Skip to main content
Log in

Morality and Interpretation: the Principle of Phronetic Charity

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The recent discussions on the unity of virtue (or lack thereof) suffer from a lack of reference to the processes through which we interpret each other as moral agents. In the present paper it is argued that much light can be thrown on that crucial issue by appealing to a version of Donald Davidson’s Principle of Charity, which we call “Principle of Phronetic Charity”. The idea is that in order to treat somebody as a moral agent, one has first to attribute to them, at least pro tempore, a significant degree of practical wisdom (intended as ethical expertise) and, then, to assess and rationally adjust such attribution of competence via actual engagement with them – a process that may lead to different responses on the part of the interpreter (i.e., the confirmation, upgrading, or withdrawing of the preliminary interpretation). After expounding and defending the Principle of Phronetic Charity and the interpretive practices connected with it, we discuss the repercussions of our account on the issue of the epistemic access to virtue. We will show, in particular, that some important components of both disunitarianism and unitarianism have to be retained: in accordance with the former, we stress the role of concrete experience over pure speculation and, up to a point, the idea that virtues tend to form variegated ensembles; in accordance with the latter, we accept the claim that virtues are not attributed to moral agents in isolation. Ultimately, however, the account developed here rejects both the atomism of the disunitarian view and the holism of the “Unity of the Virtues”, since it is in fact a form of molecularism, according to which virtues come neither individually nor as a whole, but rather as clusters.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Typically, disunitarians like Foot (1978), Nagel (1979), Williams (1982), Walker (1993), and Badhwar (1996) either do not believe the virtues to be mutually compatible (what Badhwar calls ‘Mutual Incompatibility of the Virtues’, and Walker ‘Conflict Assumption’) or claim that there is no need for a virtue to be accompanied by all others to be genuine (‘Mutual Independence of the Virtues’, in Badhwar’s words).

  2. A third, related question, which we cannot discuss here, concerns the ontogenetic level, i.e., the analysis of virtue acquisition. We discuss this issue in [reference removed for blind review] De Caro et al. (2018).

  3. For brevity, in the following, we accept Davidson’s use of “beliefs” as a label for all intentional states relevant for interpretation (see Davidson 1984a, 1984b).

  4. Meaning molecularism (from which molecularism about belief content conceptually depends) has been convincingly advocated, in different forms, by Dummett 1973, Devitt 1993, Perry 1994, and Marconi 1997. Such a view, besides being alternative to meaning holism, is also an alternative to meaning atomism, the view on which the meaning of basic semantic entities (be they words or sentences) does not depend on the meaning of other semantic entities. Analogously, molecularism about belief content opposes the related versions of holism and atomism.

  5. With the term “the good” Davidson, of course, does not refer to an abstract entity or universal (following Quine, he notoriously rejected all abstract entities as entia non grata, with the usual exception of sets and numbers), but only a substantive set of interrelated moral beliefs.

  6. Not all interpretations are necessarily also moral interpretations (think of the interactions between two people who ferociously hate each other: they still need to interpret each other, but morality is not their concern). However, as long an interpretation involves the attribution of morality to the interpreted speakers, we believe that the specific version of the Principle of Charity that we call Principle of Phronetic Charity is involved in the process.

  7. One can imagine a situation in which an interpreter does not know anything about the moral views of the interpreted speakers. This, however, would simply be a special instance of Davidson’s radical interpretation; but, as it in the latter case, it would not be in principle different from everyday moral interpretations.

  8. We have defended this view at more length in De Caro et al. 2018.

  9. Gulliford and Roberts (2018) have proposed an interesting functional analysis of virtues that conceives of them as dived in three big clusters (unified, respectively, around intelligent caring, willpower, and humility). This is an interesting proposal, but here we are not committed to any specific identification of the clusters of virtues that are necessary for moral interpretations (it may even be that such clusters vary depending on the concrete situation in which an interpretation occurs).

  10. This natural tendency is exploited by professional cheaters, who are able to produce in their interlocutors the impression that they seriously desire to be virtuous in general and that, consequently, they are trustworthy (films such as House of Games and American Hustle expose such moral-psychological dynamics brilliantly).

  11. We also believe that McDowell has gone too far in characterizing each virtue in Platonic terms. In his words, a virtue is a kind of “reliable sensitivity to a certain sort of requirement that situations impose on behavior;” it consists in “a sort of perceptual capacity;” and “the specialized sensitivities that are to be equated with particular virtues […] are actually not available one by one for a series of separate identifications” (1998, 51–52). In sum, according to McDowell, any attempt to identify a specific virtue would be useless, since no such thing would ever be available to an agent and/or to an interpreter. This view, in our opinion, is too extreme.

  12. Arguably, the most influential empirically-based attack on the virtues is the so-called “situationist criticism”, which rejects traditional accounts of ethical virtues and their essentialism, in that they would presuppose cross-situational identity of all the acts falling under the scope of the same virtue (see Doris 1998, 2002, and Harman 1999, 2000).

  13. We thank Dan Lapsley, Darcia Narvaez, Ariele Niccoli and Juliette Vazard for their observations on the talk that this article is based on, and Robert Audi, Leonard de Leon and Leonardo Moauro for the useful comments on previous versions of it.

References

  • Annas J (1993) The morality of happiness. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Annas J (2011) Intelligent Virtue. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Badhwar NK (1996) The limited Unity of virtue. Nous 30(3):306–329

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1970) Mental Events. Reprinted in Davidson 1980:207–227

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D (1973). “Radical Interpretation.” Reprinted in Davidson 1984b, 125–39

  • Davidson, D (1974). “Belief and the Basis of Meaning.” Reprinted in Davidson 1984b, 141–54

  • Davidson, D (1977). “The Method of Truth in Metaphysics.” Reprinted in Davidson 1984b, 199–214

  • Davidson D (1980). Essays on actions and events. Clarendon Press, Oxford

  • Davidson D (1984a) Expressing evaluations (the Lindley lecture). University of Kansas, Lawrence

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1984b) Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D (1984c). “Introduction” to Davidson 1984b, 13–20

  • Davidson D (1986) A Nice derangement of epitaphs. In: Grandy R, Warner R (eds) Philosophical grounds of rationality: intentions, categories, ends. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 156–174

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D (1991). “Three Varieties of Knowledge.” Reprinted in Id. Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001, 205–220

  • Davidson D (1994) Radical Interpretation Interpreted. In: Tomberlin J (ed) Epistemology, Philosophical perspectives, vol 2. Atascadero, Ridgeview, pp 121–128

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D (1999). “Interpretation: hard in theory, easy in practice.” In M. De Caro (ed.) Interpretations and Causes. New Perspectives on Donald Davidson’s Philosophy. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 31–44

  • De Caro M, Vaccarezza MS, Niccoli A (2018) Phronesis as ethical expertise: naturalism of second nature and the Unity of virtue. Journal of Value Inquiry 52(3):287–305

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M (1993). “A Critique of the Case for Semantic Holism.” Philosophical Perspectives, 7 (Logic and Language): 281–306

  • Doris JM (1998) Persons, situations, and virtue ethics. Noûs 32(4):504–530

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris JM (2002) Lack of character: personality and moral behaviour. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett M (1973) Frege, philosophy of language. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot P (1978) Virtue and vices and other essays in moral philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker-Wright J (2015) Skill, practical wisdom, and ethical naturalism. Ethical Theory and Moral Pratice 18:983–993

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1999). “Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology: Virtue Ethics and the Fundamental Attribution Error.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series (119): 316–31

  • Harman G (2000) The nonexistence of character traits. In: Byrne A, Stalnaker R, Wedgwood R (eds) Fact and value. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 117–127

    Google Scholar 

  • Irwin TH (1988). “Disunity in the Aristotelian Virtues.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, suppl. vol.: 61–78

  • Marconi D (1997) Lexical Competence. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (1998). “Virtue and Reason.” In Id., Mind, Value and Reality, Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press, 50–73

  • Nagel T (1979). “The Fragmentation of Value.” In Id., Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 128–141

  • Nagel T (1986) The view from nowhere. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Narvaez D, Lapsley DK (2005) The psychological foundations of everyday morality and moral expertise. In: Lapsley DK, Power FC (eds) Character psychology and character education. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, IN, US, pp 140–165

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry J (1994) Fodor and Lepore on holism. Philos Rev 86:474–497

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rees CF, Webber J (2014) Constancy, fidelity and integrity. In: Van Hooft S (ed) The handbook of virtue ethics. Acumen Press, Durham, pp 399–408

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell DC (2009) Practical intelligence and the virtues. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swanton C (2003) Virtue ethics: a pluralistic view. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walker ADM (1993) The incompatibility of the virtues. Ratio 6:44–62

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1982). “Conflicts of Values,” In Id., Moral Luck, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 71–82

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maria Silvia Vaccarezza.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

De Caro, M., Vaccarezza, M.S. Morality and Interpretation: the Principle of Phronetic Charity. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 23, 295–307 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-019-10054-2

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-019-10054-2

Keywords

Navigation