1 Introduction

Knowledge defeat is said to occur when a subject knows that p, then gains a putative defeater for her belief, and thereby loses her knowledge that p without necessarily losing her belief that p or any relevant evidence. Accommodating the phenomenon of knowledge defeat isn’t easy for externalist theories of knowledge.Footnote 1 Indeed, some of the best arguments that have been mounted against externalism rely on putative cases of knowledge defeat.Footnote 2 Here are two representative cases:

Red light

At t1 Yen comes to know that the wall in front of her is red via perception in optimal conditions. At t2 Yen’s trusted friend Triss tells her that the wall is illuminated by red light that would have made the wall look red even if it had been of some other colour.Footnote 3

Feint

At t1 Ciri remembers that she has a fencing session at four o’clock. There is nothing wrong with her memory, and her belief qualifies as knowledge. At t2 Ciri’s friend Zoltan tells her that he just came from the fencing hall and saw on the calendar that Ciri’s fencing lesson is at five o’clock.Footnote 4

The defeatist intuition is that Yen and Ciri must lose their knowledge after acquiring the defeater, even if they hold onto their respective beliefs. The defeatists claim that acquiring a defeater for a belief that qualifies as knowledge suffices in itself to defeat the knowledge-status of the belief. Externalist theories of knowledge have a difficult time accommodating the defeatist intuition because it’s far from obvious that Yen and Ciri cannot continue to hold onto their beliefs in a reliable way, given that the beliefs were reliably formed and maintained before they were made aware of the defeaters. For example, if knowledge is safe belief, that is, a belief that could not easily be false given the basis on which it’s held, then assuming that Yen’s and Ciri’s beliefs were safe at t1 it’s hard to see why they could not be safe at t2.Footnote 5 After all, simply acquiring new information need not change the modal profile of the belief.Footnote 6 Yen and Ciri can simply fail to rebase their beliefs on their new evidence. If Yen is asked why she believes that the wall is red, she will reply that she sees that the wall is red. She won’t reply that she knows that the wall is red because she sees that the wall is red even though the wall is illuminated by red light that would have made it look red even if it was not red. Of course, if Yen and Ciri do rebase their beliefs on their new evidence, then their beliefs might become unsafe, since they might have formed a different belief, which would have been false. But whether Yen and Ciri rebase their beliefs is a contingent matter, and therefore their knowledge need not be defeated by the putative defeater, contra the defeatist intuition (Lasonen-Aarnio, 2010).Footnote 7

Therefore, it isn’t easy to see how externalist theories of knowledge could accommodate putative cases of knowledge defeat. An option that used to be popular was to add a no-defeaters clause to the externalist theory of knowledge.Footnote 8 Those who have been unwilling to add a seemingly ad hoc no-defeaters clause to their accounts of justification or knowledge have aimed to accommodate intuitions of knowledge defeat via error-theories.

Lasonen-Aarnio (2010, 2014, forthcoming-b) has argued that knowledge can sometimes be retained in putative cases of knowledge defeat. Our negative assessment of subjects who retain their knowledge in such cases is explained by the fact that they are manifesting bad dispositions, dispositions that would in general be manifested in cases of ignorance, rather than in cases of knowledge. Baker-Hytch and Benton (2015, p. 57) have argued that if knowledge is the norm of belief, then the apparent irrationality of subjects who retain their beliefs in face of misleading evidence can be explained by the fact that such subjects violate a guidance norm that is generated by the knowledge norm of belief.Footnote 9

While I am very sympathetic to both Lasonen-Aarnio’s proposal and to Baker-Hytch and Benton’s account, I wish to sketch a new kind of error-theory that falls directly out of virtue reliabilism. The error-theory I propose differs significantly from the earlier ones. According to it, in cases where the subject dogmatically clings onto her belief she never knew to begin with, or did not acquire a putative defeater in the first place, while in cases where the subject suspends judgment she might have known, but doesn’t any more since she lacks the relevant belief. It’s an error theory for two reasons. Firstly, in some cases of putative knowledge defeat we mistakenly think that the subject had knowledge to begin with. Secondly, according to the view putative defeaters cannot on their own defeat knowledge. The defeatist intuition is explained by the fact that there are no cases where a subject knows that p at t1, and retains her knowledge of p after having received a putative defeater for p at t2.

Some readers might think that the error-theory provided is too radical. These readers are invited to see this paper as offering an argument against virtue reliabilism, since the error-theory I present falls directly out of the main tenets of virtue reliabilism. My sole aim here is to examine what consequences virtue reliabilism has for defeat.

In what follows, I’ll focus on cases like Red light and Feint that involve so-called doxastic or mental-state defeaters. All doxastic defeaters are beliefs. For instance, in ‘Red light’ the defeater that Yen has is her belief that [the wall is illuminated by red light that would have made the wall look red no matter its actual colour]. I’ll set aside cases that feature propositional or normative defeaters (Lackey, 1999). A propositional defeater for the belief that p is a true proposition such that if S were to believe it, then S wouldn’t know that p. A normative defeater is a propositional defeater that the subject should have believed. There are two reasons why I limit the scope of inquiry to the potential epistemic force of doxastic defeaters. Firstly, cases featuring doxastic defeaters are the most plausible cases of knowledge defeat. If it turned out that doxastic defeaters are void of epistemic power, as I hope to show, then there is reason to think that propositional and normative defeaters are void of epistemic power too. Secondly, I think that cases of propositional and normative defeat are highly contentious. In my mind it’s better not to use such cases when evaluating a theory. Henceforth all talk of defeaters refers to doxastic defeaters.

This essay is structured as follows. In the next section I lay out some key ideas of virtue reliabilism. In the third section I spell out under what conditions a belief can function as a defeater. In the fourth section I examine whether knowledge defeat is a genuine phenomenon, under the assumption that knowledge is always the product of one’s cognitive abilities. In the fifth section I briefly compare my account to other virtue theoretic solutions.

2 Virtue and Coherence of Character

The central thesis of virtue reliabilism is that knowledge requires that one’s cognitive success must be attributable to one’s cognitive character. Some virtue epistemologists see this central thesis as giving both necessary and sufficient conditions for knowledge.Footnote 10 Others think that it provides only a necessary condition for knowledge.Footnote 11 The central thesis can be interpreted in various ways. A cognitive success can be understood either as the acquisition or maintaining of a true belief, or as the acquisition or maintaining of knowledge. The former views belong to the classical tradition of analyzing knowledge in terms of true belief plus some other conditions.Footnote 12 The latter views belong to the knowledge first movement, championed by Williamson (2000).Footnote 13

Another aspect in which the central thesis is ambiguous is on the question when a cognitive success is attributable to the subject’s cognitive abilities. According to Greco (2010), the truth of a subject’s belief is attributable to her cognitive character just in case the fact that she believes out of cognitive character is part of the most salient causal explanation why she acquired a true, rather than a false belief. In other words, one’s cognitive character has to be an important part of the best causal explanation for one’s cognitive success in order for one to know. According to Sosa (2007, 2009), one’s cognitive success is attributable to one’s cognitive character just in case one’s cognitive success is a manifestation of the cognitive abilities that make up one’s cognitive character. Thus Sosa’s seeks to understand the attribution relation in terms of a more general metaphysical relation, namely, as the manifestation of a disposition. Many have preferred Sosa’s account to Greco’s, probably because Sosa is able to side-step some counterexamples that Greco’s account seems susceptible to.Footnote 14

Here we need not be concerned with these issues. The argument I offer doesn’t depend on how one understands cognitive success, nor on how we flesh out the attribution clause. In fact, virtue-theoretic views that don’t invoke the attribution relation, but merely require that one’s belief has to be the product of one’s cognitive abilities, also fall under the scope of the views I wish to discuss.Footnote 15 What all of these views share is the idea that knowledge requires the use of cognitive abilities. In order to make use of a cognitive ability one must possess that ability. But under what kind of conditions does one possess a certain ability?

In a broadly Aristotelian spirit, virtue epistemologists think that a reliable doxastic disposition can count as a cognitive virtue only if it’s a proper part of one’s virtuous epistemic character (Greco, 1999, p. 287; 2010, p. 150; Palermos, 2014, p. 1940; Pritchard, 2012, p. 262).Footnote 16Footnote 17 This is what differentiates virtue reliabilism form process reliabilism. Virtue reliabilists require that the reliable processes be properly grounded in the subject in order to be knowledge-conducive. According to them, not all reliable doxastic dispositions count as cognitive abilities. If Alvin has a brain lesion that causes him to believe that he has a brain lesion, his belief is the product of an extremely reliable doxastic disposition, but it’s not a product of his cognitive abilities, because the brain lesion isn’t a part of Alvin’s cognitive character (Breyer & Greco, 2008, p. 174; Greco, 2010, p. 151; Palermos, 2014, p. 1938).Footnote 18

But under what conditions is a reliable doxastic disposition a proper part of one’s cognitive character? At least three conditions have been proposed by virtue reliabilists; (1) that the disposition is stable, (2) that it’s not strange, and, (3) that it’s integrated into the subject’s cognitive character (Greco, 2010, p. 150). The central idea behind these conditions is to ensure that in order for a doxastic disposition to be a part of one’s cognitive character it has to be the agent’s disposition. Beliefs that are products of such cognitive abilities are in a sense owned by the subject, in that she is responsible for those beliefs and can be properly blamed or credited for having those beliefs. I’ll focus on condition (3), since it seems to be the most central one, and is more widely endorsed than conditions (1) and (2).Footnote 19

What suffices for cognitive integration varies from case to case. In some extreme cases, like in the brain lesion case, reflective endorsement of the truth-conduciveness of the disposition might be required (Pritchard, 2010). If, for instance, Alvin went to see a doctor who told him that he suffers from an extremely rare brain lesion that causes one to believe that one suffers from a brain lesion, the doxastic disposition generated by the brain lesion could become a part of Alvin’s cognitive character. But this kind of reflective endorsement is almost never required in more mundane cases. Doxastic dispositions that are innate, or otherwise naturally developed, are integrated into our cognitive system via subconscious mechanisms in virtue of constantly confirming each other’s outputs. Consider for example the following description of Edgar’s afternoon: Edgar sees a beautiful pint of ale and can smell the overwhelming aroma of the hops. He can feel the cold glass in his hand and sipping the beer, finds delightful notes of pine, citrus and tropical fruits. Pricking his ears he can even hear the dense head slowly dissolving, and thinks: “I’m drinking ale today”. All of these experiences confirm to Edgar that there’s a pint of ale on the table.

In Edgar’s case all of his sensory modalities part-take in confirming a single proposition. Of course this isn’t always the case. For many sensible qualities it applies that they can be sensed directly only via some particular sense modality. No one can hear the redness of the wall. Its redness can only be seen. However, many of our experiences are multi-modal in that multiple sense modalities are responsible for our phenomenological state. And it’s not just the case that our sense modalities confirm the outputs of each other. Rather, in many cases our sense modalities affect the outputs and operation of our other sense modalities.Footnote 20

A minimal externalist condition for cognitive integration is that the cognitive abilities act in concert with each other. Greco (2010, p. 152) writes that “cognitive integration is a function of cooperation and interaction, or cooperative interaction, with other aspects of the cognitive system.” Palermos (2014, pp. 1941–1942) holds that “the only necessary and sufficient condition for a process to count as knowledge-conducive is that it cooperatively interacts with the rest of the agent’s cognitive character. [The] process of cognitive integration gives rise to a coherentist effect both on the level of processes (how the beliefs are generated) and on the level of content (how the beliefs themselves combine).” Pritchard (2010, pp. 147–148) holds that a doxastic disposition D is integrated to the subject’s cognitive character only if beliefs gained via a D have cohered with the beliefs formed via the subject’s other cognitive abilities, and that if they had not, then the subject would have responded accordingly. Sosa argues also that knowledge never arises purely from one faculty, but from the interplay of cognitive faculties.Footnote 21 He writes:

Note that no human blessed with reason has merely animal knowledge of the sort attainable by beasts. For even when perceptual belief derives as directly as it ever does from sensory stimuli, it is still relevant that one has not perceived the signs of contrary testimony. A reason-endowed being automatically monitors his background information and his sensory input for contrary evidence and automatically opts for the most coherent hypothesis even when he responds most directly to sensory stimuli. […] The beliefs of a rational animal hence would seem never to issue from unaided introspection, memory, or perception. For reason is always at least a silent partner on the watch for other relevant data, a silent partner whose very silence is a contributing cause of the belief outcome. (Sosa, 1991, p. 240)

This kind of minimal integration doesn’t require any perspective on the truth conduciveness of the dispositions. The only thing that is required is that the doxastic dispositions that make up one’s virtuous cognitive character are not acting in conflict with each other. Hence we are able to lay down the following condition for minimal cognitive integration:

INTEGRATION: Subject S’s doxastic disposition D is integrated with her cognitive character only if D would act in concert with the set of doxastic dispositions D* that together with D make up S’s cognitive character if D were triggered while both D and D* are in appropriate conditions.

Given INTEGRATION, a reliable doxastic disposition can qualify as a cognitive ability just in case it acts, or would act, in concert with one’s cognitive character, while in appropriate conditions.Footnote 22 According to virtue reliabilism only beliefs gained via cognitive abilities can have positive epistemic statuses like justification or knowledge. Knowledge and justification require a kind of coherence of one’s cognitive faculties. For a subject to be eligible for such normative statuses she must keep her cognitive home in order.Footnote 23

One might object that INTEGRATION is too strong. Even though I know by testimony that the Müller-Lyer lines are equally long I still see them as of different lengths. When in the grips of the Müller-Lyer illusion my eyesight doesn’t seem to act in concert with the other doxastic dispositions that make up my cognitive character. But here it’s important to note that I don’t form the belief that the lines are of different lengths on the basis of my perceptual experience when I know that they are of the same length. The fact that I don’t form the belief is evidence that my eyesight is acting in concert with my cognitive character, since the knowledge that I’ve gained through my other cognitive faculties prevents me from forming a belief that corresponds to the experiential-state generated by my eyesight.

It would be good if we could say more about what it takes for two doxastic dispositions to act in concert with each other. Sadly virtue reliabilists have been largely silent on this issue. What seems clear, however, is that two doxastic dispositions can act in concert with each other just in case the dispositions are appropriately sensitive to each other’s outputs. It’s clear that in cases where the dispositions generate beliefs that are logically inconsistent, the dispositions are not sensitive to each other’s outputs. But while logical inconsistency of the outputs suffices to show that the doxastic dispositions are not properly integrated with the subject’s cognitive character, it cannot be a necessary condition. If the doxastic disposition D generates in me the belief that p and another doxastic disposition D* generates in me the belief [I don’t know that p] then D and D* are acting in tension with each other, even though p and [I don’t know that p] are not logically inconsistent.

A tempting way to explain the tension between D and D* is to appeal to the fact that the outputs that they generated cannot amount to knowledge simultaneously. We could then claim that two doxastic dispositions are acting in concert with each other only if it’s possible that the outputs amount to knowledge on the condition that both outputs are true. This constraint on cognitive integration is supported by the idea that knowledge is the norm of belief.Footnote 24 The purpose of our cognitive abilities is to provide a unified picture of the world that amounts to knowledge. If our doxastic dispositions are acting against each other in such a way that achieving this aim is impossible, then at least some of those doxastic dispositions are not integrated with our cognitive character.

However, by saying that two doxastic dispositions can act in concert with each other just in case the outputs they yield could have amounted to knowledge simultaneously threatens to make virtue reliabilism a circular theory of knowledge. While this would probably suit knowledge first virtue reliabilists like Kelp and Miracchi, it’s doubtful whether those who aim to provide a reductive virtue-theoretic analysis of knowledge should understand cognitive integration in this way.

But here it’s important to note that we need not commit ourselves to the idea that cognitive integration should ultimately be understood in terms of knowledge. Rather, we can only note that when it’s in principle impossible that the two outputs could have amounted to knowledge if they were true, then the doxastic dispositions that produced the outputs are not acting in concert. True, we will use our pre-theoretic understanding of knowledge when determining whether a doxastic disposition is integrated to the subject’s cognitive character, as does Williamson (2000) when he uses our pre-theoretic understanding of knowledge to determine whether a belief is safe. But this need not make virtue reliabilism a circular theory of knowledge. Virtue reliabilists are still free to unpack the notion of cognitive integration without appealing to knowledge. All we require here is that the way in which virtue reliabilists end up unpacking cognitive integration entails that two doxastic dispositions that are acting in a ‘knowledge-inconsistent way’ are not acting in concert with each other.

Finally, it’s worth keeping in mind that virtue reliabilists relativize cognitive abilities to normal or appropriate conditions and environments (Greco, 2010; Sosa, 2010). This means that cognitive abilities can be lost when moving to environments that are not suitable for the use of those abilities. The fact that one’s doxastic dispositions don’t act in concert in some such conditions and environments doesn’t mean that those doxastic dispositions wouldn’t qualify as cognitive virtues in more suitable environments and conditions, where the doxastic dispositions in question are in the market of being cognitive abilities. This helps to alleviate the pressure to think that INTEGRATION is a too strong condition.

In the next section we examine under what kind of conditions a belief can serve as a defeater.

3 Defeat and Justification

I’ll assume that only those beliefs that have a positive epistemic status can serve as defeaters. I think that this positive epistemic status is justification. Irrational and unjustified beliefs cannot serve to defeat knowledge or justified beliefs. I take this to be the mainstream position among epistemologists,Footnote 25 but it’ll be useful to go through the rationale for this position, since it plays a pivotal role in the next section.

Often some of our beliefs confer justification on our other beliefs. The fact that I know that the drink is laced with hemlock justifies me in believing that the drink is poisonous. In this case my knowledge entails the truth of the latter belief. But if I believed out of sheer paranoia that the drink is laced with hemlock, I wouldn’t be justified in believing that the drink is poisonous. While the contents of my beliefs in the above cases stand in exactly the same logical relations, my belief that the drink is poisonous isn’t justified in the latter case, since there is no justification to be transmitted from my belief that the drink is laced with hemlock. Similarly, if I were to believe out of wishful thinking that England is going to lose the game, I wouldn’t thereby be justified in believing that Italy is going to win the game. If justified beliefs could be built on paranoia and wishful thinking living a good epistemic life would be all too easy.

Given that irrational and unjustified beliefs cannot confer positive epistemic statuses on our other beliefs, it would be prima facie bizarre if they could render our justified beliefs unjustified. How could they have only this kind of negative epistemic import? Moreover, if irrational and unjustified beliefs can defeat justified beliefs, then they can also serve to restore the justificatory status of beliefs (Casullo, 2018).Footnote 26 This is because a putative defeater d can be defeated by yet another putative defeater d’, rendering the original belief justified once again (Pollock, 1987). One shouldn’t be able to restore the justificatory status of a defeated belief by irrationally believing that the putative defeater doesn’t defeat one’s original belief. Otherwise irrational and unjustified beliefs can confer justification to our beliefs. Therefore, only justified beliefs can serve as defeaters.

Virtue reliabilists think that a subject S’s belief is justified if, and only if it’s an exercise of S’s cognitive abilities (Greco, 2002, p. 311; 2010; Kelp, 2017, p. 238; Miracchi, 2015, p. 48; Sosa, 1991, p. 189). Given that beliefs need to be justified in order to serve as defeaters, a defeater-belief must be a product of one’s cognitive abilities.

4 Defeat of the Virtues?

So far I’ve shown that virtue reliabilists are committed to the idea that knowledge arises from exercises of cognitive abilities and that a doxastic disposition can qualify as a cognitive ability only if it’s suitably integrated with the cognitive character of the subject. I’ve also explained that in order for a putative defeater to have potential normative import, it must be the case that the defeater enjoys a positive epistemic standing. I assume that the defeater has to be justified in order to have potential normative import. On virtue reliabilism justified beliefs are exercises of cognitive abilities. Therefore, the defeater belief has to be an exercise of a cognitive ability in order to have potential normative import. Given this, what must virtue reliabilists say about the phenomenon of knowledge defeat?

Consider a paradigmatic case of knowledge defeat like Red light:

At t1 Yen comes to know that the wall in front of her is red via perception in optimal conditions. At t2 Yen’s trusted friend Triss tells her that the wall is illuminated by red light that would have made the wall look red even if it had been of some other colour.

In order for Red light to be a potential case of knowledge defeat it must be the case that Yen’s belief that the wall is red is a product of her cognitive abilities. Otherwise her belief could not have qualified as knowledge at t1. It must also be the case that her belief that [the wall is illuminated by red light that would have made the wall look red whatever its actual colour is] is a product of her cognitive abilities since otherwise the defeater belief wouldn’t be justified, and hence wouldn’t have any defeating force. Now suppose that Yen dogmatically clings to her belief that the wall is red after forming a justified belief in the defeater. Given that the defeater supports that her original belief doesn’t qualify as knowledge, what should virtue reliabilists say about this case?

I think that virtue reliabilists are committed to claiming that the case, when described in this way, is metaphysically impossible. It cannot be the case that both Yen’s original belief and her defeater belief are products of her cognitive abilities. Why? Because the doxastic dispositions that generate these beliefs are clearly acting in tension, rather than in concert with each other. After all, the way in which Yen believes that the wall is red can only constitute knowledge if her defeater belief isn’t knowledge and vice versa. This is because if Yen knows by visual perception alone that the wall is red at t1 it cannot be the case that wall is bathed in red light at t1, because then the colour that Yen would have seen would be that which the red light cast on the wall and not the redness of the wall. The truth of Yen’s perceptual belief would lack an appropriate causal connection to what makes it true. Similarly, Yen cannot know via testimony that the wall was bathed in red light at t1 if she knew by visual perception alone that the wall is red at t1. After all, if the wall was bathed in red light at t1 the truth of Yen’s perceptual belief would have lacked an appropriate casual connection to what makes it true, and hence she couldn’t have known by visual perception that the wall is red. So while the contents of the doxastic outputs are not logically inconsistent, the ways in which the beliefs are formed are epistemically inconsistent in that both beliefs could not have constituted knowledge simultaneously.

Recall that INTEGRATION requires that the subject’s doxastic dispositions would act in concert with the other doxastic dispositions that make up the subject’s cognitive character if it were triggered. In cases where the subject dogmatically clings onto her belief after forming a justified belief in the putative defeater, this counterfactual is false. Importantly, the counterfactual was already false at the moment when the subject formed her original belief, and hence the subject’s original belief was not a product of her cognitive abilities, and cannot qualify as knowledge. Therefore, if the defeater belief is justified, and the subject holds onto her original belief after receiving the putative defeater, her original belief never amounted to knowledge to begin with. Since the subject never acquires knowledge in this first variant of the case, there is no knowledge defeat.

Alternatively, it could be the case that Yen’s defeater belief isn’t a product of her cognitive abilities, in which case the belief would be unjustified. But if it’s true that unjustified beliefs cannot serve as defeaters Yen doesn’t have a defeater for her belief that the wall is red. Moreover, since Yen’s defeater belief isn’t a product of her cognitive abilities, the doxastic dispositions that help to constitute her cognitive character are not acting in tension with each other if she holds onto her original belief. Therefore, Yen can know that the wall is red. And since Yen can continue to know in this second variant of the case that the wall is red after t2 there is no knowledge defeat in this variant either.

But suppose that instead of dogmatically holding onto her belief, Yen suspends judgment after having formed a justified belief in the defeater. In this third variant Yen’s original belief might have amounted to knowledge, since the cognitive abilities that are responsible for her perceptual belief are acting in concert with her cognitive character. In this version Yen is acting in the same way as the subject who cannot fail to see the Müller-Lyer lines as being of different lengths but nevertheless doesn’t believe that they are of different lengths after having learned, perhaps by testimony, that the Müller-Lyer lines constitute a known illusion. But while Yen’s original belief and her defeater belief might be products of her cognitive abilities in this variant of the case, there is no knowledge defeat in this case either. It’s true that she doesn’t know that the wall is red after having received the putative defeater, but this is because she doesn’t believe that the wall is red after having received it. It’s not the defeater that robs her of knowledge; it’s her lack of belief. Below is a table that summarizes these different variants.

 

Original belief justified

Defeater belief justified

Suspends judgment

Knowledge defeated

Variant 1

No

Yes

No

No

Variant 2

Yes

No

No

No

Variant 3

Yes

Yes

Yes

No

But while knowledge defeat doesn’t occur in any of the three variants, it’s not impossible for Yen to lose her knowledge while holding onto her original belief. If Yen were to rebase her belief that the wall is red at t2, and the doxastic disposition responsible for the rebasing was not a cognitive ability, she would fail to know that the wall is red at t2, even though she would still believe that the wall is red. But here it’s important to recall that whether Yen rebases her belief at t2 is a contingent matter. And since it’s a contingent matter, Yen doesn’t necessarily lose her knowledge after having acquired the putative defeater. It could also be the case that Yen’s cognitive character changes between t1 and t2 in such a way that the doxastic disposition that generated the belief that the wall is red no longer counts as a cognitive ability at t2.Footnote 27 In this variant of the case Yen could have known at t1 that the wall is red, but doesn’t know it at t2, since the doxastic disposition in charge of retaining the belief doesn’t qualify as a cognitive ability at t2. But again, it’s a contingent matter whether Yen’s cognitive character changes between t1 and t2, and hence the fact that knowledge is lost in this variant of the case doesn’t suffice to show that Yen’s of knowledge is defeated.

Recall that knowledge defeat occurs just in case a subject knows that p, gains a putative defeater for her belief that p, and thereby loses her knowledge that p without necessarily losing her belief that p. The defeatists claim that acquiring the putative defeater suffices on its own to defeat one’s knowledge. But knowledge defeat doesn’t occur in any of the five variants of Red light that we just considered. In the first version Yen never knew, in the second one she never gained a defeater, and in the third one she lost knowledge only because she lost the relevant belief. In the last two variants Yen does lose her knowledge without losing the corresponding belief. But this is only because she either (1) starts believing that the wall is red via a method of belief-formation that isn’t a cognitive ability, or, (2) her cognitive character changes in such a way that the way in which she formed her belief originally no longer counts as a cognitive ability. Yen doesn’t lose her knowledge in any of these variants solely in virtue of having acquired a putative defeater for her belief.

So knowledge defeat, strictly speaking, is an illusory phenomenon. There are no cases where acquiring a putative defeater for a belief that qualifies as knowledge suffices on its own to defeat the belief’s epistemic standing. But while knowledge defeat turns out to be an illusory phenomenon on the sketched account, it’s nevertheless true that there are no cases where a subject knows that p after having acquired a putative defeater for her belief that p. Thus virtue reliabilists are able to explain intuitions of knowledge defeat, without granting that knowledge defeat is a genuine phenomenon. Virtue reliabilism provides an error-theory of our defeat intuitions. It’s an error-theory in two senses. First, it claims that in some putative cases of knowledge defeat, knowledge was never had to begin with. Second, the potential loss of knowledge isn’t explained in terms of the putative defeater’s normative force, but rather via the way in which the subject reacted to her epistemic situation.Footnote 28 Finally, it’s worth noting that this error-theory can explain why suspending judgment is nevertheless epistemically speaking good, even though putative defeaters lack normative force. Suspending judgment is epistemically optimal, because only in those cases where the subject suspends her judgment is it possible that both her original, and her defeater belief, were justified (variant 3 above).Footnote 29

Here’s an objection I’ve heard against the theory proposed (voiced by Maria Lasonen-Aarnio, among others). Intuitively Yen knows in Red light that the wall is red at t1 even if she would dogmatically cling onto her belief if she later gained a justified belief that is a putative defeater for her original belief (variant 1 above). Yen’s dogmatism is a vice of her epistemic character that doesn’t stain her belief, the objection goes. I grant the objector that intuitively Yen knows at t1 that the wall is red. While it might be unintuitive that Yen’s dogmatism would preclude her from knowing that the wall is red, virtue reliabilists are committed to this claim. They hold that knowledge and justification can only arise from the exercise of cognitive abilities that are integrated to one’s cognitive character.Footnote 30 Virtue reliabilists can explain the intuition that Yen knows that the wall is red at t1. In all but variant 1 Yen does know that the wall is red at t1. It’s easy to mix up the variants since information regarding Yen’s dogmatic character is revealed only later. Furthermore, variant 1 is, perhaps, the most unnatural way of fleshing out the case. Most people would withdraw their belief if they were presented with a putative defeater. It’s plausible that we implicitly assume that Yen is non-dogmatic when originally evaluating whether Yen knows at t1. First impressions are hard to shake, especially when it comes to intuitions. That said, those who think that the objection is successfully, are invited to see this paper as offering an argument against virtue reliabilism. My aim was to examine what virtue reliabilists ought to say about defeat given some of their core commitments.

5 Other Virtue Theoretic Proposals

I will briefly consider some alternative solutions to the problem of knowledge defeat, put forth by virtue reliabilists. In order to deal with defeaters Greco (2010) adds a subjective justification condition to his analysis of knowledge. According to Greco subject S’s belief that p is subjectively justified “if and only if S’s believing that p is properly motivated; if and only if S’s believing that p results from intellectual dispositions that S manifests when S is motivated to believe the truth” (2010, p. 167). Greco’s argument as to why knowledge entails subjective justification is motivated by his take on Aristoteles’s virtue ethics. According to him virtuous action requires not only that the action arises from a virtuous character trait, but also that the action is properly motivated by one’s virtuous character (Greco, 2010, p. 43).

I won’t take issue with the difficult question under what conditions a subject is properly motivated to believe the truth, nor with Greco’s motivation to add a subjective justification component to his analysis of knowledge. For the sake of the argument, I’ll also grant that in putative cases of knowledge defeat Greco’s subjective justification condition isn’t satisfied and that knowledge is hence lost in such cases. I only wish to note that the kind of virtue reliabilism that Greco endorses already has the necessary tools to explain our intuitions of knowledge defeat. Adding a subjective justification condition to the analysis isn’t necessary and achieves nothing on this score. To me, adding this condition seems like an extra cost.

Pritchard (2018) has argued that his anti-luck virtue epistemology can account for the phenomenon of knowledge defeat. He claims that a subject who comes to know that [that’s a barn] in an area with no barn facades around, loses her knowledge if she sees a sign that says that she is in the barn façade-county. He writes that “the safety of her cognitive success is now in despite of her manifestation of relevant cognitive agency, rather than being to any significant degree because of it” (2018, p. 3075). Assuming that her belief that [that’s a barn] is a product of her cognitive abilities, I fail to see why the subject’s safe cognitive success wouldn’t be to a significant degree because of the exercise of her cognitive abilities. After all, the fact that the subject trusts her perception seems to explain precisely why she continues to have a safe belief. Pritchard needs to tell us more about why the subject’s safe cognitive success isn’t attributable to her cognitive agency in cases like this, if his explanation of knowledge defeat is to succeed. Moreover, if I am correct, Pritchard already has the necessary tools to accommodate our intuitions of knowledge defeat.

As far as I know, Sosa has not addressed the problem of knowledge defeat in print. However, given his distinction between animal and reflective knowledge, he could perhaps adopt the following view.Footnote 31 In putative cases of knowledge defeat one’s original belief retains its aptness, and hence it amounts to animal knowledge. However, once the defeater is introduced, the subject can no longer aptly take her belief to be apt, which is what reflective knowledge would require (Sosa, 2011, p. ch. 1). Reflective knowledge requires that one competently assesses the risk of forming a false belief to be low enough, and arguably, one cannot have competently assessed the risk to be low enough if one has a defeater for one’s belief. Therefore, defeaters would destroy reflective knowledge, but leave animal knowledge intact. This error-theoretic account of knowledge defeat rests on Sosa’s distinction between animal and reflective knowledge. Since the error-theory that I gave is derivable from the core tenets of virtue reliabilism, it’s simpler than the possible account that Sosa’s more complicated framework could yield. Moreover, if I am correct, Sosa has the resources to accommodate our intuitions of knowledge defeat without resorting to his distinction between animal and reflective knowledge.

To wrap up, the error-theory that I have presented is preferable to extant virtue reliabilist accounts of defeat since it is simpler than those accounts and stems from the core ideas of virtue reliabilism. Virtue reliabilists need not add bells and whistles to explain defeatist intuitions.

6 Conclusions

I argued that virtue reliabilism is able to explain our defeat intuitions via a new kind of error-theory that falls directly out of the core tenets of virtue reliabilism. According to the error-theory, in paradigmatic cases of knowledge defeat where the subject holds onto her belief, the subject never knew to begin with. In cases where the subject suspends her judgment upon receiving the defeater she might have originally known, but doesn’t anymore, since she lacks the relevant belief. In neither case is knowledge lost solely in virtue of the fact that the subject acquired a defeater, and hence knowledge defeat is an illusory phenomenon. Nevertheless, the defeatists are right in claiming that there are no cases where a subject retains her knowledge of p after having acquired a defeater for p.