–6). While for Husserl the structure of intentionality is shared by a variety of intentional modalities, for the purposes of this essay I focus exclusively on perception, which he generally takes as the paradigm case in his phenomenological descriptions and which plays a central role in his explication of meaning (in the guise of Sinn or Wahrnehmungssinn) at the level of passive synthesis, where it most directly intersects with his account of the body discussed below.

  8. See Husserl (1977, p. 78; 2014, p. 66).

  9. This is related to what Rinofner-Kreidel (2013) calls this the “performance-reflection distinction” in phenomenology. I make use of this distinction (in a way that differs slightly from hers) in the rest of this paper with reference to that which is ‘performed’ or ‘non-reflective’ versus ‘reflected’ or ‘reflective.’ Note that this is not the same as the thematic versus non-thematic distinction, which has to do with attention, not reflection.

  10. See Drummond (2012), Jansen (2014).

  11. The later Husserl distinguishes between “internal” and “external” horizons (Husserl 1964a, 1973, §§8, 22). I am here referring to the internal horizon of the cabinet qua intentional object. For the sake of brevity, in the account that follows I will have to pass over several such intricacies in the Husserlian account.

  12. See Mohanty (1976, p. 139ff); Cf. Aldea (2016).

  13. Following Carr (2014, pp. 33–36), throughout this essay I distinguish between mere anticipation (implicit; protentional) in the flow of lived experience and explicit expectation about the future. Either could be in play in this example.

  14. See Gibson (1986).

  15. See Dreyfus (2005, p. 56).

  16. See Dreyfus (2007, p. 371).

  17. See Noë (2012, pp. 7–8).

  18. See Noë (2012, pp. 149ff).

  19. See Noë (2012, p. 69).

  20. See Gibson (1986, p. 134).

  21. See Gibson (1986, p. 140).

  22. Just as for Kant “the difference between the transcendental and the empirical therefore belongs only to the critique of cognitions and does not concern their relation to their object” Kant (1998, A56-57/B80-81). For a discussion of this notion in the Derridean context, see Bennington (2000, p. 82).

  23. See Rinofner-Kreidl (2013, p. 49).

  24. See Benoist (2008, p. 84).

  25. See Husserl (1964b, 1969b, passim, 1977, p. 185, 2014, p. 159); Cf. Benoist (2014). As noted above, this retention–protention structure should not be confused with the phenomena of recollection and explicit expectation about the future such as making plans or looking forward to something. The latter phenomena are necessarily thematic whereas the former are not. This is not to say that the latter play no role in meaning constitution for Husserl, but only that the role of the former in the genesis of meaning cannot be simply assimilated to that of the latter.

  26. See Michael Dummett’s preface to Husserl (2001b). This does not mean, of course, that expressed, linguistic meaning plays no role in Husserl’s account. Husserl does maintain that language helps to shape sense through its presentation in a linguistic expression, but it ultimately still “borrows” the sense from the underlying act (Smith 2006: 113–117).

  27. See Husserl (1975, 2001b, Prolegomena §3).

  28. See Husserl (1969a, 1974).

  29. See Husserl (1977, p. 258, 2014, p. 247).

  30. See Husserl (1974, p. 228, 1969a, p. 220).

  31. See Husserl (2002, p. 320).

  32. See the discussion of the “language as calculus” versus “language as universal medium” distinction in Hintikka (1984). Husserl’s work is examined explicitly in terms of this distinction in Kusch (1989, pp. 1–134).

  33. See Husserl (1974, pp. 437–46).

  34. See Husserl (1977, p. 284, 2014, p. 245). Cf. Lee Hardy, Translator’s Introduction to Husserl (1999). The exact nature of the Sinn/Bedeutung distinction in the later Husserl is as yet not extensively treated in the literature, and the interpretation presented here cannot be fully defended in this essay. For the Sinn/Bedeutung distinction in early Husserl, see Hill (1991, pp. 29–42), Vandevelde (2008), Roy (1996). Husserl never adopts the more familiar Fregean use of Sinn and Bedeutung, though he does explicitly acknowledge it in the Logical Investigations (1975, 2001b, §15). There is widespread consensus that Husserl’s use of Bedeutung corresponds more closely to Frege’s use of Sinn, whereas Husserl’s use of Sinn has no clear parallel in Frege, although its functional role is similar to the latter's later conception of Gedanken.

  35. See Husserl (1974, p. 374, 2001a, p. 33, translation modified, my emphasis).

  36. Insofar as a particular Sinn can be understood as the possible fulfillment of a meaning intention that has been made thematic through expression, it is not incorrect to say that an intended Sinn of this sort has as a condition of its possibility Bedeutung(en). But, contra Derrida (1972a, pp. 185–192, 1973, pp. 109–113) for Husserl this precondition cannot be generalized to hold for Sinne as such.

  37. Thanks to Dermot Moran for useful clarification on this point.

  38. As Drummond notes, “The assertion of an identity between the meaning of an expression and the noematic sense of an act does not entail that the noematic sense is in and of itself an intensional entity” (1990, p. 189).

  39. Derrida criticizes this notion of a pre-expressive level of sense in several places, perhaps most prominently in the section of 1972a, 1973 cited above. Since this essay appears after the more definitive treatment of Husserl in 1967b, 2011 and is said by Derrida to be ‘dependent upon it at every moment’ (1972a, 1973, note 2), I focus in the following section primarily on the book-length version, which also includes other criticisms central to the theme of this paper not as well developed in Derrida’s later essay.

  40. See Derrida (1972b, p. 378, 1982, p. 318).

  41. See Derrida (1967a, p. 227, 1997, p. 158).

  42. See Derrida (1962, p. 56, 1978, p. 66).For the notion of contamination, see Derrida (1967b, pp. 21f, 2011 pp. 17ff), and the translator’s introduction in Derrida (2011, pp. xxvff).

  43. See Derrida (1967b, pp. 97–98, 2011, pp. 74–75).

  44. See Derrida (1967b, p. 89, 2011, p. 68, first emphasis mine).

  45. See Zahavi (1999, pp. 132–37).

  46. See Derrida (1990 [1954], 2003).

  47. Derrida himself uses this language of “dialectic” in The Problem of Origin (1990, 2003).

  48. See Husserl (1970, p. 51, 1976, p. 51).

  49. Husserl does indeed occasionally use the language of “purity” in later works, especially the Crisis (1970, 1976). For a different critique of the possibility of access to the ‘pure’ lifeworld, see Carr (1974).

  50. See Derrida (1967b, p. 49n, 2011, p. 39n). See also Evans (1991, p. 143).

  51. See Derrida (1967a, p. 411, 1997, p. 290).

  52. See Derrida (1967a, p. 411, 1997, p. 290), Cf. Bennington (2000, pp. 80–92), Hodge (2009, pp. 272f).

  53. See Kant (1998, A31, A34).

  54. Cf. Lawlor, translator’s introduction to Derrida (2011, p. xxii).

  55. See Kates (2005, pp. 62ff, 72).

  56. Cf. Ruin (2010, p. 18).

  57. See Derrida (1990, p. 40, 2003, p. 4).

  58. Kates insists that this entails the need to conceive of language more radically. If the empirical existence of the sign were all that was at issue, “Derrida’s own thought would never have had to finally transgress the confines of philosophy and philosophical argumentation” (2005, p. 74).

  59. For a discussion and overview of some of the prominent positions on the status of quasi-transcendental in Derrida’s work, see Kates (2005, Ch. 1).

  60. On this point Derrida’s critique of Husserl aligns interestingly with Frege’s. See Ruin (2010), Evans (1991, pp. 131–133).

  61. See Derrida (1967b, p. 49, note, 2011, p. 39 note).

  62. See Husserl (1974, pp. 296–298, 1969a, pp. 291–293).

  63. This is at odds with Kant’s account of a priori synthetic judgment, since Kant ultimately founds the ordering of the manifold of intuition on intellectual objectivity, conceived in terms of formal intuition, which, as an intellectual activity, is considered to be dependent upon the rational employment of concepts in the understanding (Ricoeur 1967, p. 194).

  64. See Rump (2014a).

  65. It is a similar suspicion that leads Noë to include Derrida in his critique the “over-intellectualization of the intellect,” as noted above (2012, pp. 6–7).

  66. See Husserl (1970, pp. 115f, 1976, p. 118), Cf. Welton (2000, pp. 298f).

  67. See Husserl (1969a, p. 278, 1974, p. 283), Cf. Welton (1983, pp. 245ff).

  68. See Carr (1974, pp. 225ff).

  69. As Carr notes (1974, pp. 225–231) Husserl’s claim that this “dismantling” is non-reflective is highly problematic, and may even be circular. For my purposes here, what is important is only the notion that what would be revealed by such dismantling would be originary lifeworld structures independent of sedimentation and idealization.

  70. See Husserl (1964a, p. 49, 1973, p. 50).

  71. See Husserl (1964a, p. 49, 1973, p. 50, translation modified, my emphasis).

  72. See Dreyfus (2007).

  73. As Crowell puts this point, arguing for the normative character of phenomenological inquiry, “Even if practical coping and embodied engagement is not a matter of explicit thematization or rule-following, it is not opaque either, not zombie-like or robotic. Nevertheless, if we are to understand the transcendental subject of phenomenological immanence, we shall have to go beyond consciousness. Husserl understood this point clearly, since his mature work emphasized the ‘ego of habitualities,’ the constitutive contribution of the lived body, transcendental intersubjectivity, and the life-world” (2013, p. 123).

  74. See Husserl (1964a, pp. 89–90, 1973, pp. 83–84).

  75. See Husserl (1964a, p. 90, 1973, pp. 83–84).

  76. See Derrida (1967a, p. 411, 1997, pp. 290–291).

  77. See Derrida (1967a, p. 411, 1997, p. 290).

  78. See Derrida (1967a, p 411, 1997, p. 290).

  79. See Derrida (1967b, p. 89, 2011, p. 68).

  80. Thanks to an anonymous referee for a helpful discussion of this issue.

  81. See Husserl (1964a, pp. 31–32, 1973, p. 36).

  82. On the role of the notion of the “type” in Husserl’s later theory of pre-predicative experience, see Lohmar (1998).

  83. Such a case would, in a certain sense, amount to the situation that Derrida takes to be revealed by his critique.

  84. See Husserl (1964a, pp. 177f, 1973, pp. 154f).

  85. See Husserl (2000, pp. 8f, 2001a, pp. 280ff). Bower (2014) takes such observations as reasons to reject Husserl’s conception of perceptual sense (Wahrnehmungssinn). My own view is that Husserl’s conception of sense, in the case of perception, can be taken to include feeling and affect (see the example of the feeling of nostalgia at the end of Sect. 5 of this paper).

  86. The sense of objectivity at play here is thus, in an important sense, normative. This idea is explored at length in Crowell (2013). While I cannot discuss it further here, my framing of intentional objects as “unities of possible meaning” and of the “shared objectivity” of kinestheses accords with Crowell, though in my view his account does not give enough weight to ideas of the later Husserl of the sort described here [see Rump (2014b)].

  87. See Husserl (1969a, p. 279, 1974, p. 285).

  88. It is of course no coincidence that this account of kinesthesis and passive synthesis develops in the same later period in which, as noted above, Husserl moved away from a static conception of phenomenological ‘essence’ to a ‘genetic’ and more open-ended account of meaning (Cf. Costa 1998: 16ff).

  89. Cf. Crowell (2013, Ch. 5).

  90. Campbell (2008, p. 667) makes a related criticism against Noë’s earlier (2004) account. Tellingly, in his response to Campbell, Noë (2008) asserts at one point (p. 702) that sensorimotor knowledge is merely a “necessary enabling condition” for the perception of objects, but on the next page seems to equate perceptual knowledge with sensorimotor knowledge. In subsequent works (2009, 2012, 2015) Noë further addresses such objections by appeal to a broader notion of the understanding, but this notion is itself cashed out in terms of conceptuality, and thus still seems to assimilate intentional noematic content to a kind of intensional content [see Drummond (1990, p. 189; cited above), and note 94 below].

  91. Thanks to an anonymous referee for this useful formulation.

  92. See Husserl (1969a, p. 209, 1974, p. 216).

  93. See Husserl (1977, p. 203, 2014, p. 175).

  94. Noë acknowledges this Gibsonian point (2012, p. 121), but assimilates such meaning under a broadened notion of the “conceptual.” But borrowing a label typically associated with linguistic capacities to refer to something not at that level is not the same as giving an adequate phenomenological description of it on its own terms. It has not been possible in this essay to address the important difference between Noë and Husserl concerning the question of the conceptuality of non-representational meaning in embodied structures of experience—the topic of work currently in preparation. Briefly sketched: Noë continues to conceive of meaning—even at the level of embodied structures—through an extremely broad version of conceptualism. While he is clear that his notion of the concept is non-representational and not directly tied to language, his account, like the Derridean account discussed here, still relies upon a reflective notion (the concept) in accounting for a non-reflective aspect of immanent, lived experience. This view is not only suspect from the standpoint of recent work on non-conceptualism (where Husserl is again an important forebear and resource); it also ignores the problem of meaning constitution—of how we get from non-representational, embodied aspects of meaning to full-blown propositional knowledge. For a critique of John McDowell’s conceptualism along these lines, see Rump (2014a).

References

  • Aldea, Andreea Smaranda. 2016. Phenomenology as critique: Teleological–historical reflection and Husserl’s transcendental eidetics. Husserl Studies 32: 21–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennington, Geoffrey. 2000. Interrupting Derrida. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benoist, Jocelyn. 2008. Fulfilment. In Phenomenology as grammar, ed. J.P. Gálvez. Frankfurt a.M.: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benoist, Jocelyn. 2014. Intentionalität und Erfüllung: Husserlianische Meditationen über die vorgreifende Struktur der Intentionalität. In Phänomenologie der Sinnereignisse, ed. L. Tengelyi, T.N. Klass, and H. Gondek. Munich: Wilhelm Fink Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bower, Matt. 2014. Affectively driven perception: Toward a non-representational phenomenology. Husserl Studies 30: 225–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, John. 2008. Sensorimotor knowledge and naïve realism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76: 666–673.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carr, David. 1974. Phenomenology and the problem of history. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, David. 2014. Experience and history: Phenomenological perspectives on the historical world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Costa, Vincenzo. 1998. Transcendental aesthetic and the problem of transcendentality. In Alterity and facticity: New perspectives on Husserl, ed. Dan Zahavi, and Natalie Depraz. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, Steven. 2013. Normativity and phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1962. Introduction to Edmund Husserl: L’Origine de la Géométrie. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1967a. De la Grammatologie. Paris: Les Éditions de Minuit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1967b. La voix et le phénomène: Introduction au problème du signe dans la phénoménologie de Husserl. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. (ed.). 1972a. La forme et le vouloir-dire: Note sur la phénoménologie du langage. In Marges de la philosophie. Paris: Les Éditions de Minuit.

  • Derrida, Jacques. (ed.). 1972b. Signature, événement, contexte. In Marges de la philosophie. Paris: Les Éditions de Minuit.

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1973. Form and meaning: A note on the phenomenology of language. In Speech and phenomena and other essays on Husserl’s theory of signs (trans: David Allison), 107–128. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1978. Edmund Husserl’s “origin of geometry”: An introduction (trans: J.P. Leavy). Stony Brook, NY: Nicholas Hays.

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1982. Signature event context. In Margins of philosophy (trans: Alan Bass). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1990. Le Problème de la genèse dans la philosophie de Husserl. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1997. Of grammatology. Baltimore: Corrected Edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 2003. The problem of genesis in Husserl’s philosophy (trans: Marian Hobson). Chicago: University Of Chicago Press.

  • Derrida, Jacques. 2011. Voice and phenomenon: Introduction to the problem of the sign in Husserl’s phenomenology (trans: Leonard Lawlor). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Dreyfus, Hubert. 2005. Overcoming the myth of the mental: How philosophers can profit from the phenomenology of everyday expertise. In Proceedings and addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 79: 47–65.

  • Dreyfus, Hubert. 2007. Response to McDowell. Inquiry 50: 371–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John. 1990. Husserlian intentionality and non-foundational realism: Noema and object. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John. 2012. Intentionality without representationalism. In The Oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology, ed. Dan Zahavi. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J.Claude. 1991. Strategies of deconstruction: Derrida and the myth of the voice. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, James J. 1986. The ecological approach to visual perception. New York, NY: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, Claire Ortiz. 1991. Word and object in Husserl, Frege, and Russell: The roots of twentieth-century philosophy, 1st ed. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, Jaakko. 1984. A hundred years later: The rise and fall of Frege’s influence in language theory. Synthese 59: 27–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, Joanna. 2009. Topography of the border: Derrida rewriting transcendental aesthetics. In The catastrophic imperative: Subjectivity, time and memory in contemporary thought, ed. G. Buelens, D. Hoens, and S. Jöttkandt. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1964a. Erfahrung und Urteil: Untersuchung zur Genealogie der Logik, ed. Ludwig Landgrebe. Hamburg: Claassen Verlag.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1964b. the phenomenology of internal time-consciousness (trans: J.S. Churchill). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1969a. Formal and transcendental logic (trans: Dorian Cairns). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1969b. Husserliana 10. Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstesens (18931917), ed. Rudolf Boehm. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1970. The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology, ed. David Carr (trans: David Carr). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1973. Experience and judgment: Investigations in a genealogy of logic, ed. Ludwig Landgrebe (trans: James S. Churchill and Karl Ameriks). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1974. Husserliana 17. Formale und transzendentale Logik. Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft, ed. Paul Janssen. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1975. Husserliana 18. Logische Untersuchungen. Erster Teil. Prolegomena zur reinen Logik. Text der 1. und der 2. Auflage. Halle: 1900, rev. ed. 1913, ed. Elmar Holenstein. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1976. Husserliana 6. Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie. Eine Einleitung in die phänomenologische Philosophie, ed. Walter Biemel. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1977. Husserliana 3-1. Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch: Allgemeine Einführungin die reine Phänomenologie 1. Halbband: Text der 1.3. AuflageNachdruck, ed. Karl Schuhmann. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1984. Husserliana 19. Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Teil. Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. In zwei Bänden, ed. Ursula Panzer. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1987. Husserliana 26. Vorlesungen über Bedeutungslehre. Sommersemester 1908, ed. Ursula Panzer. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1999. The idea of phenomenology (trans: Lee Hardy). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2000. Husserliana 31. Aktive Synthesen: Aus der Vorlesung “Transzendentale Logik” 1920/21. Ergänzungsband zu “Analysen zur passiven Synthesis”, ed. Roland Breeur. The Hague: Kluwer.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2001a. Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: Lectures on transcendental logic (trans: Anthony Steinbock). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2001b. Logical investigations. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2002. Husserliana 20/1. Logische Untersuchungen. Ergänzungsband. Erster Teil. Entwürfe zur Umarbeitung der VI. Untersuchung und zur Vorrede für die Neuauflage der Logischen Untersuchungen (Sommer 1913), ed. Ulrich Melle. The Hague: Kluwer.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2014. Ideas for a pure phenomenology and phenomenological philosophy: First book: General introduction to pure phenomenology (trans: Dan Dahlstrom). Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • Jansen, Julia. 2014. Taking a transcendental stance: Anti-representationalism and direct realism in Kant and Husserl. In Husserl und die klassische deutsche Philosophie, ed. Faustino Fabbianelli and Sebastian Luft. Phaenomenologica 212. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1998. Critique of pure reason. In Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood, eds. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kusch, Martin. 1989. Language as calculus vs. Language as universal medium: A study in Husserl, Heidegger, and Gadamer. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, Jitendranath. 1976. Edmund husserl’s theory of meaning. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lohmar, Dieter. 1998. Erfahrung und Kategoriales Denken—Hume, Kant und Husserl über vorprädikative Erfahrung und prädikative Erkenntnis. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, Alva. 2004. Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, Alva. 2008. Reply to Campbell, Martin, and Kelly. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76: 691–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, Alva. 2009. Conscious reference. The Philosophical Quarterly 59: 470–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, Alva. 2012. Varieties of presence. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, Alva. 2015. Concept pluralism, direct perception, and the fragility of presence. In Thomas Metzinger and Jennifer M. Windt ed. Open MIND. Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

  • Ricoeur, Paul. 1967. Husserl: An analysis of his phenomenology (trans: Edward G. Ballard and Lester E. Embree). Northwestern University Press.

  • Rinofner-Kreidel, Sonja. 2013. Mental contents, transparency, realism: News from the phenomenological camp. Husserl Studies 29: 33–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roy, Jean-Michel, and Jean-François Courtine. 1996. La dissociation Husserlienne du Sinn et de la Bedeutung. In Phénoménologique et Logique, 149–169. Paris: Presses de l’Ecole Normale Superieur.

  • Ruin, Hans. 2010. Seeing meaning: Frege and Derrida on ideality and the limits of Husserlian intuitionism. Husserl Studies 27: 63–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rump, Jacob. 2014a. Kant, Husserl, and the Case for Non-Conceptual Content. In Husserl und die klassische deutsche Philosophie, ed. Faustino Fabbianelli, and Sebastian Luft, 281–295. Berlin: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-01710-5_19.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rump, Jacob. 2014b. Steven Crowell: Normativity and phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. Continental Philosophy Review 47: 479–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, David Woodruff. 2006. Husserl. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vandevelde, Pol. 2008. An unpleasant but felicitous ambiguity. In Meaning and language: Phenomenological perspectives, ed. F. Mattens. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welton, Donn. 1983. The origins of meaning: A critical study of the thresholds of Husserlian phenomenology. The Hague: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Welton, Donn. 2000. The other Husserl: The horizons of transcendental phenomenology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, Dan. 1999. Self-awareness and alterity: A phenomenological investigation. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Walter Hopp and Lisa Chinn for helpful conversations concerning the ideas in this paper, David Carr and Dermot Moran for comments on earlier drafts of some of the material, and an anonymous referee for extremely helpful insights and suggestions on a previous draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jacob Martin Rump.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rump, J.M. Making sense of the lived body and the lived world: meaning and presence in Husserl, Derrida and Noë. Cont Philos Rev 51, 141–167 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-017-9415-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-017-9415-7

Keywords

Navigation